Analysis of Flibble’s New Take on Simulating Halt Deciders and
Pathological Input ==================================================================================
1. Summary of Flibble’s New Take
--------------------------------
Flibble introduces a refined stance on the treatment of pathological input within simulating halt deciders (SHDs), asserting:
- It's sufficient for an SHD to detect *infinite recursion*, rather than
run a simulation to its literal end.
- Aborting due to stack overflow or continuing infinitely are semantically equivalent — both signify non-halting behavior.
- This leads to the articulation of "Flibble's Law":
If a problem permits infinite behavior in its formulation, it permits
infinite analysis of that behavior in its decidability scope.
2. Interpretation of Flibble’s Law
----------------------------------
This law suggests that:
- Any problem involving potentially infinite computation inherently
requires the ability to analyze such infinite behavior.
- Deciders are not invalidated by their inability to simulate forever — they are validated by their ability to detect structural infinity.
3. Shift in Position
--------------------
Earlier, Flibble emphasized that:
- Pathological inputs are ill-formed due to a category error (program conflated with its own representation).
- Therefore, halting cannot even be meaningfully questioned for such
inputs.
Now, Flibble acknowledges:
- SHDs can still offer meaningful answers by detecting recursion patterns without needing infinite runtime.
- A decider may *abort* simulation upon detecting such patterns and still
be semantically correct.
4. Contrast with Turing’s View
------------------------------
| Aspect | Turing |
Flibble | |-----------------------------|------------------------------------|--------------------------------------|
| Infinite recursion | Undecidable behavior |
Signal of ill-formed input |
| Decider responsibilities | Must decide all valid inputs | Must exclude ill-formed inputs |
| Simulation abort (overflow) | Not semantically significant | Valid detection of non-halting input |
Turing treats infinite simulation as a symptom of undecidability. Flibble treats it as a signal of semantic ill-formedness — which still permits operational classification.
5. Theoretical and Practical Implications -----------------------------------------
- **Theoretically**, Flibble provides a framework that restricts the
Halting Problem's domain to avoid paradoxes.
- **Practically**, SHDs like Peter’s can still provide useful results for many inputs, even if pathological ones must be handled by pattern
recognition or structural limits.
6. Conclusion
-------------
Flibble now offers a reconciliatory yet disciplined model:
- The Halting Problem remains malformed in full generality due to category errors.
- But deciders can responsibly detect and handle malformed inputs using structural heuristics.
- Flibble's Law provides philosophical cover for SHDs to analyze — but not execute — infinite behaviors.
This is not a retreat from his original critique of Turing’s proof; it is an evolution of it into a usable framework for analyzing decidability
within a restricted, type-safe domain.
On 5/17/25 8:27 PM, Mr Flibble wrote:
Analysis of Flibble’s New Take on Simulating Halt Deciders and
Pathological Input
==================================================================================
1. Summary of Flibble’s New Take --------------------------------
Flibble introduces a refined stance on the treatment of pathological
input within simulating halt deciders (SHDs), asserting:
- It's sufficient for an SHD to detect *infinite recursion*, rather
than run a simulation to its literal end.
But only if the recursion, is in fact, infinite.
- Aborting due to stack overflow or continuing infinitely areWhich just isn't true, and aborting due to stack overflow is NOT
semantically equivalent — both signify non-halting behavior.
- This leads to the articulation of "Flibble's Law":
If a problem permits infinite behavior in its formulation, it
permits infinite analysis of that behavior in its decidability
scope.
semantically equivalent to continuing infinitely.
The first is having a highest amount you can handle, while the latter is being able to get to any value.
If a problem will halt on a propertly configures machine after 2 million steps. but the not as well equipted machine overflows after 1 million
steps, it just got the wrong answer.
2. Interpretation of Flibble’s Law ----------------------------------
This law suggests that:
- Any problem involving potentially infinite computation inherently
requires the ability to analyze such infinite behavior.
It may require, but it still is not allowed that decider to use infinite time.
- Deciders are not invalidated by their inability to simulate forever —
they are validated by their ability to detect structural infinity.
But only if they CORRECTLY determine actual infinite behavior.
3. Shift in Position --------------------
Earlier, Flibble emphasized that:
- Pathological inputs are ill-formed due to a category error (program
conflated with its own representation).
No, they are not.
- Therefore, halting cannot even be meaningfully questioned for such
inputs.
Sure t can, as long as the input is the representation of a PROGRAM (and
that means it includes all the code that it uses) that program WILL
either halt or not, and thus that input either represents a halting
program or not, and thus the question is meaningful.
Note, the Olcoott input, defined to be just the C funcition, is not a program, so yes, THAT INPUT is invalid, but can be made valid by
completing the proof program by including in it the code for the decider
that it is designed to prove not correct.
Now, Flibble acknowledges:
- SHDs can still offer meaningful answers by detecting recursion
patterns without needing infinite runtime.
In *SOME* cases, not all. So they can be PARTIAL deciders.
- A decider may *abort* simulation upon detecting such patterns and
still be semantically correct.
But only if the pattern is ACTUALLY infinitely recursive.
4. Contrast with Turing’s View ------------------------------
| Aspect | Turing |
Flibble |
|-----------------------------|------------------------------------|--------------------------------------|
| Infinite recursion | Undecidable behavior |
Signal of ill-formed input |
| Decider responsibilities | Must decide all valid inputs |
Must exclude ill-formed inputs |
| Simulation abort (overflow) | Not semantically significant |
Valid detection of non-halting input |
But it is possible for Turing Machie to detect SOME forms of infinite recursion, so you table is just incorrect.
It is fairly easy to detect that the foloowing is non-halting:
int R() {
R();
}
So just the presence of recursion isn't the problem.
Turing treats infinite simulation as a symptom of undecidability.
Flibble treats it as a signal of semantic ill-formedness — which still
permits operational classification.
No, you are just showing you don't understand what you are talking
about, because you are believing Olcotts lies.
5. Theoretical and Practical Implications
-----------------------------------------
- **Theoretically**, Flibble provides a framework that restricts the
Halting Problem's domain to avoid paradoxes.
No, it tries to create a loosened set of requirements to see if those
can be solved.
- **Practically**, SHDs like Peter’s can still provide useful results
for many inputs, even if pathological ones must be handled by pattern
recognition or structural limits.
Yes, PARTIAL deciders have some uses, but they don't disprove the fact
that no universal decider exists.
6. Conclusion -------------
Flibble now offers a reconciliatory yet disciplined model:
- The Halting Problem remains malformed in full generality due to
category errors.
But the halting problem isn't malformed, and thus your argument is just
a bunch of hot air.
- But deciders can responsibly detect and handle malformed inputs using
structural heuristics.
But there is nothing "malformed" about the actual "pathological" program
of the proof. It is a fully valid program to be decided on.
- Flibble's Law provides philosophical cover for SHDs to analyze — but
not execute — infinite behaviors.
Only if you allow your logic to allow the insertion of false statements.
This is not a retreat from his original critique of Turing’s proof; itThe problem is you try to use an incorrect set of types, and thus fail.
is an evolution of it into a usable framework for analyzing
decidability within a restricted, type-safe domain.
On Sun, 18 May 2025 07:00:29 -0400, Richard Damon wrote:
On 5/17/25 8:27 PM, Mr Flibble wrote:==================================================================================
Analysis of Flibble’s New Take on Simulating Halt Deciders and
Pathological Input
|-----------------------------|------------------------------------|--------------------------------------|
1. Summary of Flibble’s New Take --------------------------------
Flibble introduces a refined stance on the treatment of pathological
input within simulating halt deciders (SHDs), asserting:
- It's sufficient for an SHD to detect *infinite recursion*, rather
than run a simulation to its literal end.
But only if the recursion, is in fact, infinite.
- Aborting due to stack overflow or continuing infinitely areWhich just isn't true, and aborting due to stack overflow is NOT
semantically equivalent — both signify non-halting behavior.
- This leads to the articulation of "Flibble's Law":
If a problem permits infinite behavior in its formulation, it
permits infinite analysis of that behavior in its decidability
scope.
semantically equivalent to continuing infinitely.
The first is having a highest amount you can handle, while the latter is
being able to get to any value.
If a problem will halt on a propertly configures machine after 2 million
steps. but the not as well equipted machine overflows after 1 million
steps, it just got the wrong answer.
2. Interpretation of Flibble’s Law ----------------------------------
This law suggests that:
- Any problem involving potentially infinite computation inherently
requires the ability to analyze such infinite behavior.
It may require, but it still is not allowed that decider to use infinite
time.
- Deciders are not invalidated by their inability to simulate forever — >>> they are validated by their ability to detect structural infinity.
But only if they CORRECTLY determine actual infinite behavior.
3. Shift in Position --------------------
Earlier, Flibble emphasized that:
- Pathological inputs are ill-formed due to a category error (program
conflated with its own representation).
No, they are not.
- Therefore, halting cannot even be meaningfully questioned for such
inputs.
Sure t can, as long as the input is the representation of a PROGRAM (and
that means it includes all the code that it uses) that program WILL
either halt or not, and thus that input either represents a halting
program or not, and thus the question is meaningful.
Note, the Olcoott input, defined to be just the C funcition, is not a
program, so yes, THAT INPUT is invalid, but can be made valid by
completing the proof program by including in it the code for the decider
that it is designed to prove not correct.
Now, Flibble acknowledges:
- SHDs can still offer meaningful answers by detecting recursion
patterns without needing infinite runtime.
In *SOME* cases, not all. So they can be PARTIAL deciders.
- A decider may *abort* simulation upon detecting such patterns and
still be semantically correct.
But only if the pattern is ACTUALLY infinitely recursive.
4. Contrast with Turing’s View ------------------------------
| Aspect | Turing |
Flibble |
| Infinite recursion | Undecidable behavior |
Signal of ill-formed input |
| Decider responsibilities | Must decide all valid inputs |
Must exclude ill-formed inputs |
| Simulation abort (overflow) | Not semantically significant |
Valid detection of non-halting input |
But it is possible for Turing Machie to detect SOME forms of infinite
recursion, so you table is just incorrect.
It is fairly easy to detect that the foloowing is non-halting:
int R() {
R();
}
So just the presence of recursion isn't the problem.
Turing treats infinite simulation as a symptom of undecidability.
Flibble treats it as a signal of semantic ill-formedness — which still >>> permits operational classification.
No, you are just showing you don't understand what you are talking
about, because you are believing Olcotts lies.
5. Theoretical and Practical Implications
-----------------------------------------
- **Theoretically**, Flibble provides a framework that restricts the
Halting Problem's domain to avoid paradoxes.
No, it tries to create a loosened set of requirements to see if those
can be solved.
- **Practically**, SHDs like Peter’s can still provide useful results
for many inputs, even if pathological ones must be handled by pattern
recognition or structural limits.
Yes, PARTIAL deciders have some uses, but they don't disprove the fact
that no universal decider exists.
6. Conclusion -------------
Flibble now offers a reconciliatory yet disciplined model:
- The Halting Problem remains malformed in full generality due to
category errors.
But the halting problem isn't malformed, and thus your argument is just
a bunch of hot air.
- But deciders can responsibly detect and handle malformed inputs using
structural heuristics.
But there is nothing "malformed" about the actual "pathological" program
of the proof. It is a fully valid program to be decided on.
- Flibble's Law provides philosophical cover for SHDs to analyze — but >>> not execute — infinite behaviors.
Only if you allow your logic to allow the insertion of false statements.
This is not a retreat from his original critique of Turing’s proof; it >>> is an evolution of it into a usable framework for analyzingThe problem is you try to use an incorrect set of types, and thus fail.
decidability within a restricted, type-safe domain.
Again, every single one of your points is either wrong or not a counter- argument: you've got nothing.
/Flibble
Analysis of Flibble’s New Take on Simulating Halt Deciders and
Pathological Input ==================================================================================
1. Summary of Flibble’s New Take
--------------------------------
Flibble introduces a refined stance on the treatment of pathological input within simulating halt deciders (SHDs), asserting:
- It's sufficient for an SHD to detect *infinite recursion*, rather than
run a simulation to its literal end.
- Aborting due to stack overflow or continuing infinitely are semantically equivalent — both signify non-halting behavior.
- This leads to the articulation of "Flibble's Law":
If a problem permits infinite behavior in its formulation, it permits
infinite analysis of that behavior in its decidability scope.
2. Interpretation of Flibble’s Law
----------------------------------
This law suggests that:
- Any problem involving potentially infinite computation inherently
requires the ability to analyze such infinite behavior.
- Deciders are not invalidated by their inability to simulate forever — they are validated by their ability to detect structural infinity.
3. Shift in Position
--------------------
Earlier, Flibble emphasized that:
- Pathological inputs are ill-formed due to a category error (program conflated with its own representation).
- Therefore, halting cannot even be meaningfully questioned for such
inputs.
Now, Flibble acknowledges:
- SHDs can still offer meaningful answers by detecting recursion patterns without needing infinite runtime.
- A decider may *abort* simulation upon detecting such patterns and still
be semantically correct.
4. Contrast with Turing’s View
------------------------------
| Aspect | Turing |
Flibble | |-----------------------------|------------------------------------|--------------------------------------|
| Infinite recursion | Undecidable behavior |
Signal of ill-formed input |
| Decider responsibilities | Must decide all valid inputs | Must exclude ill-formed inputs |
| Simulation abort (overflow) | Not semantically significant | Valid detection of non-halting input |
Turing treats infinite simulation as a symptom of undecidability.
On Sun, 18 May 2025 07:00:29 -0400, Richard Damon wrote:
On 5/17/25 8:27 PM, Mr Flibble wrote:==================================================================================
Analysis of Flibble’s New Take on Simulating Halt Deciders and
Pathological Input
|-----------------------------|------------------------------------|--------------------------------------|
1. Summary of Flibble’s New Take --------------------------------
Flibble introduces a refined stance on the treatment of pathological
input within simulating halt deciders (SHDs), asserting:
- It's sufficient for an SHD to detect *infinite recursion*, rather
than run a simulation to its literal end.
But only if the recursion, is in fact, infinite.
- Aborting due to stack overflow or continuing infinitely areWhich just isn't true, and aborting due to stack overflow is NOT
semantically equivalent — both signify non-halting behavior.
- This leads to the articulation of "Flibble's Law":
If a problem permits infinite behavior in its formulation, it
permits infinite analysis of that behavior in its decidability
scope.
semantically equivalent to continuing infinitely.
The first is having a highest amount you can handle, while the latter is
being able to get to any value.
If a problem will halt on a propertly configures machine after 2 million
steps. but the not as well equipted machine overflows after 1 million
steps, it just got the wrong answer.
2. Interpretation of Flibble’s Law ----------------------------------
This law suggests that:
- Any problem involving potentially infinite computation inherently
requires the ability to analyze such infinite behavior.
It may require, but it still is not allowed that decider to use infinite
time.
- Deciders are not invalidated by their inability to simulate forever — >>> they are validated by their ability to detect structural infinity.
But only if they CORRECTLY determine actual infinite behavior.
3. Shift in Position --------------------
Earlier, Flibble emphasized that:
- Pathological inputs are ill-formed due to a category error (program
conflated with its own representation).
No, they are not.
- Therefore, halting cannot even be meaningfully questioned for such
inputs.
Sure t can, as long as the input is the representation of a PROGRAM (and
that means it includes all the code that it uses) that program WILL
either halt or not, and thus that input either represents a halting
program or not, and thus the question is meaningful.
Note, the Olcoott input, defined to be just the C funcition, is not a
program, so yes, THAT INPUT is invalid, but can be made valid by
completing the proof program by including in it the code for the decider
that it is designed to prove not correct.
Now, Flibble acknowledges:
- SHDs can still offer meaningful answers by detecting recursion
patterns without needing infinite runtime.
In *SOME* cases, not all. So they can be PARTIAL deciders.
- A decider may *abort* simulation upon detecting such patterns and
still be semantically correct.
But only if the pattern is ACTUALLY infinitely recursive.
4. Contrast with Turing’s View ------------------------------
| Aspect | Turing |
Flibble |
| Infinite recursion | Undecidable behavior |
Signal of ill-formed input |
| Decider responsibilities | Must decide all valid inputs |
Must exclude ill-formed inputs |
| Simulation abort (overflow) | Not semantically significant |
Valid detection of non-halting input |
But it is possible for Turing Machie to detect SOME forms of infinite
recursion, so you table is just incorrect.
It is fairly easy to detect that the foloowing is non-halting:
int R() {
R();
}
So just the presence of recursion isn't the problem.
Turing treats infinite simulation as a symptom of undecidability.
Flibble treats it as a signal of semantic ill-formedness — which still >>> permits operational classification.
No, you are just showing you don't understand what you are talking
about, because you are believing Olcotts lies.
5. Theoretical and Practical Implications
-----------------------------------------
- **Theoretically**, Flibble provides a framework that restricts the
Halting Problem's domain to avoid paradoxes.
No, it tries to create a loosened set of requirements to see if those
can be solved.
- **Practically**, SHDs like Peter’s can still provide useful results
for many inputs, even if pathological ones must be handled by pattern
recognition or structural limits.
Yes, PARTIAL deciders have some uses, but they don't disprove the fact
that no universal decider exists.
6. Conclusion -------------
Flibble now offers a reconciliatory yet disciplined model:
- The Halting Problem remains malformed in full generality due to
category errors.
But the halting problem isn't malformed, and thus your argument is just
a bunch of hot air.
- But deciders can responsibly detect and handle malformed inputs using
structural heuristics.
But there is nothing "malformed" about the actual "pathological" program
of the proof. It is a fully valid program to be decided on.
- Flibble's Law provides philosophical cover for SHDs to analyze — but >>> not execute — infinite behaviors.
Only if you allow your logic to allow the insertion of false statements.
This is not a retreat from his original critique of Turing’s proof; it >>> is an evolution of it into a usable framework for analyzingThe problem is you try to use an incorrect set of types, and thus fail.
decidability within a restricted, type-safe domain.
Again, every single one of your points is either wrong or not a counter- argument: you've got nothing.
On 2025-05-18 00:27:29 +0000, Mr Flibble said:
Analysis of Flibble’s New Take on Simulating Halt Deciders and
Pathological Input
==================================================================================
1. Summary of Flibble’s New Take --------------------------------
Flibble introduces a refined stance on the treatment of pathological
input within simulating halt deciders (SHDs), asserting:
- It's sufficient for an SHD to detect *infinite recursion*, rather
than run a simulation to its literal end.
Detection of an infinite recursion is neither sufficent or necessary. A
halt decider is required to determine whether a computation halts. It
need not determine what kind of non-terminating behaviour the
computation has. As a SHD is a halt detector that applies to every SHD.
- Aborting due to stack overflow or continuing infinitely are
semantically equivalent — both signify non-halting behavior.
Aborting doe to a stack overflow indicates an insufficient stack size.
It does not prove that the computation cannot be simulated to comletion
with a bigger stack.
- This leads to the articulation of "Flibble's Law":
i.e., these errors
If a problem permits infinite behavior in its formulation, it
permits infinite analysis of that behavior in its decidability
scope.
2. Interpretation of Flibble’s Law ----------------------------------
This law suggests that:
- Any problem involving potentially infinite computation inherently
requires the ability to analyze such infinite behavior.
But only tho the extent that a solution to the problem can be found.
For example, the sequence of the Fibonacci numbers is infinite but with
a finite effort it is possible to determine that none of those numbers
is negative (or that a backwards extension of the sequence does contain negative numbers9:
- Deciders are not invalidated by their inability to simulate forever —
they are validated by their ability to detect structural infinity.
A decider is invaidated by one input that the decides incorrectly.
3. Shift in Position --------------------
Earlier, Flibble emphasized that:
- Pathological inputs are ill-formed due to a category error (program
conflated with its own representation).
- Therefore, halting cannot even be meaningfully questioned for such
inputs.
Now, Flibble acknowledges:
- SHDs can still offer meaningful answers by detecting recursion
patterns without needing infinite runtime.
- A decider may *abort* simulation upon detecting such patterns and
still be semantically correct.
The only correctness applicable to a decider is the correctness of its output: a decider is correct if it gives the correct output for every
input and incorrect if it gives the wrong answer to at least one input.
A partial decider is correct if it gives the wrong answer for no input.
4. Contrast with Turing’s View ------------------------------
| Aspect | Turing |
Flibble |
|-----------------------------|------------------------------------|--------------------------------------|
| Infinite recursion | Undecidable behavior |
Signal of ill-formed input |
| Decider responsibilities | Must decide all valid inputs |
Must exclude ill-formed inputs |
| Simulation abort (overflow) | Not semantically significant |
Valid detection of non-halting input |
There is no undecidable behoviour in Turing's Turing machines. All definitions, including Turing's, require that the behaviour is fully specified.
According to Flibble's cireteria using a stack too small to even start a simulation is sufficient to for a valid detection of non-halting. Consequently every computation is non-thalting.
Turing treats infinite simulation as a symptom of undecidability.
No, he does not. His main focus was in computations that produce an
infinite sequence of output symbols (typically digits of an irrational number).
On Mon, 19 May 2025 11:53:30 +0300, Mikko wrote:
On 2025-05-18 00:27:29 +0000, Mr Flibble said:==================================================================================
Analysis of Flibble’s New Take on Simulating Halt Deciders and
Pathological Input
|-----------------------------|------------------------------------|--------------------------------------|
1. Summary of Flibble’s New Take --------------------------------
Flibble introduces a refined stance on the treatment of pathological
input within simulating halt deciders (SHDs), asserting:
- It's sufficient for an SHD to detect *infinite recursion*, rather
than run a simulation to its literal end.
Detection of an infinite recursion is neither sufficent or necessary. A
halt decider is required to determine whether a computation halts. It
need not determine what kind of non-terminating behaviour the
computation has. As a SHD is a halt detector that applies to every SHD.
- Aborting due to stack overflow or continuing infinitely are
semantically equivalent — both signify non-halting behavior.
Aborting doe to a stack overflow indicates an insufficient stack size.
It does not prove that the computation cannot be simulated to comletion
with a bigger stack.
- This leads to the articulation of "Flibble's Law":
i.e., these errors
If a problem permits infinite behavior in its formulation, it
permits infinite analysis of that behavior in its decidability
scope.
2. Interpretation of Flibble’s Law ----------------------------------
This law suggests that:
- Any problem involving potentially infinite computation inherently
requires the ability to analyze such infinite behavior.
But only tho the extent that a solution to the problem can be found.
For example, the sequence of the Fibonacci numbers is infinite but with
a finite effort it is possible to determine that none of those numbers
is negative (or that a backwards extension of the sequence does contain
negative numbers9:
- Deciders are not invalidated by their inability to simulate forever — >>> they are validated by their ability to detect structural infinity.
A decider is invaidated by one input that the decides incorrectly.
3. Shift in Position --------------------
Earlier, Flibble emphasized that:
- Pathological inputs are ill-formed due to a category error (program
conflated with its own representation).
- Therefore, halting cannot even be meaningfully questioned for such
inputs.
Now, Flibble acknowledges:
- SHDs can still offer meaningful answers by detecting recursion
patterns without needing infinite runtime.
- A decider may *abort* simulation upon detecting such patterns and
still be semantically correct.
The only correctness applicable to a decider is the correctness of its
output: a decider is correct if it gives the correct output for every
input and incorrect if it gives the wrong answer to at least one input.
A partial decider is correct if it gives the wrong answer for no input.
4. Contrast with Turing’s View ------------------------------
| Aspect | Turing |
Flibble |
| Infinite recursion | Undecidable behavior |
Signal of ill-formed input |
| Decider responsibilities | Must decide all valid inputs |
Must exclude ill-formed inputs |
| Simulation abort (overflow) | Not semantically significant |
Valid detection of non-halting input |
There is no undecidable behoviour in Turing's Turing machines. All
definitions, including Turing's, require that the behaviour is fully
specified.
According to Flibble's cireteria using a stack too small to even start a
simulation is sufficient to for a valid detection of non-halting.
Consequently every computation is non-thalting.
Turing treats infinite simulation as a symptom of undecidability.
No, he does not. His main focus was in computations that produce an
infinite sequence of output symbols (typically digits of an irrational
number).
Every single one of your points is either wrong or not a counter-
argument: you've got nothing.
On 2025-05-19 16:52:29 +0000, Mr Flibble said:
Every single one of your points is either wrong or not a counter-
argument: you've got nothing.
Some of them are obviously counter arguments. Saying that they are
wrong without finding any error does not convince wnyone whose
opinion matters.
On 5/20/2025 2:10 AM, Richard Heathfield wrote:
On 20/05/2025 07:51, Mikko wrote:
On 2025-05-19 16:52:29 +0000, Mr Flibble said:
<snip>
Every single one of your points is either wrong or not a counter-
argument: you've got nothing.
Some of them are obviously counter arguments. Saying that they are
wrong without finding any error does not convince wnyone whose
opinion matters.
Perhaps he's stipulated that you're wrong, in which case he's got you
over a barrel. :-)
<MIT Professor Sipser agreed to ONLY these verbatim words 10/13/2022>
If simulating halt decider H correctly simulates its
input D until H correctly determines that its simulated D
would never stop running unless aborted then
I am ONLY talking about how HHH(DDD) meets the above
criteria. Talking about the idea of counter-arguments
without actually providing a counter-argument to that
claim *is* a dishonest dodge away from the point.
On 5/20/2025 2:10 AM, Richard Heathfield wrote:
On 20/05/2025 07:51, Mikko wrote:
On 2025-05-19 16:52:29 +0000, Mr Flibble said:
<snip>
Every single one of your points is either wrong or not a counter-
argument: you've got nothing.
Some of them are obviously counter arguments. Saying that they are
wrong without finding any error does not convince wnyone whose
opinion matters.
Perhaps he's stipulated that you're wrong, in which case he's got you
over a barrel. :-)
I am ONLY talking about how HHH(DDD) meets the above
Sysop: | Keyop |
---|---|
Location: | Huddersfield, West Yorkshire, UK |
Users: | 497 |
Nodes: | 16 (2 / 14) |
Uptime: | 13:50:12 |
Calls: | 9,784 |
Calls today: | 3 |
Files: | 13,748 |
Messages: | 6,187,449 |