• Re: Functions computed by Turing Machines MUST apply finite string tran

    From Richard Heathfield@21:1/5 to olcott on Fri May 2 05:03:26 2025
    On 02/05/2025 04:57, olcott wrote:
    On 5/1/2025 9:40 PM, dbush wrote:
    On 5/1/2025 10:34 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/1/2025 8:58 PM, André G. Isaak wrote:
    On 2025-05-01 19:09, olcott wrote:
    On 5/1/2025 7:32 PM, André G. Isaak wrote:
    On 2025-05-01 14:15, olcott wrote:
    On 5/1/2025 10:14 AM, André G. Isaak wrote:
    On 2025-04-30 21:50, olcott wrote:
    On 4/30/2025 7:17 PM, André G. Isaak wrote:

    You are still hopelessly confused about your terminology.

    Computable functions are a subset of mathematical
    functions, and mathematical functions are *not* the
    same thing as C functions. Functions do not apply
    "transformations". They are simply mappings, and a
    functions which maps every pair of natural numbers to 5
    is a perfectly legitimate, albeit not very interesting,
    function.

    What makes this function a *computable function* is
    that fact that it is possible to construct a C function
    (or a Turing Machine, or some other type of algorithm)
    such as int foo(int x, int y) {return 5;} which
    computes that particular function; but the C function
    and the computable function it computes are entirely
    separate entities.

    computes the sum of two integers
    by transforming the inputs into an output.
    int sum(int x, int y) { return x + y; }

    Computes no function because it ignores its inputs.
    int sum(int x, int y) { return 5; }

    All you're demonstrating here is that you have no clue
    what a function is, nor, apparently, do you have any
    desire to learn.

    André


    What I am explaining is that a halt decider
    must compute the mapping FROM THE INPUTS ONLY
    by applying a specific set of finite string
    transformations to the inputs.

    No. Halt deciders weren't even mentioned above. I was
    addressing your absurd claim that int foo(int x, int y) {
    return 5; } does not compute a function. This clearly
    indicates that you do not grasp the concept of "function".


    This is a brand new elaboration of computer
    science that I just came up with.

    IOW something you've pulled out of your ass.

    It is common knowledge THAT inputs must correspond
    to OUTPUTS. What is totally unknown and brand new
    created by me is HOW inputs are made to correspond
    to OUTPUTS.

    We were discussing functions. Functions don't have inputs or
    outputs; they have domains and codomains. ALGORITHMS have
    inputs and outputs, and you keep conflating the two.

    Specific finite string transformation rules are
    applied to inputs to derive outputs.

    Please point to a definition of 'function' which mentions
    "finite string transformation rules". This may be a useful
    way of viewing some (but certainly not all) algorithms, but
    it has nothing to do with functions. Functions are simply a
    mapping from one set (the domain) to another set (the
    codomain) such that every element of the domain maps to one
    and only one element of the codomain.

    What everyone else has been doing is simply GUESSING
    that they correspond or relying on some authority
    that say they must correspond. (Appeal to authority error).

    This is another baseless assertion that you've simply pulled
    out of your ass. If you think otherwise, please provide a
    concrete example

    DD correctly emulated by HHH maps to NON-HALTING BEHAVIOR.
    It really does, all that you have to do is PAY ATTENTION.

    Whether DD emulated by HH maps to halting or non-halting
    behaviour is entirely dependent on which function is being
    computed.

    André


    We are computing the halt function

    i.e. this function:


    Given any algorithm (i.e. a fixed immutable sequence of
    instructions) X described as <X> with input Y:

    (<X>,Y) maps to 1 if and only if X(Y) halts when executed directly
    (<X>,Y) maps to 0 if and only if X(Y) does not halt when
    executed directly


    Which has been proven to be uncomputable, as shown by Linz and
    as you have *explicitly* agreed is correct.

    FOR THE INPUT NOT ANY DAMN THING ELSE
    FOR THE INPUT NOT ANY DAMN THING ELSE
    FOR THE INPUT NOT ANY DAMN THING ELSE
    FOR THE INPUT NOT ANY DAMN THING ELSE

    FINITE STRING TRANSFORMATIONS OF THE INPUT ELSE WRONG
    FINITE STRING TRANSFORMATIONS OF THE INPUT ELSE WRONG
    FINITE STRING TRANSFORMATIONS OF THE INPUT ELSE WRONG

    int DD()
    {
       int Halt_Status = HHH(DD);
       if (Halt_Status)
         HERE: goto HERE;
       return Halt_Status;
    }

    Replacing the code of HHH with an unconditional simulator and
    subsequently running HHH(DD) specifies recursive
    simulation such that DD cannot possibly reach its
    "return instruction" (final halt state). Thus HHH
    is correct to reject DD as non halting.

    So you changed the input.  Changing the input is not allowed.


    I never changed the input.

    DD calls HHH. If you indulge in "Replacing the code of HHH" you
    necessarily change the behaviour of DD. DD is an input. Ergo, you
    changed the input.

    <snip>

    --
    Richard Heathfield
    Email: rjh at cpax dot org dot uk
    "Usenet is a strange place" - dmr 29 July 1999
    Sig line 4 vacant - apply within

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Heathfield@21:1/5 to dbush on Fri May 2 06:06:11 2025
    On 02/05/2025 05:08, dbush wrote:
    On 5/1/2025 11:57 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/1/2025 9:40 PM, dbush wrote:

    <snip>

    So you changed the input.  Changing the input is not allowed.


    I never changed the input.

    Yes you did.  You hypothesize changing the code of HHH, and HHH
    is part of the input. So you changed the input.


    Agreed.

    Changing the input is not allowed.

    Wweellll...

    I have a very minor objection to that view, an objection that
    I've wrapped up into a thought experiment.

    Let us hypothesise the paradoxical existence of U, a universal
    decider. If we pass it an arbitrary P and an arbitrary D, it can
    defy Turing (we're just hypothesising, remember) and produce a
    correct result. Cool, right? The snag is that it's a black box.
    We can't see the code.

    We set it to work, and for years we use it to prove all manner of
    questions - PvNP, Collatz, Goldbach, Riemann, the lot - and it
    turns out always to be right. That's good, right?

    But then one fine day in 2038 we are finally allowed to see the
    source code for U, which is when we discover that the algorithm
    changes the input<<< in some small way. Does that invalidate
    the answers it has been providing for over a decade, thousands of
    answers that have /all/ been verified?

    I would argue that it doesn't. Provided U(P,D) correctly reports
    on the behaviour a P(D) call would produce, I would argue that
    that's all that matters, and the fact that U twiddles with the P
    and D tapes and turns them into P' and D' is irrelevant, as long
    as the result we get is that of P(D), not P'(D').

    Let me show this graphically using a much simpler example - addition:

    D: 1111111111+1111111
    P: add 'em up

    P(D)!

    D': 11111111111111111

    P has changed its input by changing the + to a 1 and erasing the
    last 1, and D' now holds the correct answer to the question
    originally posed on D.

    I would argue that this is /perfectly fine/, and that there is
    nothing in Turing's problem statement to forbid it. But of course
    we must be careful that, even if U does change its inputs to P'
    and D', it must still correctly answer the question P(D).

    Of course, Mr Olcott's change is rather different, because by
    changing his HHH he's actually changing the behaviour of his DD -
    i.e. specifying a new U - but I see no reason why he can't do
    that /provided/ he can show that he always gets the correct
    answer. He has so far failed to do this with the original HHH,
    and now he has doubled his workload by giving himself another HHH
    to defend.

    Whatever 'solution' he eventually settles on, it will be easy to
    construct a P and a D that it fails to decide correctly, because
    Turing. Whether his 'solution' can invalidate Linz's proof is
    another matter; it's a mere technical question of little interest
    but, if push came to shove, my money would definitely be on Linz.

    <snip>

    --
    Richard Heathfield
    Email: rjh at cpax dot org dot uk
    "Usenet is a strange place" - dmr 29 July 1999
    Sig line 4 vacant - apply within

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to olcott on Fri May 2 09:42:09 2025
    On 5/1/25 11:57 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/1/2025 9:40 PM, dbush wrote:
    On 5/1/2025 10:34 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/1/2025 8:58 PM, André G. Isaak wrote:
    On 2025-05-01 19:09, olcott wrote:
    On 5/1/2025 7:32 PM, André G. Isaak wrote:
    On 2025-05-01 14:15, olcott wrote:
    On 5/1/2025 10:14 AM, André G. Isaak wrote:
    On 2025-04-30 21:50, olcott wrote:
    On 4/30/2025 7:17 PM, André G. Isaak wrote:

    You are still hopelessly confused about your terminology.

    Computable functions are a subset of mathematical functions, >>>>>>>>>> and mathematical functions are *not* the same thing as C
    functions. Functions do not apply "transformations". They are >>>>>>>>>> simply mappings, and a functions which maps every pair of
    natural numbers to 5 is a perfectly legitimate, albeit not >>>>>>>>>> very interesting, function.

    What makes this function a *computable function* is that fact >>>>>>>>>> that it is possible to construct a C function (or a Turing >>>>>>>>>> Machine, or some other type of algorithm) such as int foo(int >>>>>>>>>> x, int y) {return 5;} which computes that particular function; >>>>>>>>>> but the C function and the computable function it computes are >>>>>>>>>> entirely separate entities.

    computes the sum of two integers
    by transforming the inputs into an output.
    int sum(int x, int y) { return x + y; }

    Computes no function because it ignores its inputs.
    int sum(int x, int y) { return 5; }

    All you're demonstrating here is that you have no clue what a
    function is, nor, apparently, do you have any desire to learn. >>>>>>>>
    André


    What I am explaining is that a halt decider
    must compute the mapping FROM THE INPUTS ONLY
    by applying a specific set of finite string
    transformations to the inputs.

    No. Halt deciders weren't even mentioned above. I was addressing
    your absurd claim that int foo(int x, int y) { return 5; } does
    not compute a function. This clearly indicates that you do not
    grasp the concept of "function".


    This is a brand new elaboration of computer
    science that I just came up with.

    IOW something you've pulled out of your ass.

    It is common knowledge THAT inputs must correspond
    to OUTPUTS. What is totally unknown and brand new
    created by me is HOW inputs are made to correspond
    to OUTPUTS.

    We were discussing functions. Functions don't have inputs or
    outputs; they have domains and codomains. ALGORITHMS have inputs and
    outputs, and you keep conflating the two.

    Specific finite string transformation rules are
    applied to inputs to derive outputs.

    Please point to a definition of 'function' which mentions "finite
    string transformation rules". This may be a useful way of viewing
    some (but certainly not all) algorithms, but it has nothing to do
    with functions. Functions are simply a mapping from one set (the
    domain) to another set (the codomain) such that every element of the
    domain maps to one and only one element of the codomain.

    What everyone else has been doing is simply GUESSING
    that they correspond or relying on some authority
    that say they must correspond. (Appeal to authority error).

    This is another baseless assertion that you've simply pulled out of
    your ass. If you think otherwise, please provide a concrete example

    DD correctly emulated by HHH maps to NON-HALTING BEHAVIOR.
    It really does, all that you have to do is PAY ATTENTION.

    Whether DD emulated by HH maps to halting or non-halting behaviour
    is entirely dependent on which function is being computed.

    André


    We are computing the halt function

    i.e. this function:


    Given any algorithm (i.e. a fixed immutable sequence of instructions)
    X described as <X> with input Y:

    (<X>,Y) maps to 1 if and only if X(Y) halts when executed directly
    (<X>,Y) maps to 0 if and only if X(Y) does not halt when executed
    directly


    Which has been proven to be uncomputable, as shown by Linz and as you
    have *explicitly* agreed is correct.

    FOR THE INPUT NOT ANY DAMN THING ELSE
    FOR THE INPUT NOT ANY DAMN THING ELSE
    FOR THE INPUT NOT ANY DAMN THING ELSE
    FOR THE INPUT NOT ANY DAMN THING ELSE

    FINITE STRING TRANSFORMATIONS OF THE INPUT ELSE WRONG
    FINITE STRING TRANSFORMATIONS OF THE INPUT ELSE WRONG
    FINITE STRING TRANSFORMATIONS OF THE INPUT ELSE WRONG

    int DD()
    {
       int Halt_Status = HHH(DD);
       if (Halt_Status)
         HERE: goto HERE;
       return Halt_Status;
    }

    Replacing the code of HHH with an unconditional simulator and
    subsequently running HHH(DD) specifies recursive
    simulation such that DD cannot possibly reach its
    "return instruction" (final halt state). Thus HHH
    is correct to reject DD as non halting.

    So you changed the input.  Changing the input is not allowed.


    I never changed the input.

    Either DD doesn't contain the code it references of HHH, and thus is NOT
    A PROGRAM, or it does contine the code it referencess of HHH, and thus
    changing that HHH is changing the input.

    Thus, you are just proving that you don't understand what you are
    talking about and your whole argument has been based on an erroneous setup.



    <MIT Professor Sipser agreed to ONLY these verbatim words 10/13/2022>
         If simulating halt decider H correctly simulates its input D
         until H correctly determines that its simulated D would never
         stop running unless aborted then

         H can abort its simulation of D and correctly report that D
         specifies a non-halting sequence of configurations.
    </MIT Professor Sipser agreed to ONLY these verbatim words 10/13/2022>



    And *yet again* you lie by implying that Sipser agrees with you when
    it's been proven *on multiple occasions* that he does not:


    Professor Sipser gave me permission to quote
    those words above Ben verified that too.

    Yes, and they show your stupidity in not understanding what it means to
    correct determine that the (correrct) simulation of D would not halt.


    Assuming the those words are true I AM PROVED CORRECT.
    Why would professor Sipser agree with words that are not true?

    No you are not, as your H only proves that the partial emulation by H
    doesn't reach that point, not the correct emulation.

    It also seems that your "D" doesn't meet the requirements, as your claim
    above make it clear that what you think is D isn't actually a program.


    On Monday, March 6, 2023 at 2:41:27 PM UTC-5, Ben Bacarisse wrote:
    I exchanged emails with him about this. He does not agree with
    anything
    substantive that PO has written. I won't quote him, as I don't have
    permission, but he was, let's say... forthright, in his reply to me.

    Your dishonesty knows no bounds.



    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mike Terry@21:1/5 to Richard Heathfield on Sat May 3 02:16:18 2025
    On 02/05/2025 06:06, Richard Heathfield wrote:
    On 02/05/2025 05:08, dbush wrote:
    On 5/1/2025 11:57 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/1/2025 9:40 PM, dbush wrote:

    <snip>

    So you changed the input.  Changing the input is not allowed.


    I never changed the input.

    Yes you did.  You hypothesize changing the code of HHH, and HHH is part of the input. So you
    changed the input.


    Agreed.

    Changing the input is not allowed.

    Wweellll...

    I have a very minor objection to that view, an objection that I've wrapped up into a thought
    experiment.

    Let us hypothesise the paradoxical existence of U, a universal decider. If we pass it an arbitrary P
    and an arbitrary D, it can defy Turing (we're just hypothesising, remember) and produce a correct
    result. Cool, right? The snag is that it's a black box. We can't see the code.

    We set it to work, and for years we use it to prove all manner of questions - PvNP, Collatz,
    Goldbach, Riemann, the lot - and it turns out always to be right. That's good, right?

    But then one fine day in 2038 we are finally allowed to see the source code for U, which is when we
    discover that the algorithm >>>changes the input<<< in some small way. Does that invalidate the
    answers it has been providing for over a decade, thousands of answers that have /all/ been verified?

    Nobody would suggest that TMs aren't allowed to write to their tape! Of course, that's part of how
    they work, and is not what posters mean by PO "changing the input".


    I would argue that it doesn't. Provided U(P,D) correctly reports on the behaviour a P(D) call would
    produce, I would argue that that's all that matters, and the fact that U twiddles with the P and D
    tapes and turns them into P' and D' is irrelevant, as long as the result we get is that of P(D), not
    P'(D').

    Right. What you're describing is business as usual for TMs.


    Let me show this graphically using a much simpler example - addition:

    D: 1111111111+1111111
    P: add 'em up

    P(D)!

    D': 11111111111111111

    P has changed its input by changing the + to a 1 and erasing the last 1, and D' now holds the
    correct answer to the question originally posed on D.

    I would argue that this is /perfectly fine/, and that there is nothing in Turing's problem statement
    to forbid it. But of course we must be careful that, even if U does change its inputs to P' and D',
    it must still correctly answer the question P(D).

    Nothing wrong with that.

    BTW all the stuff above about universal deciders turns out to be irrelevant to your argument! (It
    just seems a bit odd to choose a non-existant TM as an example when any other (existant) TM would do
    the job more clearly...)


    Of course, Mr Olcott's change is rather different, because by changing his HHH he's actually
    changing the behaviour of his DD - i.e. specifying a new U - but I see no reason why he can't do
    that /provided/ he can show that he always gets the correct answer. He has so far failed to do this
    with the original HHH, and now he has doubled his workload by giving himself another HHH to defend.

    Right - PO's H is free to rewrite the tape in whatever way it likes, provided in the end it gets the
    right answer.

    The "you're not allowed to change the input" charge means something quite different.

    TLDR: Your talking about TMs writing to their tape as part of their normal operation. Nothing
    wrong with that. PO is effectively talking about changing the meaning of D [the input to H] half
    way through the Sipser quote.

    ----------------------------------------------------------------------------- NTLFM:

    PO is trying to interpret Sipser's quote:

    --- Start Sipser quote
    If simulating halt decider H correctly simulates its input D
    until H correctly determines that its simulated D would never
    stop running unless aborted then

    H can abort its simulation of D and correctly report that D
    specifies a non-halting sequence of configurations.
    --- End Sipser quote

    The following interpretation is ok:

    If H is given input D, and while simulating D gathers enough
    information to deduce that UTM(D) would never halt, then
    H can abort its simulation and decide D never halts.

    I'd say it's obvious that this is what Sipser is saying, because it's natural, correct, and relevant
    to what was being discussed (valid strategy for a simulating halt decider). It is trivial to check
    that what my interpretation says is valid:

    if UTM(D) would never halt, then D never halts, so if H(D) returns
    never_halts then that is the correct answer for the input. QED :)

    The key point is that throughout the quote, D
  • From Richard Heathfield@21:1/5 to Mike Terry on Sat May 3 06:47:40 2025
    On 03/05/2025 02:16, Mike Terry wrote:
    For your point of view I could probably just have said "It's
    bleedin' obvious that the input D can't be changed to D' (or
    anything else) half way through interpreting Sipser's words".

    Yes, that would cover it.

    Also probably that would be enough for you to get that your
    interpretation of "changing the input" went down the wrong road...

    More than enough.

    In passing, when I nailed down "TL;DR" I felt mildly guilty for
    scoring so few tersinosity points, but in return I must accuse
    you of undue obscurity.

    TL;DR appears to have attracted a certain currency, so okay,
    but... NTLFM? Really? "Seek and ye shall find", so I sought but
    shall findethed not. Most of my best guesses started 'Now The'
    and ended rhyming with RTFM, but none of those guesses jumped out
    as being self-evidently right. Would you care to translate?

    I kind of disagree with your mild denigration of the Linz (and similar) proofs.

    I wish to clarify that denigration was most certainly not my
    intent. There is, however, no doubt in my mind that while Linz is
    undoubtedly a worthy and indeed admirable computer scientist, his
    proof stands on giant shoulders. All I meant to say was that,
    were Linz's proof to lose its balance and take a tumble, it would
    not be the fault of the shoulders.

    --
    Richard Heathfield
    Email: rjh at cpax dot org dot uk
    "Usenet is a strange place" - dmr 29 July 1999
    Sig line 4 vacant - apply within

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From joes@21:1/5 to All on Sat May 3 16:11:16 2025
    Am Sat, 03 May 2025 10:52:35 -0500 schrieb olcott:
    On 5/2/2025 8:16 PM, Mike Terry wrote:
    On 02/05/2025 06:06, Richard Heathfield wrote:
    On 02/05/2025 05:08, dbush wrote:
    On 5/1/2025 11:57 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/1/2025 9:40 PM, dbush wrote:

    So you changed the input.  Changing the input is not allowed.
    I never changed the input.
    Yes you did.  You hypothesize changing the code of HHH, and HHH is
    part of the input. So you changed the input.
    Agreed.
    Still true.



    Of course, Mr Olcott's change is rather different, because by changing
    his HHH he's actually changing the behaviour of his DD - i.e.
    specifying a new U - but I see no reason why he can't do that /
    provided/ he can show that he always gets the correct answer. He has
    so far failed to do this with the original HHH, and now he has doubled
    his workload by giving himself another HHH to defend.

    Right - PO's H is free to rewrite the tape in whatever way it likes,
    provided in the end it gets the right answer.
    The "you're not allowed to change the input" charge means something
    quite different.
    TLDR:  Your talking about TMs writing to their tape as part of their
    normal operation.  Nothing wrong with that.  PO is effectively talking
    about changing the meaning of D [the input to H] half way through the
    Sipser quote.

    ----------------------------------------------------------------------------- >> NTLFM:
    PO is trying to interpret Sipser's quote:
    --- Start Sipser quote
    --- End Sipser quote

    The following interpretation is ok:
        If H is given input D, and while simulating D gathers enough
        information to deduce that UTM(D) would never halt, then H can
        abort its simulation and decide D never halts.

    In other words if embedded_H was a UTM would cause Ĥ applied to ⟨Ĥ⟩ to never halt then embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩
    is correctly ruled to never halt.
    Exactly, IF, but H is not an UTM but a simulator *that aborts* and returns
    to DD, which called it. You are reporting on what DD would hypothetically
    do IF it, counter to the facts, it did NOT call the aborting simulator.
    That's a different program better called something else like DD', and it
    does not behave the same. You should report on the input, which DOES call
    an aborting simulator. Do you get this?

    --
    Am Sat, 20 Jul 2024 12:35:31 +0000 schrieb WM in sci.math:
    It is not guaranteed that n+1 exists for every n.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From joes@21:1/5 to All on Sat May 3 19:04:35 2025
    Am Sat, 03 May 2025 12:07:49 -0500 schrieb olcott:

    HHH determines whether or not DD would halt if HHH would have been a
    pure simulator.
    Nobody cares about a non-input. In fact HHH is not a pure simulator
    but aborts, and DD calls *that same* HHH.

    ChatGPT DOES understand hypothetical possibilities and does understand
    that HHH computes the termination status of its input on the basis of
    these hypothetical possibilities.
    Only that is not what is asked of a halt decider.

    --
    Am Sat, 20 Jul 2024 12:35:31 +0000 schrieb WM in sci.math:
    It is not guaranteed that n+1 exists for every n.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mike Terry@21:1/5 to Richard Heathfield on Sat May 3 19:50:40 2025
    On 03/05/2025 06:47, Richard Heathfield wrote:
    On 03/05/2025 02:16, Mike Terry wrote:
    For your point of view I could probably just have said "It's bleedin' obvious that the input D
    can't be changed to D' (or anything else) half way through interpreting Sipser's words".

    Yes, that would cover it.

    :)


    Also probably that would be enough for you to get that your interpretation of "changing the input"
    went down the wrong road...

    More than enough.

    In passing, when I nailed down "TL;DR" I felt mildly guilty for scoring so few tersinosity points,
    but in return I must accuse you of undue obscurity.

    TL;DR appears to have attracted a certain currency, so okay, but... NTLFM? Really? "Seek and ye
    shall find", so I sought but shall findethed not. Most of my best guesses started 'Now The' and
    ended rhyming with RTFM, but none of those guesses jumped out as being self-evidently right. Would
    you care to translate?

    I admit to making it up, but all these (usenet?) abbreviations have to start somewhere, so I thought
    I would start a much needed new one!

    TL;DR = too long, didn't read, introducing a short summary for someone who hasn't the
    inclination/time to read a long (probably overly) verbose explanation. At least that's how I've
    seen it used. But then, how to introduce the verbose explanation? I couldn't find anything for
    that, so I invented NTLFM; which means "Not Too Long For Me" ! I'm looking forward to being a
    footnote in history when it catches on...


    I kind of disagree with your mild denigration of the Linz (and similar) proofs.

    I wish to clarify that denigration was most certainly not my intent. There is, however, no doubt in
    my mind that while Linz is undoubtedly a worthy and indeed admirable computer scientist, his proof
    stands on giant shoulders. All I meant to say was that, were Linz's proof to lose its balance and
    take a tumble, it would not be the fault of the shoulders.

    Yeah, denigration was really the wrong word, as I know there was no bad intent anywhere. Perhaps
    "downplaying" would have been what I was looking for.

    Ben pointed out there was confusion in the Linz proof with the labelling of states, and when I
    looked closely at the proof I a few years ago I recall thinking Linz had munged the conversion of
    (general) TM tape inputs to "H inputs" (which in Linz are binary representations of those tapes)
    when duplicating D's input. Now I'm not sure about that, but can't motivate myself to get to the
    bottom of it, since either way, if it is a problem it's clear how it should be fixed, and the basis
    for the proof is not affected.

    The proof is both "very easy" conceptually [as witnessed by how many people join in here, quickly
    understanding how it works if they've not come across it before], and slightly fiddly due to the TM
    H needing to have a fixed tape alphabet which must be able to represent any TM as well as any tape
    input for that TM. So there are certainly opportunities to miss details especially with a book
    aimed at those with a minimal maths background. Really, the only aspect of the proof requiring
    careful thought is convincing yourself that the fiddliness has been handled ok, along with
    understanding the notation used...

    I don't see any scope for the proof actually being invalid, and PO certainly does not present any
    argument for it being invalid. He simply believes his H can give the right answer for his D, and
    that's the beginning and end of it all. When he developed his x96utm, it became possible to
    actually run his code, and it became /manifestly/ clear his H gets the wrong answer for D. But PO
    just doubles down and comes up with bizarre explanations for why he still thinks it is right when it
    is obviously wrong.


    Mike.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Heathfield@21:1/5 to Mike Terry on Sat May 3 20:45:56 2025
    On 03/05/2025 19:50, Mike Terry wrote:
    On 03/05/2025 06:47, Richard Heathfield wrote:


    <snip>

    In passing, when I nailed down "TL;DR" I felt mildly guilty for
    scoring so few tersinosity points, but in return I must accuse
    you of undue obscurity.

    TL;DR appears to have attracted a certain currency, so okay,
    but... NTLFM? Really? "Seek and ye shall find", so I sought but
    shall findethed not. Most of my best guesses started 'Now The'
    and ended rhyming with RTFM, but none of those guesses jumped
    out as being self-evidently right. Would you care to translate?

    I admit to making it up, but all these (usenet?) abbreviations
    have to start somewhere, so I thought I would start a much needed
    new one!

    TL;DR = too long, didn't read,

    Yes, that chimes with my research, but...

    introducing a short summary for
    someone who hasn't the inclination/time to read a long (probably
    overly) verbose explanation.  At least that's how I've seen it
    used.  But then, how to introduce the verbose explanation?  I
    couldn't find anything for that, so I invented NTLFM; which means
    "Not Too Long For Me" !

    Ach! Of course.

    I'm looking forward to being a footnote
    in history when it catches on...

    In a footnote to the footnote for NTLFM I would add TOAST --- Too
    Obscure And Startlingly Terse.

    I kind of disagree with your mild denigration of the Linz (and
    similar) proofs.

    I wish to clarify that denigration was most certainly not my
    intent. There is, however, no doubt in my mind that while Linz
    is undoubtedly a worthy and indeed admirable computer
    scientist, his proof stands on giant shoulders. All I meant to
    say was that, were Linz's proof to lose its balance and take a
    tumble, it would not be the fault of the shoulders.

    Yeah, denigration was really the wrong word, as I know there was
    no bad intent anywhere.  Perhaps "downplaying" would have been
    what I was looking for.

    <nod />

    Ben pointed out there was confusion in the Linz proof with the
    labelling of states, and when I looked closely at the proof I a
    few years ago I recall thinking Linz had munged the conversion of
    (general) TM tape inputs to "H inputs" (which in Linz are binary representations of those tapes) when duplicating D's input.  Now
    I'm not sure about that, but can't motivate myself to get to the
    bottom of it, since either way, if it is a problem it's clear how
    it should be fixed, and the basis for the proof is not affected.

    The proof is both "very easy" conceptually [as witnessed by how
    many people join in here, quickly understanding how it works if
    they've not come across it before], and slightly fiddly due to
    the TM H needing to have a fixed tape alphabet which must be able
    to represent any TM as well as any tape input for that TM.  So
    there are certainly opportunities to miss details especially with
    a book aimed at those with a minimal maths background.  Really,
    the only aspect of the proof requiring careful thought is
    convincing yourself that the fiddliness has been handled ok,
    along with understanding the notation used...

    I don't see any scope for the proof actually being invalid, and
    PO certainly does not present any argument for it being invalid.
    He simply believes his H can give the right answer for his D, and
    that's the beginning and end of it all.  When he developed his
    x96utm, it became possible to actually run his code, and it
    became /manifestly/ clear his H gets the wrong answer for D.  But
    PO just doubles down and comes up with bizarre explanations for
    why he still thinks it is right when it is obviously wrong.

    As I re-read Linz /again/, two points stick out:

    "We cannot find the answer by simulating the action of M on w,
    say by performing it on a universal Turing machine, because there
    is no limit on the length of the computation. If M enters an
    infinite loop, then no matter how long we wait, we can never be
    sure that M is in fact in a loop. It may simply be a case of a
    very long computation. What we need is an algorithm that can
    determine the correct answer for any M and w by performing some
    analysis on the machine's description and the input. But as we
    now show, no such algorithm exists."

    "It is important to keep in mind what Theorem 12.1 says. It does
    not preclude solving the halting problem for specific cases;
    often we can tell by an analysis of M and w whether or not the
    Turing machine will halt. What the theorem says is that this
    cannot always be done; there is no algorithm that can make a
    correct decision for all WM and w."


    Both of these statements are self-evidently true, and both would
    appear to knock Mr O's HHH completely out of the water.

    I am conscious that you have already explained to me (twice!)
    that Mr O's approach is aimed not at overturning the overarching
    indecidability proof but a mere detail of Linz's proof.
    Unfortunately, your explanations have not managed to establish a
    firm root in what passes for my brain. This may be because I'm
    too dense to grok them, or possibly it's because your
    explanations are TOAST (see above).

    You have said, I think, that Olcott doesn't need a universal
    decider in order to prove his point. But a less ambitious decider
    doesn't contradict Linz's proof, surely? So once more for luck,
    what exactly would PO be establishing with his non-universal and
    impatient simulator if he could only get it to work?

    --
    Richard Heathfield
    Email: rjh at cpax dot org dot uk
    "Usenet is a strange place" - dmr 29 July 1999
    Sig line 4 vacant - apply within

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mike Terry@21:1/5 to olcott on Sat May 3 22:05:32 2025
    On 03/05/2025 16:52, olcott wrote:
    On 5/2/2025 8:16 PM, Mike Terry wrote:
    On 02/05/2025 06:06, Richard Heathfield wrote:
    On 02/05/2025 05:08, dbush wrote:
    On 5/1/2025 11:57 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/1/2025 9:40 PM, dbush wrote:

    <snip>

    So you changed the input.  Changing the input is not allowed.


    I never changed the input.

    Yes you did.  You hypothesize changing the code of HHH, and HHH is part of the input. So you
    changed the input.


    Agreed.

    Changing the input is not allowed.

    Wweellll...

    I have a very minor objection to that view, an objection that I've wrapped up into a thought
    experiment.

    Let us hypothesise the paradoxical existence of U, a universal decider. If we pass it an
    arbitrary P and an arbitrary D, it can defy Turing (we're just hypothesising, remember) and
    produce a correct result. Cool, right? The snag is that it's a black box. We can't see the code.

    We set it to work, and for years we use it to prove all manner of questions - PvNP, Collatz,
    Goldbach, Riemann, the lot - and it turns out always to be right. That's good, right?

    But then one fine day in 2038 we are finally allowed to see the source code for U, which is when
    we discover that the algorithm >>>changes the input<<< in some small way. Does that invalidate
    the answers it has been providing for over a decade, thousands of answers that have / all/ been
    verified?

    Nobody would suggest that TMs aren't allowed to write to their tape!  Of course, that's part of
    how they work, and is not what posters mean by PO "changing the input".


    I would argue that it doesn't. Provided U(P,D) correctly reports on the behaviour a P(D) call
    would produce, I would argue that that's all that matters, and the fact that U twiddles with the
    P and D tapes and turns them into P' and D' is irrelevant, as long as the result we get is that
    of P(D), not P'(D').

    Right.  What you're describing is business as usual for TMs.


    Let me show this graphically using a much simpler example - addition:

    D: 1111111111+1111111
    P: add 'em up

    P(D)!

    D': 11111111111111111

    P has changed its input by changing the + to a 1 and erasing the last 1, and D' now holds the
    correct answer to the question originally posed on D.

    I would argue that this is /perfectly fine/, and that there is nothing in Turing's problem
    statement to forbid it. But of course we must be careful that, even if U does change its inputs
    to P' and D', it must still correctly answer the question P(D).

    Nothing wrong with that.

    BTW all the stuff above about universal deciders turns out to be irrelevant to your argument!  (It
    just seems a bit odd to choose a non- existant TM as an example when any other (existant) TM would
    do the job more clearly...)


    Of course, Mr Olcott's change is rather different, because by changing his HHH he's actually
    changing the behaviour of his DD - i.e. specifying a new U - but I see no reason why he can't do
    that / provided/ he can show that he always gets the correct answer. He has so far failed to do
    this with the original HHH, and now he has doubled his workload by giving himself another HHH to
    defend.

    Right - PO's H is free to rewrite the tape in whatever way it likes, provided in the end it gets
    the right answer.

    The "you're not allowed to change the input" charge means something quite different.

    TLDR:  Your talking about TMs writing to their tape as part of their normal operation.  Nothing
    wrong with that.  PO is effectively talking about changing the meaning of D [the input to H] half
    way through the Sipser quote.

    -----------------------------------------------------------------------------
    NTLFM:

    PO is trying to interpret Sipser's quote:

    --- Start Sipser quote
          If simulating halt decider H correctly simulates its input D
          until H correctly determines that its simulated D would never
          stop running unless aborted then

          H can abort its simulation of D and correctly report that D
          specifies a non-halting sequence of configurations.
    --- End Sipser quote

    The following interpretation is ok:

         If H is given input D, and while simulating D gathers enough
         information to deduce that UTM(D) would never halt, then
         H can abort its simulation and decide D never halts.


    When Ĥ is applied to ⟨Ĥ⟩
    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qy ∞
    ..if H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* H.qy

    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qn
    ..if H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* H.qn

    Both the above cannot be correct as you wrote them! (You don't understand the Linz notation, and
    "no" you haven't "enhanced it" or whatever you think you've done)


    (a) Ĥ copies its input ⟨Ĥ⟩
    (b) Ĥ invokes embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩
    (c) embedded_H simulates ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩
    (d) simulated ⟨Ĥ⟩ copies its input ⟨Ĥ⟩
    (e) simulated ⟨Ĥ⟩ invokes simulated embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩
    (f) simulated embedded_H simulates ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩
    (g) goto (d) with one more level of simulation

    But this does not continue indefinitely. You forget that when you say

    (c) embedded_H simulates ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩

    embedded_H does not just stop running until the simulation returns. embedded_H is still running
    throughout the simulation and is monitoring progress to decide whether of not to abort. At some
    point it /does/ decide to abort, and steps (d)(e)(f)(g) become moot. Truth is they were always just
    an explanation for what is happening in (c), and (c) is the actual TM code running.

    So to continue, (c) aborts at some point, and

    embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qn // one of the options you listed above

    Ĥ.qn is a halt state for Ĥ, IN OTHER WORDS When Ĥ is applied to ⟨Ĥ⟩, Ĥ HALTS.⟩


    In other words if embedded_H was a UTM would cause
    Ĥ applied to ⟨Ĥ⟩ to never halt then embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩
    is correctly ruled to never halt.

    No, that's all wrong. You are trying to apply the Sipser quote to justify embedded_H deciding
    never_halt ? That's not what the quote says. From above:

    The following interpretation is ok:

    If H is given input D, and while simulating D gathers enough
    information to deduce that UTM(D) would never halt, then
    H can abort its simulation and decide D never halts.

    And we have

    (c) embedded_H simulates ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩

    Sipser's H is your embedded_H, and his D is your ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩, so the correct interpretation is:

    if embedded_H is given input ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩, and while simulating Ĥ gathers enough
    information to deduce that UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩) would never halt, then
    embedded_H can abort its simulation and decide Ĥ [run with input Ĥ]
    never halts.

    As explained above, UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩) simulates Ĥ run with input Ĥ (having the same halting behaviour)
    and Ĥ run with input Ĥ HALTS. So embedded_H does not "gather enough information to deduce that
    UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩) would never halt". THAT IS JUST A FANTASY THAT YOU HAVE.

    UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩) DOES halt, so embedded_H can't possibly gather information that genuinely implies it
    DOESN'T halt. The explanation is obvious: embedded_H gathers information that *YOU* believe
    implies that UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩) would never halt, but *YOU ARE SIMPLY WRONG*.

    I know you'll not understand what I've just said, because it is all too abstract and you don't
    understand the concepts involved, and consequently you probably don't agree with my Sipser
    interpretation, and even if you did I doubt you would be able to work out its consequences. So I
    don't expect to be posting any further.


    Mike.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to olcott on Sat May 3 17:40:04 2025
    On 5/3/25 11:52 AM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/2/2025 8:16 PM, Mike Terry wrote:
    On 02/05/2025 06:06, Richard Heathfield wrote:
    On 02/05/2025 05:08, dbush wrote:
    On 5/1/2025 11:57 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/1/2025 9:40 PM, dbush wrote:

    <snip>

    So you changed the input.  Changing the input is not allowed.


    I never changed the input.

    Yes you did.  You hypothesize changing the code of HHH, and HHH is
    part of the input. So you changed the input.


    Agreed.

    Changing the input is not allowed.

    Wweellll...

    I have a very minor objection to that view, an objection that I've
    wrapped up into a thought experiment.

    Let us hypothesise the paradoxical existence of U, a universal
    decider. If we pass it an arbitrary P and an arbitrary D, it can defy
    Turing (we're just hypothesising, remember) and produce a correct
    result. Cool, right? The snag is that it's a black box. We can't see
    the code.

    We set it to work, and for years we use it to prove all manner of
    questions - PvNP, Collatz, Goldbach, Riemann, the lot - and it turns
    out always to be right. That's good, right?

    But then one fine day in 2038 we are finally allowed to see the
    source code for U, which is when we discover that the algorithm
    changes the input<<< in some small way. Does that invalidate the
    answers it has been providing for over a decade, thousands of answers
    that have / all/ been verified?

    Nobody would suggest that TMs aren't allowed to write to their tape!
    Of course, that's part of how they work, and is not what posters mean
    by PO "changing the input".


    I would argue that it doesn't. Provided U(P,D) correctly reports on
    the behaviour a P(D) call would produce, I would argue that that's
    all that matters, and the fact that U twiddles with the P and D tapes
    and turns them into P' and D' is irrelevant, as long as the result we
    get is that of P(D), not P'(D').

    Right.  What you're describing is business as usual for TMs.


    Let me show this graphically using a much simpler example - addition:

    D: 1111111111+1111111
    P: add 'em up

    P(D)!

    D': 11111111111111111

    P has changed its input by changing the + to a 1 and erasing the last
    1, and D' now holds the correct answer to the question originally
    posed on D.

    I would argue that this is /perfectly fine/, and that there is
    nothing in Turing's problem statement to forbid it. But of course we
    must be careful that, even if U does change its inputs to P' and D',
    it must still correctly answer the question P(D).

    Nothing wrong with that.

    BTW all the stuff above about universal deciders turns out to be
    irrelevant to your argument!  (It just seems a bit odd to choose a
    non- existant TM as an example when any other (existant) TM would do
    the job more clearly...)


    Of course, Mr Olcott's change is rather different, because by
    changing his HHH he's actually changing the behaviour of his DD -
    i.e. specifying a new U - but I see no reason why he can't do that /
    provided/ he can show that he always gets the correct answer. He has
    so far failed to do this with the original HHH, and now he has
    doubled his workload by giving himself another HHH to defend.

    Right - PO's H is free to rewrite the tape in whatever way it likes,
    provided in the end it gets the right answer.

    The "you're not allowed to change the input" charge means something
    quite different.

    TLDR:  Your talking about TMs writing to their tape as part of their
    normal operation.  Nothing wrong with that.  PO is effectively talking
    about changing the meaning of D [the input to H] half way through the
    Sipser quote.

    -----------------------------------------------------------------------------
    NTLFM:

    PO is trying to interpret Sipser's quote:

    --- Start Sipser quote
          If simulating halt decider H correctly simulates its input D
          until H correctly determines that its simulated D would never
          stop running unless aborted then

          H can abort its simulation of D and correctly report that D
          specifies a non-halting sequence of configurations.
    --- End Sipser quote

    The following interpretation is ok:

         If H is given input D, and while simulating D gathers enough
         information to deduce that UTM(D) would never halt, then
         H can abort its simulation and decide D never halts.


    When Ĥ is applied to ⟨Ĥ⟩
    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qy ∞
    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qn

    (a) Ĥ copies its input ⟨Ĥ⟩
    (b) Ĥ invokes embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩
    (c) embedded_H simulates ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩
    (d) simulated ⟨Ĥ⟩ copies its input ⟨Ĥ⟩
    (e) simulated ⟨Ĥ⟩ invokes simulated embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩
    (f) simulated embedded_H simulates ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩
    (g) goto (d) with one more level of simulation

    And, since H does abort is simulation, so does embedded_H (or youy are
    just admtting to being a liar) and thus at some point the embedded_H
    that was started to be emulted in (c) *WILL* also abort its emulation
    and will transition to Ĥ.qn and Ĥ will halt.



    In other words if embedded_H was a UTM would cause
    Ĥ applied to ⟨Ĥ⟩ to never halt then embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩
    is correctly ruled to never halt.


    But embedded_H *ISN'T* a UTM, so your "logic" is just based on LYING.

    This has been explained to you many times, and your inability to refute
    this, or learn it just shows you are nothing but a stupid pathological
    lyinig idiot.

    Your place in history as such has been secured.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to olcott on Sat May 3 17:47:48 2025
    On 5/3/25 1:07 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/2/2025 8:16 PM, Mike Terry wrote:
    On 02/05/2025 06:06, Richard Heathfield wrote:
    On 02/05/2025 05:08, dbush wrote:
    On 5/1/2025 11:57 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/1/2025 9:40 PM, dbush wrote:

    <snip>

    So you changed the input.  Changing the input is not allowed.


    I never changed the input.

    Yes you did.  You hypothesize changing the code of HHH, and HHH is
    part of the input. So you changed the input.


    Agreed.

    Changing the input is not allowed.

    Wweellll...

    I have a very minor objection to that view, an objection that I've
    wrapped up into a thought experiment.

    Let us hypothesise the paradoxical existence of U, a universal
    decider. If we pass it an arbitrary P and an arbitrary D, it can defy
    Turing (we're just hypothesising, remember) and produce a correct
    result. Cool, right? The snag is that it's a black box. We can't see
    the code.

    We set it to work, and for years we use it to prove all manner of
    questions - PvNP, Collatz, Goldbach, Riemann, the lot - and it turns
    out always to be right. That's good, right?

    But then one fine day in 2038 we are finally allowed to see the
    source code for U, which is when we discover that the algorithm
    changes the input<<< in some small way. Does that invalidate the
    answers it has been providing for over a decade, thousands of answers
    that have / all/ been verified?

    Nobody would suggest that TMs aren't allowed to write to their tape!
    Of course, that's part of how they work, and is not what posters mean
    by PO "changing the input".


    I would argue that it doesn't. Provided U(P,D) correctly reports on
    the behaviour a P(D) call would produce, I would argue that that's
    all that matters, and the fact that U twiddles with the P and D tapes
    and turns them into P' and D' is irrelevant, as long as the result we
    get is that of P(D), not P'(D').

    Right.  What you're describing is business as usual for TMs.


    Let me show this graphically using a much simpler example - addition:

    D: 1111111111+1111111
    P: add 'em up

    P(D)!

    D': 11111111111111111

    P has changed its input by changing the + to a 1 and erasing the last
    1, and D' now holds the correct answer to the question originally
    posed on D.

    I would argue that this is /perfectly fine/, and that there is
    nothing in Turing's problem statement to forbid it. But of course we
    must be careful that, even if U does change its inputs to P' and D',
    it must still correctly answer the question P(D).

    Nothing wrong with that.

    BTW all the stuff above about universal deciders turns out to be
    irrelevant to your argument!  (It just seems a bit odd to choose a
    non- existant TM as an example when any other (existant) TM would do
    the job more clearly...)


    Of course, Mr Olcott's change is rather different, because by
    changing his HHH he's actually changing the behaviour of his DD -
    i.e. specifying a new U - but I see no reason why he can't do that /
    provided/ he can show that he always gets the correct answer. He has
    so far failed to do this with the original HHH, and now he has
    doubled his workload by giving himself another HHH to defend.

    Right - PO's H is free to rewrite the tape in whatever way it likes,
    provided in the end it gets the right answer.

    The "you're not allowed to change the input" charge means something
    quite different.

    TLDR:  Your talking about TMs writing to their tape as part of their
    normal operation.  Nothing wrong with that.  PO is effectively talking
    about changing the meaning of D [the input to H] half way through the
    Sipser quote.

    -----------------------------------------------------------------------------
    NTLFM:

    PO is trying to interpret Sipser's quote:

    --- Start Sipser quote
          If simulating halt decider H correctly simulates its input D
          until H correctly determines that its simulated D would never
          stop running unless aborted then

          H can abort its simulation of D and correctly report that D
          specifies a non-halting sequence of configurations.
    --- End Sipser quote

    The following interpretation is ok:

         If H is given input D, and while simulating D gathers enough
         information to deduce that UTM(D) would never halt, then
         H can abort its simulation and decide D never halts.


    That is the same way that ChatGPT understands it.

    *ChatGPT Analyzes Simulating Termination Analyzer* https://www.researchgate.net/ publication/385090708_ChatGPT_Analyzes_Simulating_Termination_Analyzer

    For DD/HHH

    int DD()
    {
      int Halt_Status = HHH(DD);
      if (Halt_Status)
        HERE: goto HERE;
      return Halt_Status;
    }

    HHH determines whether or not DD would halt
    if HHH would have been a pure simulator.

    But HHH is NOT a pure simulator, so that doesn't matter, at that HHH
    never answers

    Remember the input DD depend on the code of the decider it is defined to
    call, so your input changes.

    It seems, you are just so stupid as to not understand what a program
    actually is.


    ChatGPT DOES understand hypothetical possibilities
    and does understand that HHH computes the termination
    status of its input on the basis of these hypothetical
    possibilities.


    No, it just shows that it is as stupid as you, and believes (or pretends
    to in order to make you happy) your lies.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to olcott on Sat May 3 17:45:24 2025
    On 5/3/25 11:58 AM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/3/2025 10:52 AM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/2/2025 8:16 PM, Mike Terry wrote:
    On 02/05/2025 06:06, Richard Heathfield wrote:
    On 02/05/2025 05:08, dbush wrote:
    On 5/1/2025 11:57 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/1/2025 9:40 PM, dbush wrote:

    <snip>

    So you changed the input.  Changing the input is not allowed.


    I never changed the input.

    Yes you did.  You hypothesize changing the code of HHH, and HHH is
    part of the input. So you changed the input.


    Agreed.

    Changing the input is not allowed.

    Wweellll...

    I have a very minor objection to that view, an objection that I've
    wrapped up into a thought experiment.

    Let us hypothesise the paradoxical existence of U, a universal
    decider. If we pass it an arbitrary P and an arbitrary D, it can
    defy Turing (we're just hypothesising, remember) and produce a
    correct result. Cool, right? The snag is that it's a black box. We
    can't see the code.

    We set it to work, and for years we use it to prove all manner of
    questions - PvNP, Collatz, Goldbach, Riemann, the lot - and it turns
    out always to be right. That's good, right?

    But then one fine day in 2038 we are finally allowed to see the
    source code for U, which is when we discover that the algorithm
    changes the input<<< in some small way. Does that invalidate the
    answers it has been providing for over a decade, thousands of
    answers that have / all/ been verified?

    Nobody would suggest that TMs aren't allowed to write to their tape!
    Of course, that's part of how they work, and is not what posters mean
    by PO "changing the input".


    I would argue that it doesn't. Provided U(P,D) correctly reports on
    the behaviour a P(D) call would produce, I would argue that that's
    all that matters, and the fact that U twiddles with the P and D
    tapes and turns them into P' and D' is irrelevant, as long as the
    result we get is that of P(D), not P'(D').

    Right.  What you're describing is business as usual for TMs.


    Let me show this graphically using a much simpler example - addition:

    D: 1111111111+1111111
    P: add 'em up

    P(D)!

    D': 11111111111111111

    P has changed its input by changing the + to a 1 and erasing the
    last 1, and D' now holds the correct answer to the question
    originally posed on D.

    I would argue that this is /perfectly fine/, and that there is
    nothing in Turing's problem statement to forbid it. But of course we
    must be careful that, even if U does change its inputs to P' and D',
    it must still correctly answer the question P(D).

    Nothing wrong with that.

    BTW all the stuff above about universal deciders turns out to be
    irrelevant to your argument!  (It just seems a bit odd to choose a
    non- existant TM as an example when any other (existant) TM would do
    the job more clearly...)


    Of course, Mr Olcott's change is rather different, because by
    changing his HHH he's actually changing the behaviour of his DD -
    i.e. specifying a new U - but I see no reason why he can't do that /
    provided/ he can show that he always gets the correct answer. He has
    so far failed to do this with the original HHH, and now he has
    doubled his workload by giving himself another HHH to defend.

    Right - PO's H is free to rewrite the tape in whatever way it likes,
    provided in the end it gets the right answer.

    The "you're not allowed to change the input" charge means something
    quite different.

    TLDR:  Your talking about TMs writing to their tape as part of their
    normal operation.  Nothing wrong with that.  PO is effectively
    talking about changing the meaning of D [the input to H] half way
    through the Sipser quote.

    -----------------------------------------------------------------------------
    NTLFM:

    PO is trying to interpret Sipser's quote:

    --- Start Sipser quote
          If simulating halt decider H correctly simulates its input D
          until H correctly determines that its simulated D would never >>>       stop running unless aborted then

          H can abort its simulation of D and correctly report that D
          specifies a non-halting sequence of configurations.
    --- End Sipser quote

    The following interpretation is ok:

         If H is given input D, and while simulating D gathers enough
         information to deduce that UTM(D) would never halt, then
         H can abort its simulation and decide D never halts.


    When Ĥ is applied to ⟨Ĥ⟩
    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qy ∞
    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qn

    (a) Ĥ copies its input ⟨Ĥ⟩
    (b) Ĥ invokes embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩
    (c) embedded_H simulates ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩
    (d) simulated ⟨Ĥ⟩ copies its input ⟨Ĥ⟩
    (e) simulated ⟨Ĥ⟩ invokes simulated embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩
    (f) simulated embedded_H simulates ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩
    (g) goto (d) with one more level of simulation

    In other words if embedded_H was a UTM would cause
    Ĥ applied to ⟨Ĥ⟩ to never halt then embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩
    is correctly ruled to never halt.



    That is the same thing that ChatGPT agrees with and
    and describes in its own words.

    And yoi do know that ChatGPT has been proven to lie, and lawyers using
    it have been sacntioned.


    ChatGPT Analyzes Simulating Termination Analyzer https://www.researchgate.net/ publication/385090708_ChatGPT_Analyzes_Simulating_Termination_Analyzer

    If anyone says this is incorrect ChatGPT
    will argue against them every which way using
    its own words. Link at end of paper.

    ChatGPT actual like a profoundly brilliant genius
    unless you exceed its 4000 word limit.


    Since you began by lying to ChatGPT, all you have shown is that your
    logic is able to confuse it.

    That you think ARTIFICIAL intelegence is smart, shows that you just have natural stupidity.

    Remember, it has been PROVEN that AI's will tell you what they think you
    want to hear, and thus are not a good source of "truth"

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mike Terry@21:1/5 to Richard Heathfield on Sun May 4 01:20:59 2025
    On 03/05/2025 20:45, Richard Heathfield wrote:
    On 03/05/2025 19:50, Mike Terry wrote:
    On 03/05/2025 06:47, Richard Heathfield wrote:


    <snip>

    In passing, when I nailed down "TL;DR" I felt mildly guilty for scoring so few tersinosity
    points, but in return I must accuse you of undue obscurity.

    TL;DR appears to have attracted a certain currency, so okay, but... NTLFM? Really? "Seek and ye
    shall find", so I sought but shall findethed not. Most of my best guesses started 'Now The' and
    ended rhyming with RTFM, but none of those guesses jumped out as being self-evidently right.
    Would you care to translate?

    I admit to making it up, but all these (usenet?) abbreviations have to start somewhere, so I
    thought I would start a much needed new one!

    TL;DR = too long, didn't read,

    Yes, that chimes with my research, but...

    introducing a short summary for someone who hasn't the inclination/time to read a long (probably
    overly) verbose explanation.  At least that's how I've seen it used.  But then, how to introduce
    the verbose explanation?  I couldn't find anything for that, so I invented NTLFM; which means "Not
    Too Long For Me" !

    Ach! Of course.

    I'm looking forward to being a footnote in history when it catches on...

    In a footnote to the footnote for NTLFM I would add TOAST --- Too Obscure And Startlingly Terse.

    I kind of disagree with your mild denigration of the Linz (and similar) proofs.

    I wish to clarify that denigration was most certainly not my intent. There is, however, no doubt
    in my mind that while Linz is undoubtedly a worthy and indeed admirable computer scientist, his
    proof stands on giant shoulders. All I meant to say was that, were Linz's proof to lose its
    balance and take a tumble, it would not be the fault of the shoulders.

    Yeah, denigration was really the wrong word, as I know there was no bad intent anywhere.  Perhaps
    "downplaying" would have been what I was looking for.

    <nod />

    Ben pointed out there was confusion in the Linz proof with the labelling of states, and when I
    looked closely at the proof I a few years ago I recall thinking Linz had munged the conversion of
    (general) TM tape inputs to "H inputs" (which in Linz are binary representations of those tapes)
    when duplicating D's input.  Now I'm not sure about that, but can't motivate myself to get to the
    bottom of it, since either way, if it is a problem it's clear how it should be fixed, and the
    basis for the proof is not affected.

    The proof is both "very easy" conceptually [as witnessed by how many people join in here, quickly
    understanding how it works if they've not come across it before], and slightly fiddly due to the
    TM H needing to have a fixed tape alphabet which must be able to represent any TM as well as any
    tape input for that TM.  So there are certainly opportunities to miss details especially with a
    book aimed at those with a minimal maths background.  Really, the only aspect of the proof
    requiring careful thought is convincing yourself that the fiddliness has been handled ok, along
    with understanding the notation used...

    I don't see any scope for the proof actually being invalid, and PO certainly does not present any
    argument for it being invalid. He simply believes his H can give the right answer for his D, and
    that's the beginning and end of it all.  When he developed his x96utm, it became possible to
    actually run his code, and it became /manifestly/ clear his H gets the wrong answer for D.  But PO
    just doubles down and comes up with bizarre explanations for why he still thinks it is right when
    it is obviously wrong.

    As I re-read Linz /again/, two points stick out:

    "We cannot find the answer by simulating the action of M on w, say by performing it on a universal
    Turing machine, because there is no limit on the length of the computation. If M enters an infinite
    loop, then no matter how long we wait, we can never be sure that M is in fact in a loop. It may
    simply be a case of a very long computation. What we need is an algorithm that can determine the
    correct answer for any M and w by performing some
    analysis on the machine's description and the input. But as we
    now show, no such algorithm exists."

    "It is important to keep in mind what Theorem 12.1 says. It does not preclude solving the halting
    problem for specific cases; often we can tell by an analysis of M and w whether or not the Turing
    machine will halt. What the theorem says is that this cannot always be done; there is no algorithm
    that can make a correct decision for all WM and w."


    Both of these statements are self-evidently true, and both would appear to knock Mr O's HHH
    completely out of the water.

    I am conscious that you have already explained to me (twice!) that Mr O's approach is aimed not at
    overturning the overarching indecidability proof but a mere detail of Linz's proof. Unfortunately,
    your explanations have not managed to establish a firm root in what passes for my brain. This may be
    because I'm too dense to grok them, or possibly it's because your explanations are TOAST (see above).

    I generally think I post way too much, and tend to wander off topic with unnecessary background and
    so on, and probably I write too much from a "maths" perspective, because that's my background. Not
    sure if I can change any of that! :) Just ask if I use obscure notation or let me know if I'm going
    too fast/slow. Part of the problem is I don't know your background and what things you're super
    familiar with.


    You have said, I think, that Olcott doesn't need a universal decider in order to prove his point.
    But a less ambitious decider doesn't contradict Linz's proof, surely? So once more for luck, what
    exactly would PO be establishing with his non-universal and impatient simulator if he could only get
    it to work?

    Yes. PO is aiming to refute the /proof method/ that Linz (and similar) proofs use, i.e. to attack
    the /reasoning/ behind the proof. In effect, he is saying that his HHH/DD provide a counter-example
    to that reasoning. His HHH/DD are not full halt deciders - they're /partial/ halt deciders but that
    would be enough. I cover what a partial HD is below, and why it is enough for his argument [..if
    HHH/DD worked as originally claimed..]

    If he was successful with his HHH/DD programs, it would mean the Linz proof contained some logical
    error, and so the conclusion of the proof (the HP theorem) would not be warranted /by that proof/,
    We would have to cross that proof out of our Master Book Of Mathematical Theorems And Their Proofs!
    As there are other proofs of the theorem, the theorem itself could remain.

    It would be like the following scenario: there are many alternative proofs of Pythagorus' Theorem,
    but let's imagine that one of them - the "MikeT" proof - is the first one taught to all school
    children across the world, and it's been that way for the last 50 years. Suddenly PO finds a flaw
    in that proof! Sure, there are other proofs without that flaw so we still trust Pythagorus'
    Theorem, but we're not going to continue teaching children an incorrect proof of it, right. So
    finding such a flaw would force many changes on our education system and be highly interesting in
    its own right.

    This doesn't explain exactly how PO's HHH/DD would "refute" the Linz proof, so that's what the rest
    of the post tries to do.

    BTW, when I refer to "the Linz proof" it is purely because the Linz book is apparently the one that
    PO has access to, and when he started posting here he claimed to have refuted the "Linz" proof that
    appears in that book. As you suspect, the proof is nothing to do with Linz other than appearing in
    his book! It also appears I expect in some form in most computer science books covering computation
    theory, because it's so well known. Hmm, not sure who discovered it, but it would be one of the big
    guys like Turing, Church, Kleene,... all doing related work in the early days of the field.

    ----------------------

    So to say what PO's code would refute, I need to explain exactly how the Linz proof works. Sorry if
    you already perfectly clear on that!

    Say I give you a halt decider H. H is a TM, and following the mechanical instructions in Linz, you
    would be able to create from H a new TM H^. Basically you start with the H I gave, and edit it:

    1) add some initial code that runs before my H gets control - that code duplicates whatever input is
    on the tape when it is invoked, so that if the initial tape contained "hello\0" the modified tape
    needs to end up "hello\0hello\0".

    2) modify the halt states that my H used to indicate halt/non-halting when deciding its input:
    - the state H uses to indicate its input halts is replaced with a tight loop
    - the state H uses to indicate its input fails to halt is replaced with halt state.
    Hmm, that state was a halt state in the H I gave you, so actually there's no change
    for that state.

    So, I gave you H, and you've modified it to produce a new TM H^. The essence of the Linz proof is
    that the logic of how H^ works /guarantees/ that when we ask my H whether your H^ halts when run
    against a tape containing the TM-description of H^, my H will give the wrong answer! So, my H never
    was a halt decider after all, because it gets a wrong answer for this particular input. Halt
    deciders must decide halting correctly for /every/ input i.e. every combination of P,I [P is the
    TM, I the input tape].

    [I'm not explaining the proof of /why/ H will get the answer wrong. That's important of course and
    is in Linz and other accounts of the proof, but it's not really relevant to understanding what PO is
    trying to achieve.]

    This next bit might be a missing key for you... Looking at the above, we started by me giving you
    a "halt decider" H. What if I only gave you a lesser achievement: a "partial halt decider" that
    correctly decides halting for certain (P,I) inputs, but fails to halt for all the rest? The answer
    is the same logic still applies, but the conclusion is slightly different:

    - I give you a /partial/ HD H
    - You follow the same instructions to create the new TM, H^
    - The same reasoning of the Linz proof shows that my H does not correctly decide halting
    for the case of TM H^ running against input <H^>
    a) If H decides HALTS, we can show H^(<H^>) never halts
    b) If H decides NEVER_HALTS, we can show H^(<H^>) halts
    c) If H fails to decide (i.e. it loops) then H^(<H^>) never halts
    This last possibility is new, because H is only a partial halt decider

    Now we can look at what PO claims to have: a *partial* halt decider H, which CORRECTLY decides its
    corresponding input (<H^>,<H^>). Specifically, he claims his H decides NEVER_HALTS, and that indeed
    H^(<H^>) never halts. This contradicts the Linz proof /reasoning/ which lead to (b) above.

    Since the Linz proof reasoning would have been shown to reach a false conclusion [in the case of
    PO's HHH/DD programs], the reasoning must be wrong somewhere, and if the reasoning is wrong it can't
    be used in the Linz proof. It is ok here that H is only a partial halt decider - in fact the above
    only requires that PO's H correctly decides the one H^(<H^>) case to get the contradiction.

    Er, that's it!

    Just as a reminder I'll repeat the final outcome of all this:

    - PO's H does decide NEVER_HALTS for TM H^ running with input <H^>.
    - PO's H^ running with input <H^> in fact halts, in line with Linz logic (b) above.

    A final observation - nothing in this post is anything to do with "simulation". That comes later
    looking at how PO's H supposedly works...

    Mike.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Fred. Zwarts@21:1/5 to All on Sun May 4 08:31:27 2025
    Op 03.mei.2025 om 17:52 schreef olcott:
    On 5/2/2025 8:16 PM, Mike Terry wrote:
    On 02/05/2025 06:06, Richard Heathfield wrote:
    On 02/05/2025 05:08, dbush wrote:
    On 5/1/2025 11:57 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/1/2025 9:40 PM, dbush wrote:

    <snip>

    So you changed the input.  Changing the input is not allowed.


    I never changed the input.

    Yes you did.  You hypothesize changing the code of HHH, and HHH is
    part of the input. So you changed the input.


    Agreed.

    Changing the input is not allowed.

    Wweellll...

    I have a very minor objection to that view, an objection that I've
    wrapped up into a thought experiment.

    Let us hypothesise the paradoxical existence of U, a universal
    decider. If we pass it an arbitrary P and an arbitrary D, it can defy
    Turing (we're just hypothesising, remember) and produce a correct
    result. Cool, right? The snag is that it's a black box. We can't see
    the code.

    We set it to work, and for years we use it to prove all manner of
    questions - PvNP, Collatz, Goldbach, Riemann, the lot - and it turns
    out always to be right. That's good, right?

    But then one fine day in 2038 we are finally allowed to see the
    source code for U, which is when we discover that the algorithm
    changes the input<<< in some small way. Does that invalidate the
    answers it has been providing for over a decade, thousands of answers
    that have / all/ been verified?

    Nobody would suggest that TMs aren't allowed to write to their tape!
    Of course, that's part of how they work, and is not what posters mean
    by PO "changing the input".


    I would argue that it doesn't. Provided U(P,D) correctly reports on
    the behaviour a P(D) call would produce, I would argue that that's
    all that matters, and the fact that U twiddles with the P and D tapes
    and turns them into P' and D' is irrelevant, as long as the result we
    get is that of P(D), not P'(D').

    Right.  What you're describing is business as usual for TMs.


    Let me show this graphically using a much simpler example - addition:

    D: 1111111111+1111111
    P: add 'em up

    P(D)!

    D': 11111111111111111

    P has changed its input by changing the + to a 1 and erasing the last
    1, and D' now holds the correct answer to the question originally
    posed on D.

    I would argue that this is /perfectly fine/, and that there is
    nothing in Turing's problem statement to forbid it. But of course we
    must be careful that, even if U does change its inputs to P' and D',
    it must still correctly answer the question P(D).

    Nothing wrong with that.

    BTW all the stuff above about universal deciders turns out to be
    irrelevant to your argument!  (It just seems a bit odd to choose a
    non- existant TM as an example when any other (existant) TM would do
    the job more clearly...)


    Of course, Mr Olcott's change is rather different, because by
    changing his HHH he's actually changing the behaviour of his DD -
    i.e. specifying a new U - but I see no reason why he can't do that /
    provided/ he can show that he always gets the correct answer. He has
    so far failed to do this with the original HHH, and now he has
    doubled his workload by giving himself another HHH to defend.

    Right - PO's H is free to rewrite the tape in whatever way it likes,
    provided in the end it gets the right answer.

    The "you're not allowed to change the input" charge means something
    quite different.

    TLDR:  Your talking about TMs writing to their tape as part of their
    normal operation.  Nothing wrong with that.  PO is effectively talking
    about changing the meaning of D [the input to H] half way through the
    Sipser quote.

    -----------------------------------------------------------------------------
    NTLFM:

    PO is trying to interpret Sipser's quote:

    --- Start Sipser quote
          If simulating halt decider H correctly simulates its input D
          until H correctly determines that its simulated D would never
          stop running unless aborted then

          H can abort its simulation of D and correctly report that D
          specifies a non-halting sequence of configurations.
    --- End Sipser quote

    The following interpretation is ok:

         If H is given input D, and while simulating D gathers enough
         information to deduce that UTM(D) would never halt, then
         H can abort its simulation and decide D never halts.


    When Ĥ is applied to ⟨Ĥ⟩
    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qy ∞
    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qn

    (a) Ĥ copies its input ⟨Ĥ⟩
    (b) Ĥ invokes embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩
    (c) embedded_H simulates ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩
    (d) simulated ⟨Ĥ⟩ copies its input ⟨Ĥ⟩
    (e) simulated ⟨Ĥ⟩ invokes simulated embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩
    (f) simulated embedded_H simulates ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩
    (g) goto (d) with one more level of simulation

    In other words if embedded_H was a UTM

    But it isn't. It has code to abort. So, the following is irrelavant.

    would cause> Ĥ applied to ⟨Ĥ⟩ to never halt then embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩
    is correctly ruled to never halt.



    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Fred. Zwarts@21:1/5 to All on Sun May 4 08:37:05 2025
    Op 03.mei.2025 om 19:07 schreef olcott:
    On 5/2/2025 8:16 PM, Mike Terry wrote:
    On 02/05/2025 06:06, Richard Heathfield wrote:
    On 02/05/2025 05:08, dbush wrote:
    On 5/1/2025 11:57 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/1/2025 9:40 PM, dbush wrote:

    <snip>

    So you changed the input.  Changing the input is not allowed.


    I never changed the input.

    Yes you did.  You hypothesize changing the code of HHH, and HHH is
    part of the input. So you changed the input.


    Agreed.

    Changing the input is not allowed.

    Wweellll...

    I have a very minor objection to that view, an objection that I've
    wrapped up into a thought experiment.

    Let us hypothesise the paradoxical existence of U, a universal
    decider. If we pass it an arbitrary P and an arbitrary D, it can defy
    Turing (we're just hypothesising, remember) and produce a correct
    result. Cool, right? The snag is that it's a black box. We can't see
    the code.

    We set it to work, and for years we use it to prove all manner of
    questions - PvNP, Collatz, Goldbach, Riemann, the lot - and it turns
    out always to be right. That's good, right?

    But then one fine day in 2038 we are finally allowed to see the
    source code for U, which is when we discover that the algorithm
    changes the input<<< in some small way. Does that invalidate the
    answers it has been providing for over a decade, thousands of answers
    that have / all/ been verified?

    Nobody would suggest that TMs aren't allowed to write to their tape!
    Of course, that's part of how they work, and is not what posters mean
    by PO "changing the input".


    I would argue that it doesn't. Provided U(P,D) correctly reports on
    the behaviour a P(D) call would produce, I would argue that that's
    all that matters, and the fact that U twiddles with the P and D tapes
    and turns them into P' and D' is irrelevant, as long as the result we
    get is that of P(D), not P'(D').

    Right.  What you're describing is business as usual for TMs.


    Let me show this graphically using a much simpler example - addition:

    D: 1111111111+1111111
    P: add 'em up

    P(D)!

    D': 11111111111111111

    P has changed its input by changing the + to a 1 and erasing the last
    1, and D' now holds the correct answer to the question originally
    posed on D.

    I would argue that this is /perfectly fine/, and that there is
    nothing in Turing's problem statement to forbid it. But of course we
    must be careful that, even if U does change its inputs to P' and D',
    it must still correctly answer the question P(D).

    Nothing wrong with that.

    BTW all the stuff above about universal deciders turns out to be
    irrelevant to your argument!  (It just seems a bit odd to choose a
    non- existant TM as an example when any other (existant) TM would do
    the job more clearly...)


    Of course, Mr Olcott's change is rather different, because by
    changing his HHH he's actually changing the behaviour of his DD -
    i.e. specifying a new U - but I see no reason why he can't do that /
    provided/ he can show that he always gets the correct answer. He has
    so far failed to do this with the original HHH, and now he has
    doubled his workload by giving himself another HHH to defend.

    Right - PO's H is free to rewrite the tape in whatever way it likes,
    provided in the end it gets the right answer.

    The "you're not allowed to change the input" charge means something
    quite different.

    TLDR:  Your talking about TMs writing to their tape as part of their
    normal operation.  Nothing wrong with that.  PO is effectively talking
    about changing the meaning of D [the input to H] half way through the
    Sipser quote.

    -----------------------------------------------------------------------------
    NTLFM:

    PO is trying to interpret Sipser's quote:

    --- Start Sipser quote
          If simulating halt decider H correctly simulates its input D
          until H correctly determines that its simulated D would never
          stop running unless aborted then

          H can abort its simulation of D and correctly report that D
          specifies a non-halting sequence of configurations.
    --- End Sipser quote

    The following interpretation is ok:

         If H is given input D, and while simulating D gathers enough
         information to deduce that UTM(D) would never halt, then
         H can abort its simulation and decide D never halts.


    That is the same way that ChatGPT understands it.

    *ChatGPT Analyzes Simulating Termination Analyzer* https://www.researchgate.net/ publication/385090708_ChatGPT_Analyzes_Simulating_Termination_Analyzer

    For DD/HHH

    int DD()
    {
      int Halt_Status = HHH(DD);
      if (Halt_Status)
        HERE: goto HERE;
      return Halt_Status;
    }

    HHH determines whether or not DD would halt
    if HHH would have been a pure simulator.

    Still dreaming of a non-existing non-aborting HHH? Dreams are no
    substitute for logic.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Heathfield@21:1/5 to Mike Terry on Sun May 4 07:25:42 2025
    On 04/05/2025 01:20, Mike Terry wrote:
    On 03/05/2025 20:45, Richard Heathfield wrote:

    <snip>


    I am conscious that you have already explained to me (twice!)
    that Mr O's approach is aimed not at overturning the
    overarching indecidability proof but a mere detail of Linz's
    proof. Unfortunately, your explanations have not managed to
    establish a firm root in what passes for my brain.

    Third time's a charm, I think, or at least I'm further forward.
    (See question about a mile VVVVVsouthVVVVV of here.)

    In case I ever bail again, you have my full permission to remind
    me of <~/alldata/usenet/M_Terry_explains_olcott_reasoning.eml>
    where I have saved your reply for future re-enlightenment.

    This may be
    because I'm too dense to grok them, or possibly it's because
    your explanations are TOAST (see above).

    Turned out to be 50/50.

    I generally think I post way too much,

    I think Usenauts are best measured by their S/N ratio. That is,
    it's what you post rather than how much there is of it.

    and tend to wander off
    topic with unnecessary background and so on,

    Isaac Asimov was always at his happiest when starting an essay
    with the magic words "The Ancient Greeks..." In 1965 he wrote a
    book to be called "The Neutrino". He spent the first three
    quarters or so of the book on what he considered to be
    /necessary/ background, and Chapter 500-or-so is called "Enter
    The Neutrino". When he got the proofs back for checking, he saw
    that his copy editor had pencilled into the margin "AT LAST!"

    and probably I write
    too much from a "maths" perspective, because that's my
    background.  Not sure if I can change any of that! :)  Just ask
    if I use obscure notation or let me know if I'm going too
    fast/slow.  Part of the problem is I don't know your background
    and what things you're super familiar with.

    ISTR that I have recently gone on record as claiming (when asked
    if I have ever done any programming) to be a professional potato
    painter. The claim is rather less accurate than I generally try
    to be, and whilst it is true that I am super familiar (and
    perhaps too familiar) with potatoes, I haven't actually painted
    one since infants' school.

    My background? Unfortunately my potato-painting career never
    really took off, so I decided instead to earn my corn writing
    computer programs for a living.

    Any good?

    Well, maybe, maybe not. But I'll let my peers answer that one, if
    I can find some for you.

    They say you should never Google yourself because you might not
    like what you read. But what the hell, yeah? My seventh hit was
    for an ancient Usenet thread entitled "Richard HeathField. Bad
    ideas!" in which I am severely taken to task by a chap called
    "paulcr". It makes an entertaining read. His beef is with my
    claim that there's no /one/ way to do non-blocking input that can
    be guaranteed to work.

    https://groups.google.com/g/comp.lang.c.moderated/c/W9ViD37NpzE

    I would draw your attention not so much to my accuser as to the
    counsel for the defence. Doug Gwyn's name, for example, can be
    found in the acknowledgements section of K&R, and Francis
    Glassborow was for many years the chairman of the Association of
    C and C++ Users.

    Or if you prefer pictures, here's one I prepared earlier.
    Figuring out what it does is easy - suck it and see the Olcott
    way. Figuring out how it works, though, is a touch more
    challenging, and I leave it as an exercise with which to while
    away a Sunday morning:

    #include <stdlib.h>
    #include <stdio.h>


    #define O int
    #define B main
    #define F char
    #define U if
    #define S atoi
    #define C for
    #define A putchar
    #define T '*'
    #define E ' '
    #define D '\n'
    #define c ==
    #define o =
    #define d ++
    #define e return
    #define r ||

    O
    B (
    O k
    , F
    * v
    [ ]
    ) {
    O i
    , j = 9
    ; U ( k > 1
    ) { j = S
    ( v [ 1
    ] ) ; }
    U ( ! (
    j > 0 )
    ) { j =
    5 ; } U ( (
    j & 1 ) c 0 ) {
    d j ; } C (
    i = 0 ;
    i < j * j
    ; A ( i / j
    c ( 3 * j
    ) / 2 -
    ( i % j + 1
    ) r i / j c j /
    2 - i % j r
    i / j c
    j / 2 +
    i % j r
    i / j c
    i % j -
    j / 2 ? T
    : E ) , i d
    , i % j
    c 0
    ? A
    ( D
    ) :
    0 )
    ; e
    0 ;
    }


    You have said, I think, that Olcott doesn't need a universal
    decider in order to prove his point. But a less ambitious
    decider doesn't contradict Linz's proof, surely? So once more
    for luck, what exactly would PO be establishing with his
    non-universal and impatient simulator if he could only get it
    to work?

    Yes.  PO is aiming to refute the /proof method/ that Linz (and
    similar) proofs use, i.e. to attack the /reasoning/ behind the
    proof.  In effect, he is saying that his HHH/DD provide a
    counter-example to that reasoning.  His HHH/DD are not full halt
    deciders - they're /partial/ halt deciders but that would be
    enough.  I cover what a partial HD is below, and why it is enough
    for his argument [..if HHH/DD worked as originally claimed..]

    Okay. Nous sommes getting somewhere (or should that be someou?)

    If he was successful with his HHH/DD programs, it would mean the
    Linz proof contained some logical error, and so the conclusion of
    the proof (the HP theorem) would not be warranted /by that
    proof/, We would have to cross that proof out of our Master Book
    Of Mathematical Theorems And Their Proofs! As there are other
    proofs of the theorem, the theorem itself could remain.

    It would be like the following scenario:  there are many
    alternative proofs of Pythagorus' Theorem, but let's imagine that
    one of them - the "MikeT" proof - is the first one taught to all
    school children across the world, and it's been that way for the
    last 50 years.  Suddenly PO finds a flaw in that proof!  Sure,
    there are other proofs without that flaw so we still trust
    Pythagorus' Theorem, but we're not going to continue teaching
    children an incorrect proof of it, right.  So finding such a flaw
    would force many changes on our education system and be highly
    interesting in its own right.

    Okay, so maybe Linz's formulation is a bigger deal than I have
    been giving it credit for. (BTW ITYM Pythagoras. Spelling
    schmelling, sure, but I do think that names are important.)

    This doesn't explain exactly how PO's HHH/DD would "refute" the
    Linz proof, so that's what the rest of the post tries to do.

    Cue three descending chords, with just a hint of tremolo...

    BTW, when I refer to "the Linz proof" it is purely because the
    Linz book is apparently the one that PO has access to, and when
    he started posting here he claimed to have refuted the "Linz"
    proof that appears in that book.  As you suspect, the proof is
    nothing to do with Linz other than appearing in his book!

    I am reminded of Hellin's Law, which documents the as yet
    unexplained fact that for n>1, n-tuple births occur once in
    89^{n-1} pregnancies. In 1895, Hellin wrote down what biologists
    and demographers had already known for years. This penmanship
    appears to be his only contribution to the matter, and yet...
    Hellin's Law.

      It
    also appears I expect in some form in most computer science books
    covering computation theory, because it's so well known.  Hmm,
    not sure who discovered it, but it would be one of the big guys
    like Turing, Church, Kleene,... all doing related work in the
    early days of the field.

    Turing, I think., in 1936.

    ON COMPUTABLE NUMBERS, WITH AN APPLICATION TO
    THE ENTSCHEIDUNGSPROBLEM

    I have a 2MB PDF copy. I can't remember where I found it but, if
    you want it, drop me an email and I'll send it by return.

    So to say what PO's code would refute, I need to explain exactly
    how the Linz proof works.  Sorry if you already perfectly clear
    on that!

    I'm fine with the general idea of the proof. If we have a
    universal decider U we can (easily!) use it to make a program
    that it can't decide, and we have reductio QED.

    <snipped but not skipped>

    This next bit might be a missing key for you...    Looking at the
    above, we started by me giving you a "halt decider" H.  What if I
    only gave you a lesser achievement: a "partial halt decider" that
    correctly decides halting for certain (P,I) inputs, but fails to
    halt for all the rest?

    What's to stop the partial decider from deciding pseudorandomly?
    For example: hashing the input tapes and deciding according to
    the hash modulo 2? This would:

    1) always decide (as required);
    2) sometimes get it right (as required);
    3) sometimes get it wrong (as required if it's to be only 'partial');
    4) always make the same decision when given the same input
    (clearly desirable);
    5) be trivial to write;
    6) would step around all the simulation nonsense and puncture
    about 99% of the current quarrel.
    7) It could obviously be arranged if need be to interpret the
    hash mod 2 so that when fed itself as input it gets itself (a)
    right or (b) wrong.

    Clearly this won't do, because surely /somebody/ would have
    pointed it out by now, but... /why/ won't it do?

      The answer is the same logic still
    applies, but the conclusion is slightly different:

    -  I give you a /partial/ HD  H
    -  You follow the same instructions to create the new TM, H^
    -  The same reasoning of the Linz proof shows that my H does not
    correctly decide halting
       for the case of TM H^ running against input <H^>
       a)  If H decides HALTS, we can show H^(<H^>) never halts
       b)  If H decides NEVER_HALTS, we can show H^(<H^>) halts
       c)  If H fails to decide (i.e. it loops) then H^(<H^>) never
    halts
           This last possibility is new, because H is only a partial
    halt decider

    Now we can look at what PO claims to have: a *partial* halt
    decider H, which CORRECTLY decides its corresponding input
    (<H^>,<H^>).  Specifically, he claims his H decides NEVER_HALTS,
    and that indeed H^(<H^>) never halts.  This contradicts the Linz
    proof /reasoning/ which lead to (b) above.

    Since the Linz proof reasoning would have been shown to reach a
    false conclusion [in the case of PO's HHH/DD programs], the
    reasoning must be wrong somewhere, and if the reasoning is wrong
    it can't be used in the Linz proof.  It is ok here that H is only
    a partial halt decider - in fact the above only requires that
    PO's H correctly decides the one H^(<H^>) case to get the
    contradiction.

    Er, that's it!

    Just as a reminder I'll repeat the final outcome of all this:

    -  PO's H does decide NEVER_HALTS for TM H^ running with input <H^>.
    -  PO's H^ running with input <H^> in fact halts, in line with
    Linz logic (b) above.

    ...and so there's nothing to see.


    A final observation - nothing in this post is anything to do with "simulation".  That comes later looking at how PO's H supposedly
    works...

    Got it... ish.

    I suspect that I'll be re-reading your reply for some time to come.


    --
    Richard Heathfield
    Email: rjh at cpax dot org dot uk
    "Usenet is a strange place" - dmr 29 July 1999
    Sig line 4 vacant - apply within

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Heathfield@21:1/5 to olcott on Sun May 4 17:21:51 2025
    On 04/05/2025 17:06, olcott wrote:

    <snip>

    They simply guess that because DD(DD) halts that
    DD correctly simulated by HHH must also halt.

    It's not a guess. If direct execution halts, so must the
    simulation. If the simulation produces a different answer than
    direct execution then the simulation is flawed, and to consider
    otherwise strongly suggests that you lack the capacity to think
    logically.

    They cannot provide these detailed steps of the
    execution trace of each machine instruction

    It's not required. Such a trace could at best only show where the
    simulation fouls up.

    BECAUSE THEY KNOW THAT THEY ARE WRONG AND ONLY PLAYING HEAD GAMES.

    I am not a psychiatrist, but that smacks of projection.

    If I were contracted to write a simulation of P(D) but I
    presented a program that got a different result to a directly
    executed P(D), my client would be entitled to ask why and expect
    an answer he could understand and that made clear logical sense.
    A simulation that fails to simulate is ipso facto broken.

    --
    Richard Heathfield
    Email: rjh at cpax dot org dot uk
    "Usenet is a strange place" - dmr 29 July 1999
    Sig line 4 vacant - apply within

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Heathfield@21:1/5 to olcott on Sun May 4 20:01:17 2025
    On 04/05/2025 18:30, olcott wrote:
    On 5/4/2025 11:21 AM, Richard Heathfield wrote:
    On 04/05/2025 17:06, olcott wrote:

    <snip>

    They simply guess that because DD(DD) halts that
    DD correctly simulated by HHH must also halt.

    It's not a guess. If direct execution halts, so must the
    simulation.

    <snip>

    Maybe you are confused between halting (reaching
    a final halt state and terminating normally)
    with stopping running for any reason such as
    an aborted emulation. *THEY ARE NOT THE SAME*

    Maybe you are confused between equality and inequality.

    If DD halts when directly executed, then a correct simulation of
    DD must also halt. If it fails to do so (no matter for what
    reason), it is not a correct simulation.

    Now, let's take a different angle. You could rationally claim
    that the simulation doesn't *need* to be correct, provided only
    that your decider makes the right decision about DD's halting
    behaviour. You've already established that DD halts when directly
    executed, so you just need to ensure that your decider reports
    'halts' when passed DD as its parameter. How hard could it be?

    --
    Richard Heathfield
    Email: rjh at cpax dot org dot uk
    "Usenet is a strange place" - dmr 29 July 1999
    Sig line 4 vacant - apply within

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mike Terry@21:1/5 to Richard Heathfield on Sun May 4 19:57:27 2025
    On 04/05/2025 07:25, Richard Heathfield wrote:
    On 04/05/2025 01:20, Mike Terry wrote:
    On 03/05/2025 20:45, Richard Heathfield wrote:

    <snip>


    I am conscious that you have already explained to me (twice!) that Mr O's approach is aimed not
    at overturning the overarching indecidability proof but a mere detail of Linz's proof.
    Unfortunately, your explanations have not managed to establish a firm root in what passes for my
    brain.

    Third time's a charm, I think, or at least I'm further forward. (See question about a mile
    VVVVVsouthVVVVV of here.)

    In case I ever bail again, you have my full permission to remind me of <~/alldata/usenet/M_Terry_explains_olcott_reasoning.eml> where I have saved your reply for future
    re-enlightenment.

    This may be because I'm too dense to grok them, or possibly it's because your explanations are
    TOAST (see above).

    Turned out to be 50/50.

    I generally think I post way too much,

    I think Usenauts are best measured by their S/N ratio. That is, it's what you post rather than how
    much there is of it.

    and tend to wander off topic with unnecessary background and so on,

    Isaac Asimov was always at his happiest when starting an essay with the magic words "The Ancient
    Greeks..." In 1965 he wrote a book to be called "The Neutrino". He spent the first three quarters or
    so of the book on what he considered to be /necessary/ background, and Chapter 500-or-so is called
    "Enter The Neutrino". When he got the proofs back for checking, he saw that his copy editor had
    pencilled into the margin "AT LAST!"

    and probably I write too much from a "maths" perspective, because that's my background.  Not sure
    if I can change any of that! :)  Just ask if I use obscure notation or let me know if I'm going
    too fast/slow.  Part of the problem is I don't know your background and what things you're super
    familiar with.

    ISTR that I have recently gone on record as claiming (when asked if I have ever done any
    programming) to be a professional potato painter. The claim is rather less accurate than I generally
    try to be, and whilst it is true that I am super familiar (and perhaps too familiar) with potatoes,
    I haven't actually painted one since infants' school.

    My background? Unfortunately my potato-painting career never really took off, so I decided instead
    to earn my corn writing computer programs for a living.

    Any good?

    Sure. I expect everyone here has done more than enough programming to . It was more how much maths
    background you have + familiarity with HP proof you have.

    <..snip..>

    BTW, when I refer to "the Linz proof" it is purely because the Linz book is apparently the one
    that PO has access to, and when he started posting here he claimed to have refuted the "Linz"
    proof that appears in that book.  As you suspect, the proof is nothing to do with Linz other than
    appearing in his book!

    I am reminded of Hellin's Law, which documents the as yet unexplained fact that for n>1, n-tuple
    births occur once in 89^{n-1} pregnancies. In 1895, Hellin wrote down what biologists and
    demographers had already known for years. This penmanship appears to be his only contribution to the
    matter, and yet... Hellin's Law.

    Well, Linz doesn't get "Linz's proof", except here in PO thread land. He's just one of dozens of
    authors covering the proof, not the first or last, but simply the one PO talks about...

      It also appears I expect in some form in most computer science books covering computation
    theory, because it's so well known.  Hmm, not sure who discovered it, but it would be one of the
    big guys like Turing, Church, Kleene,... all doing related work in the early days of the field.

    Turing, I think., in 1936.

    ON COMPUTABLE NUMBERS, WITH AN APPLICATION TO
    THE ENTSCHEIDUNGSPROBLEM

    I have a 2MB PDF copy. I can't remember where I found it but, if you want it, drop me an email and
    I'll send it by return.

    Thanks, but I have a PDF tucked away. You may be right that it is where the halting problem first
    gets covered, or at least HP for TMs.

    So to say what PO's code would refute, I need to explain exactly how the Linz proof works.  Sorry
    if you already perfectly clear on that!

    I'm fine with the general idea of the proof. If we have a universal decider U we can (easily!) use
    it to make a program that it can't decide, and we have reductio QED.

    <snipped but not skipped>

    This next bit might be a missing key for you...    Looking at the above, we started by me giving
    you a "halt decider" H.  What if I only gave you a lesser achievement: a "partial halt decider"
    that correctly decides halting for certain (P,I) inputs, but fails to halt for all the rest?

    What's to stop the partial decider from deciding pseudorandomly? For example: hashing the input
    tapes and deciding according to the hash modulo 2? This would:

    1) always decide (as required);
    2) sometimes get it right (as required);
    3) sometimes get it wrong (as required if it's to be only 'partial');

    No, partial halt deciders [*PHD*s] aren't supposed to get it wrong! If they don't know the answer
    they're supposed to never answer, but if they do answer [i.e. HALTS or NEVER_HALTS] it must be
    right. We could define PHDs so that they have a 3rd answer DONT_KNOW, but assuming we still allow
    them to never answer I don't see that the DONT_KNOW answer adds much. [the new PHDs would be
    equivalent to my definition]

    If we add a DONT_KNOW answer, and then insist the PHD must halt with one of the 3 answers, I think
    that would be a different concept, because a PHD might be searching for a particular test condition
    and never find it. That would be an infinite loop, which I consider reasonable, but if it is forced
    instead to decide DONT_KNOW in finite time, then such a potentially unending search would be
    excluded. So I think we have a different concept of PHD now.

    Actually, while I've talked about PHDs which are not allowed to decide incorrectly, in fact for PO's
    purposes it wouldn't matter if we allowed PHDs to decide inputs incorrectly like you're imagining.
    We could be talking about a new type of TM, maybe call it a "Putative PHD" [*PPHD*] which takes the
    (P,I) input, and may decide HALTS/NEVER_HALTS or never decide, and PPHDs have no requirement to
    answer correctly. [PO's HHH is really a PPHD, not a PHD as it sometimes answers incorrectly]

    Everything I've said about PHD's in relation to PO's claims to refute Linz, would work equally well
    with PPHDs! That's because all that really matters for PO is that the ONE SPECIFIC INPUT
    (<H^>,<H^>) must be decided correctly. It's still the case, even for PPHDs, that the reasoning used
    in the Linz proof implies that if H is a PPHD, H will NOT decide input (<H^>,<H^>) correctly. So if
    PO could provides even a PPHD H that decides (<H^>,<H^>) /correctly/ that shows a problem with the
    Linz proof logic. [Of course, PO cannot provide such an H.]

    4) always make the same decision when given the same input (clearly desirable);
    5) be trivial to write;
    6) would step around all the simulation nonsense and puncture about 99% of the current quarrel.
    7) It could obviously be arranged if need be to interpret the hash mod 2 so that when fed itself as
    input it gets itself (a) right or (b) wrong.

    Yes PHDs can be trivial, even given they are not allowed to give wrong answers. A PHD could examine
    its input and check whether the starting state is a halt state. If it is, it returns HALTS
    otherwise it just loops (or return DONT+KNOW if we allow that). That's not very useful to anyone,
    but more functional PHDs may be of genuine use to developers.

    Or a PHD could simulate its input and examine the computation steps for tight loops. If it spots
    one it decides NEVER_HALTS, and if the simulation halts it decides HALTS. That is a valid PHD which
    would sometimes decide halting correctly, and never decide incorrectly. It is a bit like PO's H,
    except that PO's H has further tests beyond the simple tight loop test. One of those tests is
    unsound, in that it is intended to detect non-halting behaviour but it can also match inputs that
    halt. [That's what happens with his HHH/DD pair]


    Clearly this won't do, because surely /somebody/ would have pointed it out by now, but... /why/
    won't it do?


    That's a good question!

    Given that PO's /only aim/ is to deliver an H which works for ONE SPECIFIC INPUT (<H^>,<H^>), why
    can't he just assume in his code for H that that is the input, and simply give whatever answer he
    needs for his argument to work? Someone else pointed this out a few years ago - PO could just write
    a trivial stub that works in this one input scenario. [Hmm, I think that was Malcolm McLean who
    hasn't posted for a couple of years.]

    Logically that makes perfect sense. But for PO I suppose the answer is that if he just did that, it
    would be too obvious that it Just Doesn't Work. In fact it would be obvious that it /can't/ work
    due to the way H^ relates to H, together with the reasoning in the Linz proof.

    His H could just return NEVER_HALTS straight away, which it is going to do later on anyway for input
    (<H^>,<H^>). The logic of how it gets that decision doesn't really matter! The H^ built from that
    H will internally run its embedded_H code which will similarly "decide" DOESNT_HALT and H^ will then
    halt. That's all the same as in PO's actual code, HHH/DD but without all the faffing around with
    simulations!! :) Yes, coding H like that means it will get other inputs completely wrong - but so
    what? We are just interested in what happens with that one input case.

    In the end the answer to your question is that PO /needs/ all the faffing with simulation to
    maintain his faulty intuitions /in his own mind/. His simulation loop watches for a particular
    (unsound) "non-halting" pattern, and it sees it when simulating H^(<H^>), which is one of PO's
    justifications for saying that H^(<H^>) "really" never halts, even though it does. If he just had
    stub routines that returned NEVER_HALTS without seeing the "non-halting" pattern, the big picture
    outcome would be exactly the same, but he'd lose his justification that maintains his intuition that
    H^ never halts.

    Mike.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Heathfield@21:1/5 to olcott on Sun May 4 20:13:19 2025
    On 04/05/2025 18:38, olcott wrote:

    <snip>

    int sum(int x, int y) { return x + y; }
    The mapping from sum(3,2) to sum 5 + 6 does not
    exist

    That's meaningless. Addition maps two ordinary numbers onto one
    number. The mapping of 3 + 2 is to 5, and the mapping of 5 + 6 is
    to 11. sum(3,2) is the notation of a programming language's
    function call, not a mapping. Are you confusing 'computable
    function' with 'programming language procedure'?

    for the same reason that the mapping from DD correctly
    simulated by HHH to DD(DD) does not exist.

    So you're saying that HHH cannot correctly simulate DD? I agree.

    THE MAPPING MUST BE WHAT THE INPUT ACTUALLY SPECIES
    NOT MERELY WHAT SOMEONE EXPECTS.

    You might find it easier simply to say that the decider must
    decide correctly. (I concur.)


    <snip>

    --
    Richard Heathfield
    Email: rjh at cpax dot org dot uk
    "Usenet is a strange place" - dmr 29 July 1999
    Sig line 4 vacant - apply within

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Heathfield@21:1/5 to olcott on Sun May 4 20:22:40 2025
    On 04/05/2025 19:17, olcott wrote:
    I hereby overload the
    term "mapping" with this new meaning.

    Don't expect anyone to remember that. You'd do better to define a
    new term.

    --
    Richard Heathfield
    Email: rjh at cpax dot org dot uk
    "Usenet is a strange place" - dmr 29 July 1999
    Sig line 4 vacant - apply within

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Heathfield@21:1/5 to olcott on Sun May 4 22:26:47 2025
    On 04/05/2025 21:06, olcott wrote:
    Computable functions REPORT ON WHAT THEIR INPUT ACTUALLY SPECIFIES

    What is pi's input?

    --
    Richard Heathfield
    Email: rjh at cpax dot org dot uk
    "Usenet is a strange place" - dmr 29 July 1999
    Sig line 4 vacant - apply within

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Heathfield@21:1/5 to Mike Terry on Sun May 4 22:18:27 2025
    On 04/05/2025 19:57, Mike Terry wrote:

    <snip>

    It was more how much maths background you have
    + familiarity with HP proof you have.

    Sorry for the noise, then.

    Very little. I rattled through the first ten years easily enough,
    but I hit a hard wall (integration by parts) and never really
    recovered. Such mathematics as I have picked up since has mostly
    been through popularisers such as Martin Gardner, Ian Stewart,
    and Douglas Hofstadter. I think it was in Hofstadter that I first
    learned of the Halting Problem.

    <snip>

    What's to stop the partial decider from deciding
    pseudorandomly? For example: hashing the input tapes and
    deciding according to the hash modulo 2? This would:

    1) always decide (as required);
    2) sometimes get it right (as required);
    3) sometimes get it wrong (as required if it's to be only
    'partial');

    No, partial halt deciders [*PHD*s] aren't supposed to get it
    wrong!

    We must distinguish carefully between PHDs and PhDs (although,
    come to think of it, PhDs aren't supposed to get it wrong either).

    But... okay, I'll read on...

    If they don't know the answer they're supposed to never
    answer, but if they do answer [i.e. HALTS or NEVER_HALTS] it must
    be right.  We could define PHDs so that they have a 3rd answer
    DONT_KNOW, but assuming we still allow them to never answer I
    don't see that the DONT_KNOW answer adds much.  [the new PHDs
    would be equivalent to my definition]

    If they never answer, how long do we wait for nothing to happen?

    If we add a DONT_KNOW answer, and then insist the PHD must halt
    with one of the 3 answers, I think that would be a different
    concept, because a PHD might be searching for a particular test
    condition and never find it.  That would be an infinite loop,
    which I consider reasonable, but if it is forced instead to
    decide DONT_KNOW in finite time, then such a potentially unending
    search would be excluded.  So I think we have a different concept
    of PHD now.

    I've got my wallet in my hand, but I'm not quite ready yet to buy
    a PHD that doesn't answer. DONT_KNOW is conceptually easier to
    swallow (even though the mileage doesn't look all that great).

    Actually, while I've talked about PHDs which are not allowed to
    decide incorrectly, in fact for PO's purposes it wouldn't matter
    if we allowed PHDs to decide inputs incorrectly like you're
    imagining. We could be talking about a new type of TM, maybe call
    it a "Putative PHD"  [*PPHD*] which takes the (P,I) input, and
    may decide HALTS/NEVER_HALTS or never decide, and PPHDs have no
    requirement to answer correctly.  [PO's HHH is really a PPHD, not
    a PHD as it sometimes answers incorrectly]

    Which raises the question of why he bothers.

    Everything I've said about PHD's in relation to PO's claims to
    refute Linz, would work equally well with PPHDs!  That's because
    all that really matters for PO is that the ONE SPECIFIC INPUT
    (<H^>,<H^>) must be decided correctly.  It's still the case, even
    for PPHDs, that the reasoning used in the Linz proof implies that
    if H is a PPHD, H will NOT decide input (<H^>,<H^>) correctly.
    So if PO could provides even a PPHD H that decides (<H^>,<H^>)
    /correctly/ that shows a problem with the Linz proof logic.  [Of
    course, PO cannot provide such an H.]

    Well, it's not hard. Scaffolding first (not for publication):

    1) he writes H(P,D), which hashes P and D (md5 hash, say? Or even
    just add up the bits!) and returns mod 2 of the result,
    interpreting 0 as 'loops' and 1 as 'halts'
    2) he waves Turing's magic wand and sees whether he gets the
    result he needs for (<H^><H^>).
    3) if so, great! But if not, he reverses the meanings of 0 and 1.
    4) remove from the docs all signs of fiddling the mod 2 meanings.

    Having 'tuned' his PPHD, he can now publish and claim his place
    in history.

    <snip>

    Clearly this won't do, because surely /somebody/ would have
    pointed it out by now, but... /why/ won't it do?


    That's a good question!

    Given that PO's /only aim/ is to deliver an H which works for ONE
    SPECIFIC INPUT (<H^>,<H^>), why can't he just assume in his code
    for H that that is the input, and simply give whatever answer he
    needs for his argument to work?  Someone else pointed this out a
    few years ago - PO could just write a trivial stub that works in
    this one input scenario.

    I would have been surprised to learn that it hadn't already come up.

      [Hmm, I think that was Malcolm McLean
    who hasn't posted for a couple of years.]

    I hope he's okay. (Malcolm and I have crossed many swords and we
    rarely agreed, but I recall him being a most well-mannered and
    personable fellow.

    Logically that makes perfect sense.  But for PO I suppose the
    answer is that if he just did that, it would be too obvious that
    it Just Doesn't Work.  In fact it would be obvious that it
    /can't/ work due to the way H^ relates to H, together with the
    reasoning in the Linz proof.

    It's already obvious that his HHH doesn't work, but... well,
    perhaps one man's obvious is another man's Turing Award.

    <snip>

    In the end the answer to your question is that PO /needs/ all the
    faffing with simulation to maintain his faulty intuitions /in his
    own mind/.

    Yes, I think there's something in that. And he has to retain the
    illusion that he's achieved something difficult.

    <snip>

    --
    Richard Heathfield
    Email: rjh at cpax dot org dot uk
    "Usenet is a strange place" - dmr 29 July 1999
    Sig line 4 vacant - apply within

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to olcott on Sun May 4 19:50:19 2025
    On 5/4/25 1:30 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/4/2025 11:21 AM, Richard Heathfield wrote:
    On 04/05/2025 17:06, olcott wrote:

    <snip>

    They simply guess that because DD(DD) halts that
    DD correctly simulated by HHH must also halt.

    It's not a guess. If direct execution halts, so must the simulation.

    _DD()
    [00002133] 55         push ebp      ; housekeeping
    [00002134] 8bec       mov ebp,esp   ; housekeeping
    [00002136] 51         push ecx      ; make space for local [00002137] 6833210000 push 00002133 ; push DD
    [0000213c] e882f4ffff call 000015c3 ; call HHH(DD)
    [00002141] 83c404     add esp,+04
    [00002144] 8945fc     mov [ebp-04],eax
    [00002147] 837dfc00   cmp dword [ebp-04],+00
    [0000214b] 7402       jz 0000214f
    [0000214d] ebfe       jmp 0000214d
    [0000214f] 8b45fc     mov eax,[ebp-04]
    [00002152] 8be5       mov esp,ebp
    [00002154] 5d         pop ebp
    [00002155] c3         ret
    Size in bytes:(0035) [00002155]

    Maybe you are confused between halting (reaching
    a final halt state and terminating normally)
    with stopping running for any reason such as
    an aborted emulation. *THEY ARE NOT THE SAME*

    But Halting is a property of the Machine iteelf, and not defined for a
    partial emulation as generated by a reason of an aborted emulation.


    DD correctly emulated by HHH stops running when
    HHH aborts its simulation.

    Nope, that just show you are using an improperly defined term, as it
    isn't "correct"


    DD correctly emulated by HHH cannot possibly
    reach its "return" instruction final halt state.

    No, "DD correctly emulated by HHH" is just a fantasy of ylur mind, and
    thhus not a valid basis to talk about anything,

    After all, you have insisted on a definiton of HHH, as it is defined in Halt7.c, and it doesn't do what you claim HHH must do, thus all you are
    doing is proving you are just a pathological liar.


    You must be imagining that DD emulated by HHH
    leaps over the "call" instruction and jumps
    straight to the "ret" instruction.


    No, HHH just incorrectly stops its emulation, making your claims of a DD correctly emulated by HHGH just a pathological lie out that comes out of
    your ignorant imagination.


    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to olcott on Sun May 4 19:54:02 2025
    On 5/4/25 4:02 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/4/2025 2:01 PM, Richard Heathfield wrote:
    On 04/05/2025 18:30, olcott wrote:
    On 5/4/2025 11:21 AM, Richard Heathfield wrote:
    On 04/05/2025 17:06, olcott wrote:

    <snip>

    They simply guess that because DD(DD) halts that
    DD correctly simulated by HHH must also halt.

    It's not a guess. If direct execution halts, so must the simulation.

    <snip>

    Maybe you are confused between halting (reaching
    a final halt state and terminating normally)
    with stopping running for any reason such as
    an aborted emulation. *THEY ARE NOT THE SAME*

    Maybe you are confused between equality and inequality.

    If DD halts when directly executed, then a correct simulation of DD
    must also halt.

    ONLY IF YOU STUPIDLY IGNORE THE X86 LANGUAGE
    THAT PROVES THAT DD CORRECTLY EMULATED BY HHH IS
    NOT THE SAME EXECUTION TRACE AS DIRECTLY EXECUTED DD(DD)

    _DD()
    [00002133] 55         push ebp      ; housekeeping
    [00002134] 8bec       mov ebp,esp   ; housekeeping
    [00002136] 51         push ecx      ; make space for local [00002137] 6833210000 push 00002133 ; push DD
    [0000213c] e882f4ffff call 000015c3 ; call HHH(DD)
    [00002141] 83c404     add esp,+04
    [00002144] 8945fc     mov [ebp-04],eax
    [00002147] 837dfc00   cmp dword [ebp-04],+00
    [0000214b] 7402       jz 0000214f
    [0000214d] ebfe       jmp 0000214d
    [0000214f] 8b45fc     mov eax,[ebp-04]
    [00002152] 8be5       mov esp,ebp
    [00002154] 5d         pop ebp
    [00002155] c3         ret
    Size in bytes:(0035) [00002155]

    After DD is correctly emulated by HHH
    HHH MUST EMULATE ITSELF EMULATING DD
    OR IT VIOLATES THE RULES OF THE X86 LANGUAGE.

    DD is NOT correctly emulated by HHH, and thus you just prove yourself to
    be a pathological iiar.


    The relationshop between HHH and DD is the exact
    same infinite recursion as the above HHH and DDD
    except that HHH is smart enough to cut it off
    and not get stuck in infinite recursion.



    No, because HHH does exactly the same thing for both, as it never sees
    far enough to tell the difference, and thus HHH always returns 0 to its
    caller, and thus both DD and DDD will halt.

    Sorry, your problem is you keep on talking about some imaginary HHH that
    isn't the HHH that you have insisted is the HHH that exists in the
    problem in the published Halt7.c

    This just proves that you are nothing but a stupid liar that doesn't
    even remember his own stipulations.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to olcott on Sun May 4 19:46:12 2025
    On 5/4/25 12:06 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/3/2025 4:28 PM, dbush wrote:
    On 5/3/2025 3:45 PM, Richard Heathfield wrote:

    I am conscious that you have already explained to me (twice!) that Mr
    O's approach is aimed not at overturning the overarching
    indecidability proof but a mere detail of Linz's proof.
    Unfortunately, your explanations have not managed to establish a firm
    root in what passes for my brain. This may be because I'm too dense
    to grok them, or possibly it's because your explanations are TOAST
    (see above).

    You have said, I think, that Olcott doesn't need a universal decider
    in order to prove his point. But a less ambitious decider doesn't
    contradict Linz's proof, surely? So once more for luck, what exactly
    would PO be establishing with his non-universal and impatient
    simulator if he could only get it to work?

    The core issue is that PO, despise being nearly 70 and having worked
    as a programmer, fundamentally doesn't understand proof by contradiction.


    The actual issue is the NO ONE here (or perhaps anywhere)
    sufficiently understands the key details about
    COMPUTING THE MAPPING FROM AN INPUT TO AN OUTPUT.

    No, the problem is you don't understand is that the mapping that the
    halt decider is being asked to compute, doesn't need to be defined by a "computation".


    Many here know that a mapping from the input must be
    computed. What they don't know are ALL of the tiny
    detailed steps required to compute this mapping.

    No, it doesn't. The DECIDER can only do a computation, but the mapping
    it is asked to compute doesn't need to be.

    Please try to show a reference that says a "Function" (not a "Computable Function") has to have its mapping computed.

    Of that we can only create problems based on Computable Funcitons.



    They simply guess that because DD(DD) halts that
    DD correctly simulated by HHH must also halt.

    No, the problem is that HHH doesn't correctlyu simulate its input.

    A fact you have implicitly agreed to by refusing to show where the so
    called "correct simulation" by HHH actually correctly diviated from that
    actual correct simulation that matched the direct execution of the input.

    You know, the instruction correctly simulated according to the x86
    language as described by the official Intel Documentation.


    They cannot provide these detailed steps of the
    execution trace of each machine instruction showing
    exactly how DD correctly emulated by HHH halts
    BECAUSE THEY KNOW THAT THEY ARE WRONG AND ONLY PLAYING HEAD GAMES.

    Because you have proven that no HHH that answer can correctly simulate
    its input.

    In fact, your asking for someone to provide your proof just shows you
    don't understand how proofs actualy worl.


    _DD()
    [00002133] 55         push ebp      ; housekeeping
    [00002134] 8bec       mov ebp,esp   ; housekeeping
    [00002136] 51         push ecx      ; make space for local [00002137] 6833210000 push 00002133 ; push DD
    [0000213c] e882f4ffff call 000015c3 ; call HHH(DD)
    [00002141] 83c404     add esp,+04
    [00002144] 8945fc     mov [ebp-04],eax
    [00002147] 837dfc00   cmp dword [ebp-04],+00
    [0000214b] 7402       jz 0000214f
    [0000214d] ebfe       jmp 0000214d
    [0000214f] 8b45fc     mov eax,[ebp-04]
    [00002152] 8be5       mov esp,ebp
    [00002154] 5d         pop ebp
    [00002155] c3         ret
    Size in bytes:(0035) [00002155]



    Which isn't a correct program, as it doesn't include to code for HHH,
    and if you do include the code of your Halt7.c, your requirement becomes
    a category error as you can't aslk for the results of a correct
    simulation from a defined program that does do one.

    All you are showing is you fundamentally don't understand what a
    "Program", is, showing you are just totally ignorant of what you talk about.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to olcott on Sun May 4 19:58:18 2025
    On 5/4/25 1:38 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/4/2025 11:57 AM, dbush wrote:
    On 5/4/2025 12:06 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/3/2025 4:28 PM, dbush wrote:
    On 5/3/2025 3:45 PM, Richard Heathfield wrote:

    I am conscious that you have already explained to me (twice!) that
    Mr O's approach is aimed not at overturning the overarching
    indecidability proof but a mere detail of Linz's proof.
    Unfortunately, your explanations have not managed to establish a
    firm root in what passes for my brain. This may be because I'm too
    dense to grok them, or possibly it's because your explanations are
    TOAST (see above).

    You have said, I think, that Olcott doesn't need a universal
    decider in order to prove his point. But a less ambitious decider
    doesn't contradict Linz's proof, surely? So once more for luck,
    what exactly would PO be establishing with his non-universal and
    impatient simulator if he could only get it to work?

    The core issue is that PO, despise being nearly 70 and having worked
    as a programmer, fundamentally doesn't understand proof by
    contradiction.


    The actual issue is the NO ONE here (or perhaps anywhere)
    sufficiently understands the key details about
    COMPUTING THE MAPPING FROM AN INPUT TO AN OUTPUT.

    Many here know that a mapping from the input must be
    computed.

    False.  There is no requirement that a mapping is computable.  The
    halting function is one such mapping, as Linz and others have proved
    and you have *explictly* agreed is correct.


    What they don't know are ALL of the tiny
    detailed steps required to compute this mapping.


    And if the mapping isn't computable, like the halting function, there
    are no such steps.


    int sum(int x, int y) { return x + y; }
    The mapping from sum(3,2) to sum 5 + 6 does not
    exist

    Which is just a nonsense statement.

    You don't map a progrma invocation to anything but the output it
    generates, and then compare it to the mapping the program was supposed
    to compute.


    for the same reason that the mapping from DD correctly
    simulated by HHH to DD(DD) does not exist.

    No, the mapping from DD correctly simulated by HHH just doesn't exist,
    as the defined HHH doesn't correctly simulate its input.


    THE MAPPING MUST BE WHAT THE INPUT ACTUALLY SPECIES
    NOT MERELY WHAT SOMEONE EXPECTS.


    Right, and by the DEFINITION of the Halting Problem, the input to the
    decider represents the actual program to be decided on, and the mapping
    is based on the actual execution of that program.

    If you as the programmer didn't give it the right representatin, then
    the error is on YOUR part.



    They simply guess that because DD(DD) halts that
    DD correctly simulated by HHH must also halt.

    A correct simulation is stipulated to be one that exactly matches the
    behavior of the machine to be simulated.


    I not you never answer this issue. Probably because you know you are
    just lying about what a correct simulation is.

    DD is not correctly simulated by HHH, as the last instruction
    simulated is not simulated correctly, because the x86 language
    requires any executed instruction other than a HLT to be followed by
    the execution of the next instruction.

    We also know that "DD correctly simulated by HHH" is PO-speak for
    "Replacing the code of HHH with an unconditional simulator and
    subsequently running HHH(DD)", as you have agreed and given permission
    to replace the former with the later.

    This means that you're changing the input.

    Changing the input is not allowed.


    They cannot provide these detailed steps of the
    execution trace of each machine instruction showing
    exactly how DD correctly emulated by HHH halts
    BECAUSE THEY KNOW THAT THEY ARE WRONG AND ONLY PLAYING HEAD GAMES.

    That you don't understand requirements doesn't make it a head game.



    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to olcott on Sun May 4 20:03:33 2025
    On 5/4/25 2:17 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/4/2025 12:48 PM, dbush wrote:
    On 5/4/2025 1:38 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/4/2025 11:57 AM, dbush wrote:
    On 5/4/2025 12:06 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/3/2025 4:28 PM, dbush wrote:
    On 5/3/2025 3:45 PM, Richard Heathfield wrote:

    I am conscious that you have already explained to me (twice!)
    that Mr O's approach is aimed not at overturning the overarching >>>>>>> indecidability proof but a mere detail of Linz's proof.
    Unfortunately, your explanations have not managed to establish a >>>>>>> firm root in what passes for my brain. This may be because I'm
    too dense to grok them, or possibly it's because your
    explanations are TOAST (see above).

    You have said, I think, that Olcott doesn't need a universal
    decider in order to prove his point. But a less ambitious decider >>>>>>> doesn't contradict Linz's proof, surely? So once more for luck,
    what exactly would PO be establishing with his non-universal and >>>>>>> impatient simulator if he could only get it to work?

    The core issue is that PO, despise being nearly 70 and having
    worked as a programmer, fundamentally doesn't understand proof by
    contradiction.


    The actual issue is the NO ONE here (or perhaps anywhere)
    sufficiently understands the key details about
    COMPUTING THE MAPPING FROM AN INPUT TO AN OUTPUT.

    Many here know that a mapping from the input must be
    computed.

    False.  There is no requirement that a mapping is computable.  The
    halting function is one such mapping, as Linz and others have proved
    and you have *explictly* agreed is correct.


    What they don't know are ALL of the tiny
    detailed steps required to compute this mapping.


    And if the mapping isn't computable, like the halting function,
    there are no such steps.


    int sum(int x, int y) { return x + y; }
    The mapping from sum(3,2) to sum 5 + 6 does not
    exist

    Category error.  A mapping is an association between an input domain
    and an output domain, not a C function call to a value.


    We can be more vague and say there is a mapping
    from pairs of integers to their integer sum value.

    What is "vague" about that?



    The mapping from sum(3,2) is much more specific it
    only maps to 5 by the rules of arithmetic.

    No, sum(3,2) maps to the 5 that sum computes.

    It is correct because the "vague" mapping you talked about above agrees
    with that.


    If there is no preexisting term for the mapping from
    one specific input to one specific output via a specific
    set of transformation rules then I hereby overload the
    term "mapping" with this new meaning.

    Sounds like what you mean by the computation performed by the machine.


    INPUTS to functions computed by Turing Machines
    must correspond to OUTPUTS via an algorithm.

    That defines what the Turing Machine WILL produce.

    That doesn't define what it must produce to be "correct"


    The WILD GUESS that DD correctly emulated by HHH
    must halt because DD(DD) halts ignores that a
    specific algorithms is required.

    "correctly emulated by HHH" is a void term, as HHH doesn't always
    correctly emulate its input.

    The mapping that HHH must produce, to be a Halt Decider, is what the
    direct execution of the program the input represent would do.

    PERIOD.


    If you cannot show every detailed step of the full
    execution trace of HOW DD emulated by HHH
    reaches its own emulated final halt state
    THEN ALL YOU HAVE IS BLUSTER.

    Since you have proven that HHH doesn't do a correct simulation, you have
    proven that you request is just a strawman.

    We don't care a rat's ass what HHH's possible partial emulation does,
    that just determines the answer it will give, not the correct answer it
    needs to produce to be correct.

    Sorry, yopu are just proving your ignorance of what you are talking about.


    _DD()
    [00002133] 55         push ebp      ; housekeeping
    [00002134] 8bec       mov ebp,esp   ; housekeeping
    [00002136] 51         push ecx      ; make space for local [00002137] 6833210000 push 00002133 ; push DD
    [0000213c] e882f4ffff call 000015c3 ; call HHH(DD)
    [00002141] 83c404     add esp,+04
    [00002144] 8945fc     mov [ebp-04],eax
    [00002147] 837dfc00   cmp dword [ebp-04],+00
    [0000214b] 7402       jz 0000214f
    [0000214d] ebfe       jmp 0000214d
    [0000214f] 8b45fc     mov eax,[ebp-04]
    [00002152] 8be5       mov esp,ebp
    [00002154] 5d         pop ebp
    [00002155] c3         ret
    Size in bytes:(0035) [00002155]



    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to olcott on Sun May 4 20:07:24 2025
    On 5/4/25 4:06 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/4/2025 2:13 PM, Richard Heathfield wrote:
    On 04/05/2025 18:38, olcott wrote:

    <snip>

    int sum(int x, int y) { return x + y; }
    The mapping from sum(3,2) to sum 5 + 6 does not
    exist

    That's meaningless. Addition maps two ordinary numbers onto one
    number. The mapping of 3 + 2 is to 5, and the mapping of 5 + 6 is to
    11. sum(3,2) is the notation of a programming language's function
    call, not a mapping. Are you confusing 'computable function' with
    'programming language procedure'?

    for the same reason that the mapping from DD correctly
    simulated by HHH to DD(DD) does not exist.

    So you're saying that HHH cannot correctly simulate DD? I agree.


    Yes and int sum(int x, int y) { return x + y; }
    can not have sum(3,2) return the sum of 5 + 7 for the same reason.

    How does that happen?

    Or, are you just admitting that this is what you HHH is doing by your progjection


    Computable functions REPORT ON WHAT THEIR INPUT ACTUALLY SPECIFIES
    not some twisted delusion.


    But the definition of what the input actually specifies for a Halt
    Decider *IS* the behavior of the direct execution of the program it
    represents. There was no specification that the Function was computable,
    in fact, the question was, "Is it Computable?"

    The task of the programmer, is to try to figure out if we can make a
    finite algroithm compute it, to make it a Computable Function.

    Your problem is you just don't understand that not all functions we want
    to decide on are, in fact, computable, and that a major point of
    computation theory is to divide the space of Functions into Computable
    and non-Computable Functions.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to olcott on Sun May 4 20:15:31 2025
    On 5/4/25 12:21 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/3/2025 4:47 PM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 5/3/25 1:07 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/2/2025 8:16 PM, Mike Terry wrote:
    On 02/05/2025 06:06, Richard Heathfield wrote:
    On 02/05/2025 05:08, dbush wrote:
    On 5/1/2025 11:57 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/1/2025 9:40 PM, dbush wrote:

    <snip>

    So you changed the input.  Changing the input is not allowed. >>>>>>>>

    I never changed the input.

    Yes you did.  You hypothesize changing the code of HHH, and HHH is >>>>>> part of the input. So you changed the input.


    Agreed.

    Changing the input is not allowed.

    Wweellll...

    I have a very minor objection to that view, an objection that I've
    wrapped up into a thought experiment.

    Let us hypothesise the paradoxical existence of U, a universal
    decider. If we pass it an arbitrary P and an arbitrary D, it can
    defy Turing (we're just hypothesising, remember) and produce a
    correct result. Cool, right? The snag is that it's a black box. We
    can't see the code.

    We set it to work, and for years we use it to prove all manner of
    questions - PvNP, Collatz, Goldbach, Riemann, the lot - and it
    turns out always to be right. That's good, right?

    But then one fine day in 2038 we are finally allowed to see the
    source code for U, which is when we discover that the algorithm
    changes the input<<< in some small way. Does that invalidate the
    answers it has been providing for over a decade, thousands of
    answers that have / all/ been verified?

    Nobody would suggest that TMs aren't allowed to write to their tape!
    Of course, that's part of how they work, and is not what posters
    mean by PO "changing the input".


    I would argue that it doesn't. Provided U(P,D) correctly reports on
    the behaviour a P(D) call would produce, I would argue that that's
    all that matters, and the fact that U twiddles with the P and D
    tapes and turns them into P' and D' is irrelevant, as long as the
    result we get is that of P(D), not P'(D').

    Right.  What you're describing is business as usual for TMs.


    Let me show this graphically using a much simpler example - addition: >>>>>
    D: 1111111111+1111111
    P: add 'em up

    P(D)!

    D': 11111111111111111

    P has changed its input by changing the + to a 1 and erasing the
    last 1, and D' now holds the correct answer to the question
    originally posed on D.

    I would argue that this is /perfectly fine/, and that there is
    nothing in Turing's problem statement to forbid it. But of course
    we must be careful that, even if U does change its inputs to P' and
    D', it must still correctly answer the question P(D).

    Nothing wrong with that.

    BTW all the stuff above about universal deciders turns out to be
    irrelevant to your argument!  (It just seems a bit odd to choose a
    non- existant TM as an example when any other (existant) TM would do
    the job more clearly...)


    Of course, Mr Olcott's change is rather different, because by
    changing his HHH he's actually changing the behaviour of his DD -
    i.e. specifying a new U - but I see no reason why he can't do
    that / provided/ he can show that he always gets the correct
    answer. He has so far failed to do this with the original HHH, and
    now he has doubled his workload by giving himself another HHH to
    defend.

    Right - PO's H is free to rewrite the tape in whatever way it likes,
    provided in the end it gets the right answer.

    The "you're not allowed to change the input" charge means something
    quite different.

    TLDR:  Your talking about TMs writing to their tape as part of their
    normal operation.  Nothing wrong with that.  PO is effectively
    talking about changing the meaning of D [the input to H] half way
    through the Sipser quote.

    -----------------------------------------------------------------------------
    NTLFM:

    PO is trying to interpret Sipser's quote:

    --- Start Sipser quote
          If simulating halt decider H correctly simulates its input D >>>>       until H correctly determines that its simulated D would never >>>>       stop running unless aborted then

          H can abort its simulation of D and correctly report that D >>>>       specifies a non-halting sequence of configurations.
    --- End Sipser quote

    The following interpretation is ok:

         If H is given input D, and while simulating D gathers enough
         information to deduce that UTM(D) would never halt, then
         H can abort its simulation and decide D never halts.


    That is the same way that ChatGPT understands it.

    *ChatGPT Analyzes Simulating Termination Analyzer*
    https://www.researchgate.net/
    publication/385090708_ChatGPT_Analyzes_Simulating_Termination_Analyzer

    For DD/HHH

    int DD()
    {
       int Halt_Status = HHH(DD);
       if (Halt_Status)
         HERE: goto HERE;
       return Halt_Status;
    }

    HHH determines whether or not DD would halt
    if HHH would have been a pure simulator.

    But HHH is NOT a pure simulator, so that doesn't matter, at that HHH
    never answers

    Remember the input DD depend on the code of the decider it is defined
    to call, so your input changes.

    It seems, you are just so stupid as to not understand what a program
    actually is.


    ChatGPT DOES understand hypothetical possibilities
    and does understand that HHH computes the termination
    status of its input on the basis of these hypothetical
    possibilities.


    No, it just shows that it is as stupid as you, and believes (or
    pretends to in order to make you happy) your lies.

    If that was true then you would be able to point
    out its mistake. The only reason that you cannot
    do this is THAT IT MADE NO MISTAKE!




    You mean like the fact that the decider DOESN'T do a correct simulation,
    since it aborts before it gets to the final state, and thus the actual
    correct simulation of the input by an actual correct simulation wil show
    that the correct simuation of the input will halt?

    You began with the lie that your decider did a correct simulation, and
    thus you create a contradiction when you then talk about it aborting its simulation.

    A program can't both be a correct simulation and a partial simulation.

    Sorry, you seem to be too stupid to understand such a basic fact about programs.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to olcott on Sun May 4 20:12:03 2025
    On 5/4/25 11:54 AM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/3/2025 7:20 PM, Mike Terry wrote:
    On 03/05/2025 20:45, Richard Heathfield wrote:
    On 03/05/2025 19:50, Mike Terry wrote:
    On 03/05/2025 06:47, Richard Heathfield wrote:


    <snip>

    In passing, when I nailed down "TL;DR" I felt mildly guilty for
    scoring so few tersinosity points, but in return I must accuse you
    of undue obscurity.

    TL;DR appears to have attracted a certain currency, so okay, but...
    NTLFM? Really? "Seek and ye shall find", so I sought but shall
    findethed not. Most of my best guesses started 'Now The' and ended
    rhyming with RTFM, but none of those guesses jumped out as being
    self-evidently right. Would you care to translate?

    I admit to making it up, but all these (usenet?) abbreviations have
    to start somewhere, so I thought I would start a much needed new one!

    TL;DR = too long, didn't read,

    Yes, that chimes with my research, but...

    introducing a short summary for someone who hasn't the inclination/
    time to read a long (probably overly) verbose explanation.  At least
    that's how I've seen it used.  But then, how to introduce the
    verbose explanation?  I couldn't find anything for that, so I
    invented NTLFM; which means "Not Too Long For Me" !

    Ach! Of course.

    I'm looking forward to being a footnote in history when it catches
    on...

    In a footnote to the footnote for NTLFM I would add TOAST --- Too
    Obscure And Startlingly Terse.

    I kind of disagree with your mild denigration of the Linz (and
    similar) proofs.

    I wish to clarify that denigration was most certainly not my
    intent. There is, however, no doubt in my mind that while Linz is
    undoubtedly a worthy and indeed admirable computer scientist, his
    proof stands on giant shoulders. All I meant to say was that, were
    Linz's proof to lose its balance and take a tumble, it would not be
    the fault of the shoulders.

    Yeah, denigration was really the wrong word, as I know there was no
    bad intent anywhere.  Perhaps "downplaying" would have been what I
    was looking for.

    <nod />

    Ben pointed out there was confusion in the Linz proof with the
    labelling of states, and when I looked closely at the proof I a few
    years ago I recall thinking Linz had munged the conversion of
    (general) TM tape inputs to "H inputs" (which in Linz are binary
    representations of those tapes) when duplicating D's input.  Now I'm
    not sure about that, but can't motivate myself to get to the bottom
    of it, since either way, if it is a problem it's clear how it should
    be fixed, and the basis for the proof is not affected.

    The proof is both "very easy" conceptually [as witnessed by how many
    people join in here, quickly understanding how it works if they've
    not come across it before], and slightly fiddly due to the TM H
    needing to have a fixed tape alphabet which must be able to
    represent any TM as well as any tape input for that TM.  So there
    are certainly opportunities to miss details especially with a book
    aimed at those with a minimal maths background.  Really, the only
    aspect of the proof requiring careful thought is convincing yourself
    that the fiddliness has been handled ok, along with understanding
    the notation used...

    I don't see any scope for the proof actually being invalid, and PO
    certainly does not present any argument for it being invalid. He
    simply believes his H can give the right answer for his D, and
    that's the beginning and end of it all.  When he developed his
    x96utm, it became possible to actually run his code, and it became /
    manifestly/ clear his H gets the wrong answer for D.  But PO just
    doubles down and comes up with bizarre explanations for why he still
    thinks it is right when it is obviously wrong.

    As I re-read Linz /again/, two points stick out:

    "We cannot find the answer by simulating the action of M on w, say by
    performing it on a universal Turing machine, because there is no
    limit on the length of the computation. If M enters an infinite loop,
    then no matter how long we wait, we can never be sure that M is in
    fact in a loop. It may simply be a case of a very long computation.
    What we need is an algorithm that can determine the correct answer
    for any M and w by performing some
    analysis on the machine's description and the input. But as we
    now show, no such algorithm exists."

    "It is important to keep in mind what Theorem 12.1 says. It does not
    preclude solving the halting problem for specific cases; often we can
    tell by an analysis of M and w whether or not the Turing machine will
    halt. What the theorem says is that this cannot always be done; there
    is no algorithm that can make a correct decision for all WM and w."


    Both of these statements are self-evidently true, and both would
    appear to knock Mr O's HHH completely out of the water.

    I am conscious that you have already explained to me (twice!) that Mr
    O's approach is aimed not at overturning the overarching
    indecidability proof but a mere detail of Linz's proof.
    Unfortunately, your explanations have not managed to establish a firm
    root in what passes for my brain. This may be because I'm too dense
    to grok them, or possibly it's because your explanations are TOAST
    (see above).

    I generally think I post way too much, and tend to wander off topic
    with unnecessary background and so on, and probably I write too much
    from a "maths" perspective, because that's my background.  Not sure if
    I can change any of that! :)  Just ask if I use obscure notation or
    let me know if I'm going too fast/slow.  Part of the problem is I
    don't know your background and what things you're super familiar with.


    You have said, I think, that Olcott doesn't need a universal decider
    in order to prove his point. But a less ambitious decider doesn't
    contradict Linz's proof, surely? So once more for luck, what exactly
    would PO be establishing with his non-universal and impatient
    simulator if he could only get it to work?

    Yes.  PO is aiming to refute the /proof method/ that Linz (and
    similar) proofs use, i.e. to attack the /reasoning/ behind the proof.
    In effect, he is saying that his HHH/DD provide a counter-example to
    that reasoning.  His HHH/DD are not full halt deciders - they're /
    partial/ halt deciders but that would be enough.  I cover what a
    partial HD is below, and why it is enough for his argument [..if HHH/
    DD worked as originally claimed..]

    If he was successful with his HHH/DD programs, it would mean the Linz
    proof contained some logical error, and so the conclusion of the proof
    (the HP theorem) would not be warranted /by that proof/, We would have
    to cross that proof out of our Master Book Of Mathematical Theorems
    And Their Proofs! As there are other proofs of the theorem, the
    theorem itself could remain.

    It would be like the following scenario:  there are many alternative
    proofs of Pythagorus' Theorem, but let's imagine that one of them -
    the "MikeT" proof - is the first one taught to all school children
    across the world, and it's been that way for the last 50 years.
    Suddenly PO finds a flaw in that proof!  Sure, there are other proofs
    without that flaw so we still trust Pythagorus' Theorem, but we're not
    going to continue teaching children an incorrect proof of it, right.
    So finding such a flaw would force many changes on our education
    system and be highly interesting in its own right.

    This doesn't explain exactly how PO's HHH/DD would "refute" the Linz
    proof, so that's what the rest of the post tries to do.


    The two proofs are isomorphic to each other.
    DD correctly emulated by HHH cannot possibly reach its own
    emulated "return instruction" final halt state.

    And where do you get that the criteria is based on "correctly emulated
    by HHH?"


    ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ correctly simulated by embedded_H cannot possibly
    reach its own simulated final halt state ⟨Ĥ.qn⟩

    But embedded_H doesn't correctly emulate its input, as neither does H,
    which it behaves identically to, which you have shown to abort its
    emulation and transition to the non-halting output state.


    BTW, when I refer to "the Linz proof" it is purely because the Linz
    book is apparently the one that PO has access to, and when he started
    posting here he claimed to have refuted the "Linz" proof that appears
    in that book.  As you suspect, the proof is nothing to do with Linz
    other than appearing in his book!

    That Linz uses explicit state transitions transforms
    the alternative vague proofs into an exactingly precise
    formal specification.

    Which you don't do correctly, as no where does Linz say his decider uses correct emulatiion.


    It also appears I expect in some form in most computer science books
    covering computation theory, because it's so well known.  Hmm, not
    sure who discovered it, but it would be one of the big guys like
    Turing, Church, Kleene,... all doing related work in the early days of
    the field.

    ----------------------

    So to say what PO's code would refute, I need to explain exactly how
    the Linz proof works.  Sorry if you already perfectly clear on that!


    When Ĥ is applied to ⟨Ĥ⟩
    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qy ∞
      or
    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qn

    (a) Ĥ copies its input ⟨Ĥ⟩
    (b) Ĥ invokes embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩
    (c) embedded_H simulates ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩

    ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ correctly simulated by embedded_H cannot possibly
    reach its own simulated final halt state ⟨Ĥ.qn⟩

    And since embedded_H doesn't even try to completely simulate its input,
    but stops and goes to Qn, just like H does, means you logic is just a lie


    Professor Sipser never took the time to understand
    the simple idea of recursive simulation.



    No, YOU don't understand that embedded_H does exactly the same thing as
    H, and that was based on the rules established when H was initially
    designed, and can't change after that.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Ben Bacarisse@21:1/5 to Richard Heathfield on Mon May 5 01:54:44 2025
    Richard Heathfield <rjh@cpax.org.uk> writes:

    On 04/05/2025 19:57, Mike Terry wrote:
    ...
      [Hmm, I think that was Malcolm McLean who hasn't posted for a couple of
    years.]

    I hope he's okay. (Malcolm and I have crossed many swords and we rarely agreed, but I recall him being a most well-mannered and personable
    fellow.

    He was very seriously ill the last time he posted in comp.lang.c. I
    fear the worst. None of his GIT projects have had any activity for
    nearly a year.

    --
    Ben.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Ben Bacarisse@21:1/5 to Mike Terry on Mon May 5 02:04:38 2025
    Mike Terry <news.dead.person.stones@darjeeling.plus.com> writes:
    ...
    As explained above, UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩) simulates Ĥ run with input Ĥ (having the
    same halting behaviour) and Ĥ run with input Ĥ HALTS. So embedded_H does not "gather enough information to deduce that UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩) would never
    halt". THAT IS JUST A FANTASY THAT YOU HAVE.

    UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩) DOES halt, so embedded_H can't possibly gather information
    that genuinely implies it DOESN'T halt. The explanation is obvious: embedded_H gathers information that *YOU* believe implies that UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩)
    would never halt, but *YOU ARE SIMPLY WRONG*.

    He used to claim that false ("does not halt") was the correct answer,
    /even though/ the computation in question halts! Those were simpler
    days. Of course cranks will never admit to having been wrong about
    anything other than a detail or two, so anyone who could be bothered
    could try to get him to retract that old claim.

    I know you'll not understand what I've just said, because it is all too abstract and you don't understand the concepts involved, and consequently
    you probably don't agree with my Sipser interpretation, and even if you did
    I doubt you would be able to work out its consequences. So I don't expect
    to be posting any further.

    Not you then! I sympathise, though my reason for not talking to him is
    his unacceptable insults.

    --
    Ben.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mike Terry@21:1/5 to Richard Heathfield on Mon May 5 05:00:39 2025
    On 04/05/2025 22:18, Richard Heathfield wrote:
    On 04/05/2025 19:57, Mike Terry wrote:

    <snip>

    It was more how much maths background you have
    + familiarity with HP proof you have.

    Sorry for the noise, then.

    Very little. I rattled through the first ten years easily enough, but I hit a hard wall (integration
    by parts) and never really recovered. Such mathematics as I have picked up since has mostly been
    through popularisers such as Martin Gardner, Ian Stewart, and Douglas Hofstadter. I think it was in
    Hofstadter that I first learned of the Halting Problem.

    <snip>

    What's to stop the partial decider from deciding pseudorandomly? For example: hashing the input
    tapes and deciding according to the hash modulo 2? This would:

    1) always decide (as required);
    2) sometimes get it right (as required);
    3) sometimes get it wrong (as required if it's to be only 'partial');

    No, partial halt deciders [*PHD*s] aren't supposed to get it wrong!

    We must distinguish carefully between PHDs and PhDs (although, come to think of it, PhDs aren't
    supposed to get it wrong either).

    But... okay, I'll read on...

    If they don't know the answer they're supposed to never answer, but if they do answer [i.e. HALTS
    or NEVER_HALTS] it must be right.  We could define PHDs so that they have a 3rd answer DONT_KNOW,
    but assuming we still allow them to never answer I don't see that the DONT_KNOW answer adds much.
    [the new PHDs would be equivalent to my definition]

    If they never answer, how long do we wait for nothing to happen?

    How much time do you have to invest in getting an answer? You could wait 1 day, and if there's no
    answer count it as a don't know.

    You could upgrade from a PHD to one of those new-fangled HDs that are "guaranteed to answer". But
    then how long do we wait for our guaranteed answer? Again it depends how much time we're willing to
    invest - in real life we have to set a timeout - e.g. 1 day - and if it's not answered by then we
    move, accepting that we still don't know! Is the HD really worth the upgrade cost? :)

    These sorts of Computation Theory concepts are theoretical in nature. We already have concepts like
    TM "Language Accepters" which accept the precisely the strings of a given Language. That is, the TM
    starts with the test string on its input tape, and halts in a final state precisely when the string
    belongs to the language. Strings not in the language may result in the TM never halting [or, it may
    be allowed to halt in a /non-final/ state].


    If we add a DONT_KNOW answer, and then insist the PHD must halt with one of the 3 answers, I think
    that would be a different concept, because a PHD might be searching for a particular test
    condition and never find it.  That would be an infinite loop, which I consider reasonable, but if
    it is forced instead to decide DONT_KNOW in finite time, then such a potentially unending search
    would be excluded.  So I think we have a different concept of PHD now.

    I've got my wallet in my hand, but I'm not quite ready yet to buy a PHD that doesn't answer.
    DONT_KNOW is conceptually easier to swallow (even though the mileage doesn't look all that great).

    Actually, while I've talked about PHDs which are not allowed to decide incorrectly, in fact for
    PO's purposes it wouldn't matter if we allowed PHDs to decide inputs incorrectly like you're
    imagining. We could be talking about a new type of TM, maybe call it a "Putative PHD"  [*PPHD*]
    which takes the (P,I) input, and may decide HALTS/NEVER_HALTS or never decide, and PPHDs have no
    requirement to answer correctly.  [PO's HHH is really a PPHD, not a PHD as it sometimes answers
    incorrectly]

    Which raises the question of why he bothers.

    PO does not acknowledge that his HHH gives the wrong answer!


    Everything I've said about PHD's in relation to PO's claims to refute Linz, would work equally
    well with PPHDs!  That's because all that really matters for PO is that the ONE SPECIFIC INPUT
    (<H^>,<H^>) must be decided correctly.  It's still the case, even for PPHDs, that the reasoning
    used in the Linz proof implies that if H is a PPHD, H will NOT decide input (<H^>,<H^>) correctly.
    So if PO could provides even a PPHD H that decides (<H^>,<H^>) /correctly/ that shows a problem
    with the Linz proof logic.  [Of course, PO cannot provide such an H.]

    Well, it's not hard. Scaffolding first (not for publication):

    1) he writes H(P,D), which hashes P and D (md5 hash, say? Or even just add up the bits!) and returns
    mod 2 of the result, interpreting 0 as 'loops' and 1 as 'halts'
    2) he waves Turing's magic wand and sees whether he gets the result he needs for (<H^><H^>).
    3) if so, great! But if not, he reverses the meanings of 0 and 1.
    4) remove from the docs all signs of fiddling the mod 2 meanings.

    Having 'tuned' his PPHD, he can now publish and claim his place in history.

    Ah, that's not what I thought you were thinking.

    What you're suggesting doesn't work! Remember the order - first H is fixed, then H^ is created
    based on H. H will fail when deciding halting for input (<H^>,<H^>).

    So now you want to edit the code of H to make a new TM which we'll call H2, so that H2 gives the
    opposite answer to H for any input. That's great - H2 will correctly decide input (<H^>,<H^>). You
    see - there's nothing "undecidable" or "paradoxical" about input (<H^>,<H^>) per se. H^(<H^>) has
    an unambiguous behaviour; either it halts or it never halts and either way that dictates the answer
    that a halt-decider must give. H gives the wrong answer, but your H2 gets it right.

    As I said, that's great, except... the HP proof doesn't claim that H2 will decide (<H^>,<H^>)
    incorrectly! What it says is that H2 will decide (<H2^>,<H2^>) incorrectly. To build H2^ we need
    to follow the Linz recipe again, but starting from H2 instead of H, so H2^ is different from H^.

    And what do you know? When we ask H2 whether H2^(<H2^>) halts, it will give the wrong answer. With
    a little thought we see that the original H will give the right answer for input (<H2^>,<H2^>), but
    again that's not contradicting anything in the HP proof, so no help to PO.

    PO likes to imagine that there's something Wrong with H^ or H2^ which warrants them being excluded
    from HP or treated differently re. definition of halting etc.. Normally he does that by pretending
    that H and H1 are "one machine", and "whichever decision that machine makes it will be wrong!!", so
    we have Pathelogical Self Refernce or some kind of paradox or what not. Thinking clearly as above
    (and giving distinct names for distinct objects helps) makes it clear he's just muddling things up.


    Mike.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Fred. Zwarts@21:1/5 to All on Mon May 5 08:41:53 2025
    Op 04.mei.2025 om 22:06 schreef olcott:
    On 5/4/2025 2:13 PM, Richard Heathfield wrote:
    On 04/05/2025 18:38, olcott wrote:

    <snip>

    int sum(int x, int y) { return x + y; }
    The mapping from sum(3,2) to sum 5 + 6 does not
    exist

    That's meaningless. Addition maps two ordinary numbers onto one
    number. The mapping of 3 + 2 is to 5, and the mapping of 5 + 6 is to
    11. sum(3,2) is the notation of a programming language's function
    call, not a mapping. Are you confusing 'computable function' with
    'programming language procedure'?

    for the same reason that the mapping from DD correctly
    simulated by HHH to DD(DD) does not exist.

    So you're saying that HHH cannot correctly simulate DD? I agree.


    Yes and int sum(int x, int y) { return x + y; }
    can not have sum(3,2) return the sum of 5 + 7 for the same reason.

    Computable functions

    should

    REPORT ON WHAT THEIR INPUT ACTUALLY SPECIFIES

    Erroneous functions (such as HHH) compute something else, e.g. by using
    a non-input.

    not some twisted delusion.


    The dream that HHH does not abort is such a twisted delusion, used by
    the erroneous HHH.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mikko@21:1/5 to olcott on Mon May 5 10:25:53 2025
    On 2025-05-04 17:30:25 +0000, olcott said:

    On 5/4/2025 11:21 AM, Richard Heathfield wrote:
    On 04/05/2025 17:06, olcott wrote:

    <snip>

    They simply guess that because DD(DD) halts that
    DD correctly simulated by HHH must also halt.

    It's not a guess. If direct execution halts, so must the simulation.

    _DD()
    [00002133] 55 push ebp ; housekeeping
    [00002134] 8bec mov ebp,esp ; housekeeping
    [00002136] 51 push ecx ; make space for local
    [00002137] 6833210000 push 00002133 ; push DD
    [0000213c] e882f4ffff call 000015c3 ; call HHH(DD)
    [00002141] 83c404 add esp,+04
    [00002144] 8945fc mov [ebp-04],eax
    [00002147] 837dfc00 cmp dword [ebp-04],+00
    [0000214b] 7402 jz 0000214f
    [0000214d] ebfe jmp 0000214d
    [0000214f] 8b45fc mov eax,[ebp-04]
    [00002152] 8be5 mov esp,ebp
    [00002154] 5d pop ebp
    [00002155] c3 ret
    Size in bytes:(0035) [00002155]

    Maybe you are confused between halting (reaching
    a final halt state and terminating normally)
    with stopping running for any reason such as
    an aborted emulation. *THEY ARE NOT THE SAME*

    Apparently you are confused between non-halting
    (impossibility of reaching a treminal state)
    with stopping for any reason other than reaching
    a terminal state. *THEY ARE NOT THE SAME*

    That an execution is aborted before the computation has reached
    its temrminal state does not mean that a full execution of that
    computation does not reach a terminal state.

    --
    Mikko

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Heathfield@21:1/5 to Ben Bacarisse on Mon May 5 09:21:34 2025
    On 05/05/2025 01:54, Ben Bacarisse wrote:
    Richard Heathfield <rjh@cpax.org.uk> writes:

    On 04/05/2025 19:57, Mike Terry wrote:
    ...
      [Hmm, I think that was Malcolm McLean who hasn't posted for a couple of >>> years.]

    I hope he's okay. (Malcolm and I have crossed many swords and we rarely
    agreed, but I recall him being a most well-mannered and personable
    fellow.

    He was very seriously ill the last time he posted in comp.lang.c. I
    fear the worst. None of his GIT projects have had any activity for
    nearly a year.

    Perhaps the biggest problem with a text medium is that sometimes
    there are no right words.

    --
    Richard Heathfield
    Email: rjh at cpax dot org dot uk
    "Usenet is a strange place" - dmr 29 July 1999
    Sig line 4 vacant - apply within

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mikko@21:1/5 to dbush on Mon May 5 11:54:32 2025
    On 2025-05-04 16:57:06 +0000, dbush said:

    On 5/4/2025 12:06 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/3/2025 4:28 PM, dbush wrote:
    On 5/3/2025 3:45 PM, Richard Heathfield wrote:

    I am conscious that you have already explained to me (twice!) that Mr
    O's approach is aimed not at overturning the overarching indecidability >>>> proof but a mere detail of Linz's proof. Unfortunately, your
    explanations have not managed to establish a firm root in what passes
    for my brain. This may be because I'm too dense to grok them, or
    possibly it's because your explanations are TOAST (see above).

    You have said, I think, that Olcott doesn't need a universal decider in >>>> order to prove his point. But a less ambitious decider doesn't
    contradict Linz's proof, surely? So once more for luck, what exactly
    would PO be establishing with his non-universal and impatient simulator >>>> if he could only get it to work?

    The core issue is that PO, despise being nearly 70 and having worked as
    a programmer, fundamentally doesn't understand proof by contradiction.


    The actual issue is the NO ONE here (or perhaps anywhere)
    sufficiently understands the key details about
    COMPUTING THE MAPPING FROM AN INPUT TO AN OUTPUT.

    Many here know that a mapping from the input must be
    computed.

    False. There is no requirement that a mapping is computable. The
    halting function is one such mapping, as Linz and others have proved
    and you have *explictly* agreed is correct.


    What they don't know are ALL of the tiny
    detailed steps required to compute this mapping.


    And if the mapping isn't computable, like the halting function, there
    are no such steps.

    Either so or there is an infinte number of steps. An infinite input can
    be given to a Turing machine but a Turing machine cannot determine
    whether its input is infinite.

    They simply guess that because DD(DD) halts that
    DD correctly simulated by HHH must also halt.

    A correct simulation is stipulated to be one that exactly matches the behavior of the machine to be simulated.

    DD is not correctly simulated by HHH, as the last instruction simulated
    is not simulated correctly, because the x86 language requires any
    executed instruction other than a HLT to be followed by the execution
    of the next instruction.

    We also know that "DD correctly simulated by HHH" is PO-speak for
    "Replacing the code of HHH with an unconditional simulator and
    subsequently running HHH(DD)", as you have agreed and given permission
    to replace the former with the later.

    This means that you're changing the input.

    Changing the input is not allowed.


    They cannot provide these detailed steps of the
    execution trace of each machine instruction showing
    exactly how DD correctly emulated by HHH halts
    BECAUSE THEY KNOW THAT THEY ARE WRONG AND ONLY PLAYING HEAD GAMES.

    That you don't understand requirements doesn't make it a head game.

    However, the same practical advice applies to both: don't participate.

    --
    Mikko

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Heathfield@21:1/5 to Mike Terry on Mon May 5 09:55:05 2025
    On 05/05/2025 05:00, Mike Terry wrote:
    On 04/05/2025 22:18, Richard Heathfield wrote:


    <snip>

    [Of course, PO cannot provide such an H.]

    Well, it's not hard. Scaffolding first (not for publication):

    1) he writes H(P,D), which hashes P and D (md5 hash, say? Or
    even just add up the bits!) and returns mod 2 of the result,
    interpreting 0 as 'loops' and 1 as 'halts'
    2) he waves Turing's magic wand and sees whether he gets the
    result he needs for (<H^><H^>).
    3) if so, great! But if not, he reverses the meanings of 0 and 1.
    4) remove from the docs all signs of fiddling the mod 2 meanings.

    Having 'tuned' his PPHD, he can now publish and claim his place
    in history.

    Ah, that's not what I thought you were thinking.

    Why do I get the feeling that I'm not quite as clever as you
    thought I was? :-)

    What you're suggesting doesn't work!  Remember the order

    We choose a door /first/, and /then/ Monty shows us a goat...

    I have absolutely no doubt that you're right and that my 'hack'
    is ill-considered, but my eyes are starting to bleed, so instead
    of point-to-pointing you I'm going to bail and retreat to my
    LaTeX coal face.

    <snip>

    PO likes to imagine that there's something Wrong with H^ or H2^
    which warrants them being excluded from HP or treated differently
    re. definition of halting etc..  Normally he does that by
    pretending that H and H1 are "one machine", and "whichever
    decision that machine makes it will be wrong!!", so we have
    Pathelogical Self Refernce or some kind of paradox or what not.
    Thinking clearly as above (and giving distinct names for distinct
    objects helps) makes it clear he's just muddling things up.

    Mike, thy name is Sisyphus.

    --
    Richard Heathfield
    Email: rjh at cpax dot org dot uk
    "Usenet is a strange place" - dmr 29 July 1999
    Sig line 4 vacant - apply within

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to olcott on Mon May 5 07:09:03 2025
    On 5/5/25 12:57 AM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/3/2025 7:20 PM, Mike Terry wrote:
    On 03/05/2025 20:45, Richard Heathfield wrote:
    On 03/05/2025 19:50, Mike Terry wrote:
    On 03/05/2025 06:47, Richard Heathfield wrote:


    <snip>

    In passing, when I nailed down "TL;DR" I felt mildly guilty for
    scoring so few tersinosity points, but in return I must accuse you
    of undue obscurity.

    TL;DR appears to have attracted a certain currency, so okay, but...
    NTLFM? Really? "Seek and ye shall find", so I sought but shall
    findethed not. Most of my best guesses started 'Now The' and ended
    rhyming with RTFM, but none of those guesses jumped out as being
    self-evidently right. Would you care to translate?

    I admit to making it up, but all these (usenet?) abbreviations have
    to start somewhere, so I thought I would start a much needed new one!

    TL;DR = too long, didn't read,

    Yes, that chimes with my research, but...

    introducing a short summary for someone who hasn't the inclination/
    time to read a long (probably overly) verbose explanation.  At least
    that's how I've seen it used.  But then, how to introduce the
    verbose explanation?  I couldn't find anything for that, so I
    invented NTLFM; which means "Not Too Long For Me" !

    Ach! Of course.

    I'm looking forward to being a footnote in history when it catches
    on...

    In a footnote to the footnote for NTLFM I would add TOAST --- Too
    Obscure And Startlingly Terse.

    I kind of disagree with your mild denigration of the Linz (and
    similar) proofs.

    I wish to clarify that denigration was most certainly not my
    intent. There is, however, no doubt in my mind that while Linz is
    undoubtedly a worthy and indeed admirable computer scientist, his
    proof stands on giant shoulders. All I meant to say was that, were
    Linz's proof to lose its balance and take a tumble, it would not be
    the fault of the shoulders.

    Yeah, denigration was really the wrong word, as I know there was no
    bad intent anywhere.  Perhaps "downplaying" would have been what I
    was looking for.

    <nod />

    Ben pointed out there was confusion in the Linz proof with the
    labelling of states, and when I looked closely at the proof I a few
    years ago I recall thinking Linz had munged the conversion of
    (general) TM tape inputs to "H inputs" (which in Linz are binary
    representations of those tapes) when duplicating D's input.  Now I'm
    not sure about that, but can't motivate myself to get to the bottom
    of it, since either way, if it is a problem it's clear how it should
    be fixed, and the basis for the proof is not affected.

    The proof is both "very easy" conceptually [as witnessed by how many
    people join in here, quickly understanding how it works if they've
    not come across it before], and slightly fiddly due to the TM H
    needing to have a fixed tape alphabet which must be able to
    represent any TM as well as any tape input for that TM.  So there
    are certainly opportunities to miss details especially with a book
    aimed at those with a minimal maths background.  Really, the only
    aspect of the proof requiring careful thought is convincing yourself
    that the fiddliness has been handled ok, along with understanding
    the notation used...

    I don't see any scope for the proof actually being invalid, and PO
    certainly does not present any argument for it being invalid. He
    simply believes his H can give the right answer for his D, and
    that's the beginning and end of it all.  When he developed his
    x96utm, it became possible to actually run his code, and it became /
    manifestly/ clear his H gets the wrong answer for D.  But PO just
    doubles down and comes up with bizarre explanations for why he still
    thinks it is right when it is obviously wrong.

    As I re-read Linz /again/, two points stick out:

    "We cannot find the answer by simulating the action of M on w, say by
    performing it on a universal Turing machine, because there is no
    limit on the length of the computation. If M enters an infinite loop,
    then no matter how long we wait, we can never be sure that M is in
    fact in a loop. It may simply be a case of a very long computation.
    What we need is an algorithm that can determine the correct answer
    for any M and w by performing some
    analysis on the machine's description and the input. But as we
    now show, no such algorithm exists."

    "It is important to keep in mind what Theorem 12.1 says. It does not
    preclude solving the halting problem for specific cases; often we can
    tell by an analysis of M and w whether or not the Turing machine will
    halt. What the theorem says is that this cannot always be done; there
    is no algorithm that can make a correct decision for all WM and w."


    Both of these statements are self-evidently true, and both would
    appear to knock Mr O's HHH completely out of the water.

    I am conscious that you have already explained to me (twice!) that Mr
    O's approach is aimed not at overturning the overarching
    indecidability proof but a mere detail of Linz's proof.
    Unfortunately, your explanations have not managed to establish a firm
    root in what passes for my brain. This may be because I'm too dense
    to grok them, or possibly it's because your explanations are TOAST
    (see above).

    I generally think I post way too much, and tend to wander off topic
    with unnecessary background and so on, and probably I write too much
    from a "maths" perspective, because that's my background.

    Not so much programming background?

    Not sure if I can change any of that! :)  Just ask if I use obscure
    notation or let me know if I'm going too fast/slow.  Part of the
    problem is I don't know your background and what things you're super
    familiar with.


    You have said, I think, that Olcott doesn't need a universal decider
    in order to prove his point. But a less ambitious decider doesn't
    contradict Linz's proof, surely? So once more for luck, what exactly
    would PO be establishing with his non-universal and impatient
    simulator if he could only get it to work?

    Yes.  PO is aiming to refute the /proof method/ that Linz (and
    similar) proofs use, i.e. to attack the /reasoning/ behind the proof.
    In effect, he is saying that his HHH/DD provide a counter-example to
    that reasoning.  His HHH/DD are not full halt deciders - they're /
    partial/ halt deciders but that would be enough.

    Or we could call them their software engineering name
    of "termination analyzers".

    But "Termination analyzers" are not "partial halt deciders", in fact the Termination Analyzation problem is a tougher problem than Halt Deciding
    because it needs to decide if the given algorithm will halt for *ALL*
    inputs.

    It still requires it to be able to process EVERY possible input to be
    totally correct.

    It is just that the field was created after the Halting Problem was
    solved, and thus we know that no such program exists, so we know we are
    always talking about partial deciders, and talk about what sort of
    limitd domain they work under.



     I cover what a partial HD is

    And since it doesn't get it one input correctly, it isn't even that.

    below, and why it is enough for his argument [..if HHH/DD worked as
    originally claimed..]

    If he was successful with his HHH/DD programs, it would mean the Linz
    proof contained some logical error, and so the conclusion of the proof
    (the HP theorem) would not be warranted /by that proof/, We would have
    to cross that proof out of our Master Book Of Mathematical Theorems
    And Their Proofs! As there are other proofs of the theorem, the
    theorem itself could remain.

    It would be like the following scenario:  there are many alternative
    proofs of Pythagorus' Theorem, but let's imagine that one of them -
    the "MikeT" proof - is the first one taught to all school children
    across the world, and it's been that way for the last 50 years.
    Suddenly PO finds a flaw in that proof!  Sure, there are other proofs
    without that flaw so we still trust Pythagorus' Theorem, but we're not
    going to continue teaching children an incorrect proof of it, right.
    So finding such a flaw would force many changes on our education
    system and be highly interesting in its own right.

    This doesn't explain exactly how PO's HHH/DD would "refute" the Linz
    proof, so that's what the rest of the post tries to do.

    BTW, when I refer to "the Linz proof" it is purely because the Linz
    book is apparently the one that PO has access to, and when he started
    posting here he claimed to have refuted the "Linz" proof that appears
    in that book.  As you suspect, the proof is nothing to do with Linz
    other than appearing in his book!  It also appears I expect in some
    form in most computer science books covering computation theory,
    because it's so well known.  Hmm, not sure who discovered it, but it
    would be one of the big guys like Turing, Church, Kleene,... all doing
    related work in the early days of the field.

    ----------------------

    So to say what PO's code would refute, I need to explain exactly how
    the Linz proof works.  Sorry if you already perfectly clear on that!

    Say I give you a halt decider H.  H is a TM, and following the
    mechanical instructions in Linz, you would be able to create from H a
    new TM H^.  Basically you start with the H I gave, and edit it:

    1) add some initial code that runs before my H gets control - that
    code duplicates whatever input is on the tape when it is invoked, so
    that if the initial tape contained "hello\0" the modified tape needs
    to end up "hello\0hello\0".

    2) modify the halt states that my H used to indicate halt/non-halting
    when deciding its input:
        -  the state H uses to indicate its input halts is replaced with a >> tight loop
        -  the state H uses to indicate its input fails to halt is
    replaced with halt state.
           Hmm, that state was a halt state in the H I gave you, so
    actually there's no change
           for that state.

    So, I gave you H, and you've modified it to produce a new TM H^.  The
    essence of the Linz proof is that the logic of how H^ works /
    guarantees/ that when we ask my H whether your H^ halts when run
    against a tape containing the TM-description of H^, my H will give the
    wrong answer! So, my H never was a halt decider after all, because it
    gets a wrong answer for this particular input.  Halt deciders must
    decide halting correctly for /every/ input i.e. every combination of
    P,I  [P is the TM, I the input tape].

    [I'm not explaining the proof of /why/ H will get the answer wrong.
    That's important of course and is in Linz and other accounts of the
    proof, but it's not really relevant to understanding what PO is trying
    to achieve.]

    This next bit might be a missing key for you...    Looking at the
    above, we started by me giving you a "halt decider" H.  What if I only
    gave you a lesser achievement: a "partial halt decider" that correctly
    decides halting for certain (P,I) inputs, but fails to halt for all
    the rest? The answer is the same logic still applies, but the
    conclusion is slightly different:

    -  I give you a /partial/ HD  H
    -  You follow the same instructions to create the new TM, H^
    -  The same reasoning of the Linz proof shows that my H does not
    correctly decide halting
        for the case of TM H^ running against input <H^>
        a)  If H decides HALTS, we can show H^(<H^>) never halts
        b)  If H decides NEVER_HALTS, we can show H^(<H^>) halts
        c)  If H fails to decide (i.e. it loops) then H^(<H^>) never halts >>         This last possibility is new, because H is only a partial halt
    decider

    Now we can look at what PO claims to have: a *partial* halt decider H,
    which CORRECTLY decides its corresponding input (<H^>,<H^>).
    Specifically, he claims his H decides NEVER_HALTS, and that indeed
    H^(<H^>) never halts.  This contradicts the Linz proof /reasoning/
    which lead to (b) above.

    Since the Linz proof reasoning would have been shown to reach a false
    conclusion [in the case of PO's HHH/DD programs], the reasoning must
    be wrong somewhere, and if the reasoning is wrong it can't be used in
    the Linz proof.  It is ok here that H is only a partial halt decider -
    in fact the above only requires that PO's H correctly decides the one
    H^(<H^>) case to get the contradiction.

    Er, that's it!

    Just as a reminder I'll repeat the final outcome of all this:

    -  PO's H does decide NEVER_HALTS for TM H^ running with input <H^>.
    -  PO's H^ running with input <H^> in fact halts, in line with Linz
    logic (b) above.

    A final observation - nothing in this post is anything to do with
    "simulation".  That comes later looking at how PO's H supposedly works... >>
    Mike.




    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to olcott on Mon May 5 21:23:45 2025
    On 5/4/25 9:23 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/4/2025 8:04 PM, Ben Bacarisse wrote:
    Mike Terry <news.dead.person.stones@darjeeling.plus.com> writes:
    ...
    As explained above, UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩) simulates Ĥ run with input Ĥ (having
    the
    same halting behaviour) and Ĥ run with input Ĥ HALTS.  So embedded_H
    does
    not "gather enough information to deduce that UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩) would never
    halt".  THAT IS JUST A FANTASY THAT YOU HAVE.

    UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩) DOES halt, so embedded_H can't possibly gather information
    that genuinely implies it DOESN'T halt.  The explanation is obvious:
    embedded_H gathers information that *YOU* believe implies that
    UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩)
    would never halt, but *YOU ARE SIMPLY WRONG*.

    He used to claim that false ("does not halt") was the correct answer,
    /even though/ the computation in question halts!  Those were simpler
    days.  Of course cranks will never admit to having been wrong about
    anything other than a detail or two, so anyone who could be bothered
    could try to get him to retract that old claim.


    <MIT Professor Sipser agreed to ONLY these verbatim words 10/13/2022>
        If simulating halt decider H correctly simulates its input D
        until H correctly determines that its simulated D would never
        stop running unless aborted then

        H can abort its simulation of D and correctly report that D
        specifies a non-halting sequence of configurations.
    </MIT Professor Sipser agreed to ONLY these verbatim words 10/13/2022>

    When Ĥ is applied to ⟨Ĥ⟩
    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qy ∞
    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qn

    In other words embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ is correct to
    reject its input if

    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* UTM ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qy ∞
    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* UTM ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qn
    Would not halt.

    Nope, because that isn't the input that it was given. Ĥ doesn't use a
    UTM (unless H is actually such a machine). H is allowed to abort its
    emulaiton if UTM (Ĥ) (Ĥ) would never halt, but UTM (Ĥ) (Ĥ) sees that
    Ĥ (Ĥ) ⊢* embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qn since embedded_H is the same as H
    and your H does do that, and thus H never had the needed proof to do
    that, so it made an error.

    You are just showing that you idea of "logic" is based on just lying
    about what words mean.


    I know you'll not understand what I've just said, because it is all too
    abstract and you don't understand the concepts involved, and
    consequently
    you probably don't agree with my Sipser interpretation, and even if
    you did
    I doubt you would be able to work out its consequences.  So I don't
    expect
    to be posting any further.

    Not you then!  I sympathise, though my reason for not talking to him is
    his unacceptable insults.




    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to olcott on Mon May 5 21:27:58 2025
    On 5/4/25 11:04 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/4/2025 9:58 PM, dbush wrote:
    On 5/4/2025 9:23 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/4/2025 8:04 PM, Ben Bacarisse wrote:
    Mike Terry <news.dead.person.stones@darjeeling.plus.com> writes:
    ...
    As explained above, UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩) simulates Ĥ run with input Ĥ >>>>> (having the
    same halting behaviour) and Ĥ run with input Ĥ HALTS.  So
    embedded_H does
    not "gather enough information to deduce that UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩) would never
    halt".  THAT IS JUST A FANTASY THAT YOU HAVE.

    UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩) DOES halt, so embedded_H can't possibly gather >>>>> information
    that genuinely implies it DOESN'T halt.  The explanation is obvious: >>>>> embedded_H gathers information that *YOU* believe implies that
    UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩)
    would never halt, but *YOU ARE SIMPLY WRONG*.

    He used to claim that false ("does not halt") was the correct answer,
    /even though/ the computation in question halts!  Those were simpler
    days.  Of course cranks will never admit to having been wrong about
    anything other than a detail or two, so anyone who could be bothered
    could try to get him to retract that old claim.


    <MIT Professor Sipser agreed to ONLY these verbatim words 10/13/2022>
         If simulating halt decider H correctly simulates its input D
         until H correctly determines that its simulated D would never
         stop running unless aborted then

         H can abort its simulation of D and correctly report that D
         specifies a non-halting sequence of configurations.
    </MIT Professor Sipser agreed to ONLY these verbatim words 10/13/2022>


    And you *CONTINUE* to lie by implying that Sipser agrees with you when
    it's been repeated proven that he does not:

    On Monday, March 6, 2023 at 2:41:27 PM UTC-5, Ben Bacarisse wrote:
    I exchanged emails with him about this. He does not agree with
    anything
    substantive that PO has written. I won't quote him, as I don't have
    permission, but he was, let's say... forthright, in his reply to me.

    This demonstrates a reckless disregard for the truth on your part.

    When Ĥ is applied to ⟨Ĥ⟩
    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qy ∞
    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qn

    In other words embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ is correct to
    reject its input if

    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* UTM ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qy ∞
    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* UTM ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qn
    Would not halt.


    In other words, you change the input.

    Changing the input is not allowed.

    D *WOULD NEVER STOP RUNNING UNLESS*
    indicates that professor Sipser was agreeing
    to hypotheticals AS *NOT CHANGING THE INPUT*

    Right, the hypothecial H that doesn't abort still gets the input that
    calls the H that does what H will actually do.


    You are taking
    *WOULD NEVER STOP RUNNING UNLESS*
    to mean *NEVER STOPS RUNNING* that is incorrect.



    No, ot means that if *THIS* input would never stop running when actually correcttly emulated or executed. THIS input calls the actual H that
    aborts and goes to qn, and thus THIS input will halt.

    Your problem is you don't understand that the input program includes BY
    COPY (and not just by name reference) the decider that it is supposed to refute, and thus NEVER CHANGES when you think about alternate behavior
    of the decider, which actually is creating a new alternate decider.

    You are just proving your ignorance of the rules of the game you are
    playing, and it seem you hav disqualified yourself by breaking them.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to olcott on Tue May 6 07:23:39 2025
    On 5/5/25 10:36 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/5/2025 8:23 PM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 5/4/25 9:23 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/4/2025 8:04 PM, Ben Bacarisse wrote:
    Mike Terry <news.dead.person.stones@darjeeling.plus.com> writes:
    ...
    As explained above, UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩) simulates Ĥ run with input Ĥ >>>>> (having the
    same halting behaviour) and Ĥ run with input Ĥ HALTS.  So
    embedded_H does
    not "gather enough information to deduce that UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩) would never
    halt".  THAT IS JUST A FANTASY THAT YOU HAVE.

    UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩) DOES halt, so embedded_H can't possibly gather >>>>> information
    that genuinely implies it DOESN'T halt.  The explanation is obvious: >>>>> embedded_H gathers information that *YOU* believe implies that
    UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩)
    would never halt, but *YOU ARE SIMPLY WRONG*.

    He used to claim that false ("does not halt") was the correct answer,
    /even though/ the computation in question halts!  Those were simpler
    days.  Of course cranks will never admit to having been wrong about
    anything other than a detail or two, so anyone who could be bothered
    could try to get him to retract that old claim.


    <MIT Professor Sipser agreed to ONLY these verbatim words 10/13/2022>
         If simulating halt decider H correctly simulates its input D
         until H correctly determines that its simulated D would never
         stop running unless aborted then

         H can abort its simulation of D and correctly report that D
         specifies a non-halting sequence of configurations.
    </MIT Professor Sipser agreed to ONLY these verbatim words 10/13/2022>

    When Ĥ is applied to ⟨Ĥ⟩
    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qy ∞
    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qn

    In other words embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ is correct to
    reject its input if

    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* UTM ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qy ∞
    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* UTM ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qn
    Would not halt.

    Nope, because that isn't the input that it was given.

    *Wrong*
    <MIT Professor Sipser agreed to ONLY these verbatim words 10/13/2022>
        If simulating halt decider H correctly simulates its input D
        until H correctly determines that its *simulated D would never*
        *stop running unless aborted* then

    *simulated D would never stop running unless aborted*
    simulated D (the actual input)
    never stop running unless aborted (hypothetical H/D pair)


    No, that is changing the input.

    Never stops running, hypothectical H given original D

    That DOES halt, as shown by HHH1.

    Your problem is that you don't understand what a PROGRAM is, so your D
    isn't really a program, and you keep on equivocating about what it is.

    Either it IS a program, and contains the code for the one H it is
    designed to prove wrong, and thus doesn't change when you hypoothosize
    about giving THIS input to another version of H.

    Or if it does somehow change, it never was a program in the first place.

    You are just proving you are too stupid to understand this basic fact.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Fred. Zwarts@21:1/5 to All on Tue May 6 21:01:42 2025
    Op 06.mei.2025 om 19:49 schreef olcott:
    On 5/6/2025 6:23 AM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 5/5/25 10:36 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/5/2025 8:23 PM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 5/4/25 9:23 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/4/2025 8:04 PM, Ben Bacarisse wrote:
    Mike Terry <news.dead.person.stones@darjeeling.plus.com> writes:
    ...
    As explained above, UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩) simulates Ĥ run with input Ĥ
    (having the
    same halting behaviour) and Ĥ run with input Ĥ HALTS.  So
    embedded_H does
    not "gather enough information to deduce that UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩) would
    never
    halt".  THAT IS JUST A FANTASY THAT YOU HAVE.

    UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩) DOES halt, so embedded_H can't possibly gather >>>>>>> information
    that genuinely implies it DOESN'T halt.  The explanation is obvious: >>>>>>> embedded_H gathers information that *YOU* believe implies that
    UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩)
    would never halt, but *YOU ARE SIMPLY WRONG*.

    He used to claim that false ("does not halt") was the correct answer, >>>>>> /even though/ the computation in question halts!  Those were simpler >>>>>> days.  Of course cranks will never admit to having been wrong about >>>>>> anything other than a detail or two, so anyone who could be bothered >>>>>> could try to get him to retract that old claim.


    <MIT Professor Sipser agreed to ONLY these verbatim words 10/13/2022> >>>>>      If simulating halt decider H correctly simulates its input D >>>>>      until H correctly determines that its simulated D would never >>>>>      stop running unless aborted then

         H can abort its simulation of D and correctly report that D >>>>>      specifies a non-halting sequence of configurations.
    </MIT Professor Sipser agreed to ONLY these verbatim words 10/13/2022> >>>>>
    When Ĥ is applied to ⟨Ĥ⟩
    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qy ∞
    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qn

    In other words embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ is correct to
    reject its input if

    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* UTM ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qy ∞
    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* UTM ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qn
    Would not halt.

    Nope, because that isn't the input that it was given.

    *Wrong*
    <MIT Professor Sipser agreed to ONLY these verbatim words 10/13/2022>
         If simulating halt decider H correctly simulates its input D
         until H correctly determines that its *simulated D would never* >>>      *stop running unless aborted* then

    *simulated D would never stop running unless aborted*
    simulated D (the actual input)
    never stop running unless aborted (hypothetical H/D pair)


    No, that is changing the input.


    *would never stop running unless aborted*
    means the hypothetical same HHH that DD calls
    except that this HHH does not abort.


    Which makes it a fundamentally different HHH. Changing the input is not allowed.
    Is it over your head that changing a program makes it different?

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From joes@21:1/5 to All on Tue May 6 20:25:36 2025
    Am Tue, 06 May 2025 12:49:13 -0500 schrieb olcott:
    On 5/6/2025 6:23 AM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 5/5/25 10:36 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/5/2025 8:23 PM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 5/4/25 9:23 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/4/2025 8:04 PM, Ben Bacarisse wrote:
    Mike Terry <news.dead.person.stones@darjeeling.plus.com> writes:
    ...
    As explained above, UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩) simulates Ĥ run with input Ĥ
    (having the same halting behaviour) and Ĥ run with input Ĥ HALTS.  >>>>>>> So embedded_H does not "gather enough information to deduce that >>>>>>> UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩) would never halt".  THAT IS JUST A FANTASY THAT YOU
    HAVE.
    UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩) DOES halt, so embedded_H can't possibly gather >>>>>>> information that genuinely implies it DOESN'T halt.  The
    explanation is obvious: embedded_H gathers information that *YOU* >>>>>>> believe implies that UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩)
    would never halt, but *YOU ARE SIMPLY WRONG*.

    He used to claim that false ("does not halt") was the correct
    answer,
    /even though/ the computation in question halts!  Those were
    simpler days.  Of course cranks will never admit to having been
    wrong about anything other than a detail or two, so anyone who
    could be bothered could try to get him to retract that old claim.

    <MIT Professor Sipser agreed to ONLY these verbatim words
    10/13/2022>
    </MIT Professor Sipser agreed to ONLY these verbatim words
    10/13/2022>

    When Ĥ is applied to ⟨Ĥ⟩
    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qy ∞
    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qn

    In other words embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ is correct to reject its input if

    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* UTM ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qy ∞
    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* UTM ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qn Would not halt.

    Nope, because that isn't the input that it was given.

    *Wrong*
    <MIT Professor Sipser agreed to ONLY these verbatim words 10/13/2022>
         If simulating halt decider H correctly simulates its input D
         until H correctly determines that its *simulated D would
         never stop running unless aborted* then

    *simulated D would never stop running unless aborted*
    simulated D (the actual input)
    never stop running unless aborted (hypothetical H/D pair)

    No, that is changing the input.

    *would never stop running unless aborted* means the hypothetical same
    HHH that DD calls except that this HHH does not abort.
    Yes, that is not the same HHH.

    --
    Am Sat, 20 Jul 2024 12:35:31 +0000 schrieb WM in sci.math:
    It is not guaranteed that n+1 exists for every n.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to olcott on Tue May 6 22:10:13 2025
    On 5/6/25 1:49 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/6/2025 6:23 AM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 5/5/25 10:36 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/5/2025 8:23 PM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 5/4/25 9:23 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/4/2025 8:04 PM, Ben Bacarisse wrote:
    Mike Terry <news.dead.person.stones@darjeeling.plus.com> writes:
    ...
    As explained above, UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩) simulates Ĥ run with input Ĥ
    (having the
    same halting behaviour) and Ĥ run with input Ĥ HALTS.  So
    embedded_H does
    not "gather enough information to deduce that UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩) would
    never
    halt".  THAT IS JUST A FANTASY THAT YOU HAVE.

    UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩) DOES halt, so embedded_H can't possibly gather >>>>>>> information
    that genuinely implies it DOESN'T halt.  The explanation is obvious: >>>>>>> embedded_H gathers information that *YOU* believe implies that
    UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩)
    would never halt, but *YOU ARE SIMPLY WRONG*.

    He used to claim that false ("does not halt") was the correct answer, >>>>>> /even though/ the computation in question halts!  Those were simpler >>>>>> days.  Of course cranks will never admit to having been wrong about >>>>>> anything other than a detail or two, so anyone who could be bothered >>>>>> could try to get him to retract that old claim.


    <MIT Professor Sipser agreed to ONLY these verbatim words 10/13/2022> >>>>>      If simulating halt decider H correctly simulates its input D >>>>>      until H correctly determines that its simulated D would never >>>>>      stop running unless aborted then

         H can abort its simulation of D and correctly report that D >>>>>      specifies a non-halting sequence of configurations.
    </MIT Professor Sipser agreed to ONLY these verbatim words 10/13/2022> >>>>>
    When Ĥ is applied to ⟨Ĥ⟩
    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qy ∞
    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qn

    In other words embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ is correct to
    reject its input if

    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* UTM ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qy ∞
    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* UTM ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qn
    Would not halt.

    Nope, because that isn't the input that it was given.

    *Wrong*
    <MIT Professor Sipser agreed to ONLY these verbatim words 10/13/2022>
         If simulating halt decider H correctly simulates its input D
         until H correctly determines that its *simulated D would never* >>>      *stop running unless aborted* then

    *simulated D would never stop running unless aborted*
    simulated D (the actual input)
    never stop running unless aborted (hypothetical H/D pair)


    No, that is changing the input.


    *would never stop running unless aborted*
    means the hypothetical same HHH that DD calls
    except that this HHH does not abort.


    Nope, can't change the input.

    The HHH deciding the outer DD can be changed, but not the HHH that DD
    calls, as that is in the input, or you have lied about DD being a representation of a program.

    Sorry, but you are just showing your stupdity and that you are just a pathological liar that doesn't care about the actual facts, only what
    you can make up as false claims.

    Good luck on Judgement Day, your list of lies is getting very long.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to olcott on Tue May 6 22:12:16 2025
    On 5/6/25 3:15 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/6/2025 2:01 PM, Fred. Zwarts wrote:
    Op 06.mei.2025 om 19:49 schreef olcott:
    On 5/6/2025 6:23 AM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 5/5/25 10:36 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/5/2025 8:23 PM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 5/4/25 9:23 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/4/2025 8:04 PM, Ben Bacarisse wrote:
    Mike Terry <news.dead.person.stones@darjeeling.plus.com> writes: >>>>>>>> ...
    As explained above, UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩) simulates Ĥ run with input Ĥ
    (having the
    same halting behaviour) and Ĥ run with input Ĥ HALTS.  So >>>>>>>>> embedded_H does
    not "gather enough information to deduce that UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩) >>>>>>>>> would never
    halt".  THAT IS JUST A FANTASY THAT YOU HAVE.

    UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩) DOES halt, so embedded_H can't possibly gather >>>>>>>>> information
    that genuinely implies it DOESN'T halt.  The explanation is >>>>>>>>> obvious:
    embedded_H gathers information that *YOU* believe implies that >>>>>>>>> UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩)
    would never halt, but *YOU ARE SIMPLY WRONG*.

    He used to claim that false ("does not halt") was the correct
    answer,
    /even though/ the computation in question halts!  Those were
    simpler
    days.  Of course cranks will never admit to having been wrong about >>>>>>>> anything other than a detail or two, so anyone who could be
    bothered
    could try to get him to retract that old claim.


    <MIT Professor Sipser agreed to ONLY these verbatim words
    10/13/2022>
         If simulating halt decider H correctly simulates its input D >>>>>>>      until H correctly determines that its simulated D would never >>>>>>>      stop running unless aborted then

         H can abort its simulation of D and correctly report that D >>>>>>>      specifies a non-halting sequence of configurations.
    </MIT Professor Sipser agreed to ONLY these verbatim words
    10/13/2022>

    When Ĥ is applied to ⟨Ĥ⟩
    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qy ∞
    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qn

    In other words embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ is correct to
    reject its input if

    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* UTM ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qy ∞
    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* UTM ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qn
    Would not halt.

    Nope, because that isn't the input that it was given.

    *Wrong*
    <MIT Professor Sipser agreed to ONLY these verbatim words 10/13/2022> >>>>>      If simulating halt decider H correctly simulates its input D >>>>>      until H correctly determines that its *simulated D would never* >>>>>      *stop running unless aborted* then

    *simulated D would never stop running unless aborted*
    simulated D (the actual input)
    never stop running unless aborted (hypothetical H/D pair)


    No, that is changing the input.


    *would never stop running unless aborted*
    means the hypothetical same HHH that DD calls
    except that this HHH does not abort.


    Which makes it a fundamentally different HHH.

    None-the-less it is the words that the best selling
    author of theory of computation textbooks agreed to:
    *would never stop running unless aborted*


    And it DOES stop running without being aborted.

    is the hypothetical HHH/DD pair where the same HHH
    that DD calls does not abort the simulation of its input.


    Which is isn't except in your stupid mind. The truth is you don't get to
    change the input, which to be a valid input, contains the code for the
    original HHH which does abort, and thus will halt when correctly emulated.

    You just don't understand what you are talking about, and seem to be too
    stupid to learn it.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to olcott on Tue May 6 22:13:30 2025
    On 5/6/25 4:38 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/6/2025 3:25 PM, joes wrote:
    Am Tue, 06 May 2025 12:49:13 -0500 schrieb olcott:
    On 5/6/2025 6:23 AM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 5/5/25 10:36 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/5/2025 8:23 PM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 5/4/25 9:23 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/4/2025 8:04 PM, Ben Bacarisse wrote:
    Mike Terry <news.dead.person.stones@darjeeling.plus.com> writes: >>>>>>>> ...
    As explained above, UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩) simulates Ĥ run with input Ĥ
    (having the same halting behaviour) and Ĥ run with input Ĥ HALTS. >>>>>>>>> So embedded_H does not "gather enough information to deduce that >>>>>>>>> UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩) would never halt".  THAT IS JUST A FANTASY THAT YOU
    HAVE.
    UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩) DOES halt, so embedded_H can't possibly gather >>>>>>>>> information that genuinely implies it DOESN'T halt.  The
    explanation is obvious: embedded_H gathers information that *YOU* >>>>>>>>> believe implies that UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩)
    would never halt, but *YOU ARE SIMPLY WRONG*.

    He used to claim that false ("does not halt") was the correct
    answer,
    /even though/ the computation in question halts!  Those were
    simpler days.  Of course cranks will never admit to having been >>>>>>>> wrong about anything other than a detail or two, so anyone who >>>>>>>> could be bothered could try to get him to retract that old claim. >>>>>>>>
    <MIT Professor Sipser agreed to ONLY these verbatim words
    10/13/2022>
    </MIT Professor Sipser agreed to ONLY these verbatim words
    10/13/2022>

    When Ĥ is applied to ⟨Ĥ⟩
    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qy ∞
    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qn

    In other words embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ is correct to reject its input if

    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* UTM ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qy ∞
    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* UTM ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qn Would not halt. >>>>>>
    Nope, because that isn't the input that it was given.

    *Wrong*
    <MIT Professor Sipser agreed to ONLY these verbatim words 10/13/2022> >>>>>       If simulating halt decider H correctly simulates its input D >>>>>       until H correctly determines that its *simulated D would
          never stop running unless aborted* then

    *simulated D would never stop running unless aborted*
    simulated D (the actual input)
    never stop running unless aborted (hypothetical H/D pair)

    No, that is changing the input.

    *would never stop running unless aborted* means the hypothetical same
    HHH that DD calls except that this HHH does not abort.
    Yes, that is not the same HHH.


    Yet is the HHH that Professor Sipser agreed would be
    the correct measure of the behavior of the actual input.


    But not the D that he was talking about, which is FIXED to always use
    the original decider.

    Sorry, you don't get to put words in peoples mouths, and ar just showing
    how much your world is based on lying.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Fred. Zwarts@21:1/5 to All on Wed May 7 12:16:06 2025
    Op 06.mei.2025 om 21:15 schreef olcott:
    On 5/6/2025 2:01 PM, Fred. Zwarts wrote:
    Op 06.mei.2025 om 19:49 schreef olcott:
    On 5/6/2025 6:23 AM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 5/5/25 10:36 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/5/2025 8:23 PM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 5/4/25 9:23 PM, olcott wrote:
    On 5/4/2025 8:04 PM, Ben Bacarisse wrote:
    Mike Terry <news.dead.person.stones@darjeeling.plus.com> writes: >>>>>>>> ...
    As explained above, UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩) simulates Ĥ run with input Ĥ
    (having the
    same halting behaviour) and Ĥ run with input Ĥ HALTS.  So >>>>>>>>> embedded_H does
    not "gather enough information to deduce that UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩) >>>>>>>>> would never
    halt".  THAT IS JUST A FANTASY THAT YOU HAVE.

    UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩) DOES halt, so embedded_H can't possibly gather >>>>>>>>> information
    that genuinely implies it DOESN'T halt.  The explanation is >>>>>>>>> obvious:
    embedded_H gathers information that *YOU* believe implies that >>>>>>>>> UTM(⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩)
    would never halt, but *YOU ARE SIMPLY WRONG*.

    He used to claim that false ("does not halt") was the correct
    answer,
    /even though/ the computation in question halts!  Those were
    simpler
    days.  Of course cranks will never admit to having been wrong about >>>>>>>> anything other than a detail or two, so anyone who could be
    bothered
    could try to get him to retract that old claim.


    <MIT Professor Sipser agreed to ONLY these verbatim words
    10/13/2022>
         If simulating halt decider H correctly simulates its input D >>>>>>>      until H correctly determines that its simulated D would never >>>>>>>      stop running unless aborted then

         H can abort its simulation of D and correctly report that D >>>>>>>      specifies a non-halting sequence of configurations.
    </MIT Professor Sipser agreed to ONLY these verbatim words
    10/13/2022>

    When Ĥ is applied to ⟨Ĥ⟩
    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qy ∞
    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qn

    In other words embedded_H ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ is correct to
    reject its input if

    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* UTM ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qy ∞
    Ĥ.q0 ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* UTM ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⟨Ĥ⟩ ⊢* Ĥ.qn
    Would not halt.

    Nope, because that isn't the input that it was given.

    *Wrong*
    <MIT Professor Sipser agreed to ONLY these verbatim words 10/13/2022> >>>>>      If simulating halt decider H correctly simulates its input D >>>>>      until H correctly determines that its *simulated D would never* >>>>>      *stop running unless aborted* then

    *simulated D would never stop running unless aborted*
    simulated D (the actual input)
    never stop running unless aborted (hypothetical H/D pair)


    No, that is changing the input.


    *would never stop running unless aborted*
    means the hypothetical same HHH that DD calls
    except that this HHH does not abort.


    Which makes it a fundamentally different HHH.

    None-the-less it is the words that the best selling
    author of theory of computation textbooks agreed to:
    *would never stop running unless aborted*

    is the hypothetical HHH/DD pair where the same HHH
    that DD calls does not abort the simulation of its input.



    Nevertheless, this change makes it fundamentally different.
    I can't believe that you are so stupid to think that modifying a program
    does not make a program different. Are you trolling?
    HHH should decide about its input, not about a fundamentally different hypothetical input.
    Sum(2,3) should compute the sum of 2 and 3, not the sum of a
    hypothetical 1 and 4, nor of only the first part of the input 2.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Fred. Zwarts@21:1/5 to All on Wed May 7 17:30:17 2025
    Op 07.mei.2025 om 17:03 schreef olcott:
    On 5/7/2025 7:01 AM, dbush wrote:
    On 5/7/2025 6:16 AM, Fred. Zwarts wrote:
    Op 06.mei.2025 om 21:15 schreef olcott:
    None-the-less it is the words that the best selling
    author of theory of computation textbooks agreed to:
    *would never stop running unless aborted*

    is the hypothetical HHH/DD pair where the same HHH
    that DD calls does not abort the simulation of its input.



    Nevertheless, this change makes it fundamentally different.
    I can't believe that you are so stupid to think that modifying a
    program does not make a program different. Are you trolling?

    Given that he's shown he doesn't understand (and this list is by no
    means exhaustive):

    * what requirements are
    * what correct means
    * what true means
    * what a proof is
    * how proof by contradiction works

    I wouldn't put it past him that he actually believes it.  He'll say
    anything to avoid admitting to himself that he wasted that last 22
    years not understanding what he was working on.

    (Anyone else that wants to add to this list, feel free)

    A simulating halt decider must correctly
    predict *what the behavior would be* if it
    did not abort its simulation.

    WRONG. it must analyse which behaviour is specified by the input,
    without that 'if'.
    Using the 'if', changes the input, which is not allowed.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From joes@21:1/5 to All on Wed May 7 15:44:41 2025
    Am Wed, 07 May 2025 10:03:55 -0500 schrieb olcott:
    On 5/7/2025 7:01 AM, dbush wrote:
    On 5/7/2025 6:16 AM, Fred. Zwarts wrote:
    Op 06.mei.2025 om 21:15 schreef olcott:

    None-the-less it is the words that the best selling author of theory
    of computation textbooks agreed to: *would never stop running unless
    aborted*
    is the hypothetical HHH/DD pair where the same HHH that DD calls does
    not abort the simulation of its input.

    Nevertheless, this change makes it fundamentally different.
    I can't believe that you are so stupid to think that modifying a
    program does not make a program different. Are you trolling?

    Given that he's shown he doesn't understand (and this list is by no
    means exhaustive):
    * what requirements are * what correct means * what true means * what a
    proof is * how proof by contradiction works
    I wouldn't put it past him that he actually believes it.  He'll say
    anything to avoid admitting to himself that he wasted that last 22
    years not understanding what he was working on.
    (Anyone else that wants to add to this list, feel free)

    A simulating halt decider must correctly predict *what the behavior
    would be* if it did not abort its simulation.
    ...if it, the simulator, didn't abort. The input DD that is being
    simulated still calls the same real HHH that does abort.

    *simulated D would never stop running unless aborted*
    means that HHH examines what the behavior of DD *would be*
    if it never aborted its simulation. This is a different
    hypothetical HHH/DD pair than the actual HHH/DD pair.
    So a non-input.

    If it did not do this and simply kept simulating a non-terminating input
    it would break the requirement that itself must halt.
    If it does do this it breaks the requirement that it must return the value
    of a full simulation.

    --
    Am Sat, 20 Jul 2024 12:35:31 +0000 schrieb WM in sci.math:
    It is not guaranteed that n+1 exists for every n.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Heathfield@21:1/5 to olcott on Wed May 7 20:02:24 2025
    On 07/05/2025 19:47, olcott wrote:

    <snip>

    HHH did not abort its input. That is the ONLY way that
    simulating halt deciders can possibly work.

    Another only is that simulating halt deciders (like code-parsing
    halt deciders) can only possibly work if they don't claim to be
    universal.

    --
    Richard Heathfield
    Email: rjh at cpax dot org dot uk
    "Usenet is a strange place" - dmr 29 July 1999
    Sig line 4 vacant - apply within

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Heathfield@21:1/5 to olcott on Wed May 7 22:44:51 2025
    On 07/05/2025 20:59, olcott wrote:
    On 5/7/2025 2:02 PM, Richard Heathfield wrote:
    On 07/05/2025 19:47, olcott wrote:

    <snip>

    HHH did not abort its input. That is the ONLY way that
    simulating halt deciders can possibly work.

    Another only is that simulating halt deciders (like
    code-parsing halt deciders) can only possibly work if they
    don't claim to be universal.


    That is why I switched to "termination analyzer" as
    long as it correctly determines the halt status on one
    single input that has no inputs then it is correct.

    Except that it fails to analyse its input program correctly.

    You will accept, I think, that your 'analysis' consists of
    simulating the input program. Since by your own admission the
    simulation fails to simulate the whole program, however, if by
    some chance it produces the right answer it's more by luck than
    judgement. If you're going to guess the answer, why bother to
    write a program? Just toss a coin.

    --
    Richard Heathfield
    Email: rjh at cpax dot org dot uk
    "Usenet is a strange place" - dmr 29 July 1999
    Sig line 4 vacant - apply within

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Heathfield@21:1/5 to olcott on Wed May 7 22:55:13 2025
    On 07/05/2025 22:49, olcott wrote:

    <snip>

    I don't think it make sense to continue to talk to
    clueless people that lack the technical capacity
    to verify key facts.

    How right you are.

    --
    Richard Heathfield
    Email: rjh at cpax dot org dot uk
    "Usenet is a strange place" - dmr 29 July 1999
    Sig line 4 vacant - apply within

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)