• Seven deadly sins of set theory

    From WM@21:1/5 to All on Thu Jan 4 09:59:24 2024
    1. Scrooge McDuck's bankrupt

    Scrooge Mc Duck earns 1000 $ daily and spends only 1 $ per day. As a cartoon-figure he will live forever and his wealth will increase without
    bound. But according to set theory he will get bankrupt if he spends the dollars in the same order as he receives them. Only if he always spends
    them in another order, for instance every day the second dollar
    received, he will get rich. These different results prove set theory to
    be useless for all practical purposes.

    The above story is only the story of Tristram Shandy in simplified
    terms, which has been narrated by Fraenkel, one of the fathers of ZF set theory.

    "Well known is the story of Tristram Shandy who undertakes to write his biography, in fact so pedantically, that the description of each day
    takes him a full year. Of course he will never get ready if continuing
    that way. But if he lived infinitely long (for instance a 'countable
    infinity' of years [...]), then his biography would get 'ready',
    because, expressed more precisely, every day of his life, how late ever, finally would get its description because the year scheduled for this
    work would some time appear in his life." [A. Fraenkel: "Einleitung in
    die Mengenlehre", 3rd ed., Springer, Berlin (1928) p. 24] "If he is
    mortal he can never terminate; but did he live forever then no part of
    his biography would remain unwritten, for to each day of his life a year devoted to that day's description would correspond." [A.A. Fraenkel, A.
    Levy: "Abstract set theory", 4th ed., North Holland, Amsterdam (1976) p.
    30]

    2. Failed enumeration of the fractions

    All natural numbers are said to be enough to index all positive
    fractions. This can be disproved when the natural numbers are taken from
    the first column of the matrix of all positive fractions

    1/1, 1/2, 1/3, 1/4, ...
    2/1, 2/2, 2/3, 2/4, ...
    3/1, 3/2, 3/3, 3/4, ...
    4/1, 4/2, 4/3, 4/4, ...
    .. .

    To cover the whole matrix by the integer fractions amounts to the idea
    that the letters X in

    XOOO...
    XOOO...
    XOOO...
    XOOO...
    ..

    can be redistributed to cover all positions by exchanging them with the
    letters O. (X and O must be exchanged because where an index has left,
    there is no index remaining.) But where should the O remain if not
    within the matrix at positions not covered by X?

    3. Violation of translation invariance

    Translation invariance is fundamental to every scientific theory. With n
    m ∈ ℕ and q ∈ {ℚ ∩ (0, 1]} there is precisely the same number of rational points n + q in (n, n+1] as of rational points m + q in (m,
    m+1] . However, half of all positive rational numbers of Cantor's
    enumeration
    1/1, 1/2, 2/1, 1/3, 2/2, 3/1, 1/4, 2/3, 3/2, 4/1, 1/5, 2/4, 3/3, 4/2,
    5/1, ...
    are of the form 0 + q and lie in the first unit interval between 0 and
    1. There are less rational points in (1, 2] but more than in (2, 3] and
    so on.

    4. Violation of inclusion monotony

    Every endsegment E(n) = {n, n+1, n+2, ...} of natural numbers has an
    infinite intersection with all other infinite endsegments.
    ∀k ∈ ℕ_def: ∩{E(1), E(2), ..., E(k)} = E(k) /\ |E(k)| = ℵ₀ .
    Set theory however comes to the conclusion that there are only infinite endsegments and that their intersection is empty. This violates the
    inclusion monotony of the endegments according to which, as long as only non-empty endsegments are concerned, their intersection is non-empty.

    5. Actual infinity implies a smallest unit fraction

    All unit fractions 1/n have finite distances from each other
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) = d_n > 0.
    Therefore the function Number of Unit Fractions between 0 and x, NUF(x),
    cannot be infinite for all x > 0. The claim of set theory
    ∀x ∈ (0, 1]: NUF(x) = ℵo
    is wrong. If every positive point has ℵo unit fractions at its left-hand side, then there is no positive point with less than ℵo unit fractions
    at its left-hand side, then all positive points have ℵo unit fractions
    at their left-hand side, then the interval (0, 1] has ℵo unit fractions
    at its left-hand side, then ℵo unit fractions are negative.
    Contradiction.

    6. There are more path than nodes in the infinite Binary Tree

    Since each of n paths in the complete infinite Binary Tree contains at
    least one node differing from all other paths, there are not less nodes
    than paths possible. Everything else would amount to having more houses
    than bricks.

    7. The diagonal does not define a number

    An endless digit sequence without finite definition of the digits cannot
    define a real number. After every known digit almost all digits will
    follow.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From immibis@21:1/5 to All on Thu Jan 4 22:53:25 2024
    On 1/4/24 10:59, WM wrote:
    [snip]

    what point are you trying to make? infinity is strange

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to immibis on Fri Jan 5 10:22:57 2024
    immibis schrieb am Donnerstag, 4. Januar 2024 um 22:53:35 UTC+1:

    what point are you trying to make? infinity is strange

    But it is based on logic. This logic is violated in the seven points I
    made.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Fri Jan 5 10:04:36 2024
    On 1/5/24 5:22 AM, WM wrote:
    immibis schrieb am Donnerstag, 4. Januar 2024 um 22:53:35 UTC+1:

    what point are you trying to make? infinity is strange

    But it is based on logic. This logic is violated in the seven points I
    made.

    Regards, WM

    Which are base on logic that doesn't handle infinity.

    Yes, it is well know that infinite sets break some of the seemingly
    obvious properties that hold for finite sets.

    YOU just don't seem to understand and accept that fact, and keep on
    making the ERROR of asuming it must.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Fri Jan 5 13:32:12 2024
    On 1/4/2024 4:59 AM, WM wrote:

    7. The diagonal does not define a number

    An endless digit sequence without
    finite definition of the digits
    cannot define a real number.
    After every known digit
    almost all digits will follow.

    After every known and unknown digit,
    almost all digits follow.

    For each digit in the sequence,
    the cardinal of digits.before is ⁺¹.able,
    the cardinal of digits.after is
    larger than each ⁺¹.able cardinal,
    and thus is not.⁺¹.able.


    It is sufficient that
    an endless digit sequence without
    finite definition of the digits
    exist.

    There is at most one real number
    which is permitted by each
    finite initial sub.sequence of digits.
    That one real number is the one which
    the endless digit sequence represents.

    | Assume otherwise.
    | Assume two points at a distance d > 0
    | are permitted by each
    | finite initial sub.sequence of digits.
    |
    | However,
    | there is an initial n.digit sub.sequence which
    | permits only points apart by 10-n < d
    | Those two points cannot both be permitted
    | by that n.digit sub.sequence or
    | by each finite initial sub.sequence.
    | Contradiction.

    Therefore,
    there is at most one real number
    which is permitted by each
    finite initial sub.sequence of digits.

    Also,
    there is at least one real number
    which is permitted by each
    finite initial sub.sequence of digits.

    That follows from the requirement that
    functions which jump
    are discontinuous at some point.

    For each endless digit sequence,
    each digit preceded by ⁺¹.ably.many digits,
    there is no more and no less than
    one point.

    For each point,
    there is no less than one and
    no more than one
    (no more than two for trailing 0's and 9's)
    endless digit sequence,
    each digit preceded by ⁺¹.ably.many digits,

    The representation of real points by digits
    is obviously cousin to
    the representation of rational points by digits.

    However, the cousins are not the same.
    The points _exist_
    The digit.sequences _exist_
    We know that by augmenting descriptive claims
    with only not.first.false claims.
    That isn't a calculation in the sense that
    a rational point is calculated.

    Nevertheless, we know they exist, uncalculated,
    because we know that
    a finite sequence of _claims_
    if it has no first.false _claim_
    has no false _claim_

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Sat Jan 6 14:29:22 2024
    On 1/5/2024 5:58 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On Friday, January 5, 2024
    at 10:32:19 AM UTC-8, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 1/4/2024 4:59 AM, WM wrote:

    An endless digit sequence without
    finite definition of the digits
    cannot define a real number.
    After every known digit
    almost all digits will follow.

    The representation of real points by digits
    is obviously cousin to
    the representation of rational points by digits.

    However, the cousins are not the same.
    The points _exist_
    The digit.sequences _exist_
    We know that by augmenting descriptive claims
    with only not.first.false claims.
    That isn't a calculation in the sense that
    a rational point is calculated.

    Nevertheless, we know they exist, uncalculated,
    because we know that
    a finite sequence of _claims_
    if it has no first.false _claim_
    has no false _claim_

    If it's sufficient
    to establish a model of arithmetic
    then by the GIT's
    you'll agree it's at best incomplete.

    I'm not sure we're on the same page
    with regard to incompleteness.

    Incomplete == some things we can't know.
    Were you (RF) seriously contemplating
    not (some things we can't know)?

    Gödel didn't surprise with the result itself.
    Yes, some things we can't know. Whatever.
    Gödel surprised with _proving_ it.
    | On Formally Undecidable Propositions of
    | Principia Mathematica and Related Systems
    |
    _Formally_ undecidable.

    ----
    If a theory has a model,
    then it's consistent.

    If a theory can express
    recursive definitions
    non.recursively
    (re.stated without the defined term)
    (which is something arithmetic can do),
    then
    the theory can _quote_
    recursive definitions of
    what it is to be a formula and
    what it is to be a proof.

    By "quote", I mean: represent
    an object of language (formula, proof) by
    an object of study (number, set)
    (Gödel.numbers et al)

    If a theory can quote
    what it is to be a formula and
    what it is to be a proof,
    then the theory can express G(x) such that
    G("H(x)") ⟹ proof of H("H(x)") not.exists.
    ¬G("H(x)") ⟹ proof of contradiction exists.

    If a theory can express G("H(x)")
    then the theory can express G("G(x)")
    G("G(x)") ⟹ proof of G("G(x)") not.exists.
    ¬G("G(x)") ⟹ proof of contradiction exists.

    If a theory has a certain
    very.attainable level of expressiveness,
    then choose one: incomplete or inconsistent.

    But there is a model. It's consistent.
    So, it's incomplete.

    ... That it's false to say
    it's, the "true", claim.
    Only scientific and not falsified.

    Platonism then sort of demands
    "there are true numbers, so work it up".

    "There is no 'but', only 'yet', ...."

    We know that
    each theory is true of
    whatever that theory is true of.

    Some theories are true of nothing.
    Contradictions can be proved in those.

    Some theories are true of something,
    of what we intend or of something unintended.
    Contradictions cannot be proved in those.

    Some theories, numbers, for example,
    if they can prove they're consistent,
    would prove that they _aren't_ consistent.

    There is no "yet" to not.proving consistency.
    We know there is no such proof --
    or, if (sadly) there is, it's meaningless,
    about nothing.

    However,
    there are better options than
    a theory proving itself consistent.

    Gödel's work does not deny that
    some other theory can prove
    our theory consistent.

    For example,
    ZFC is a theorem of
    ZFC+inaccessible.cardinal.exists

    Some theories are so simple that,
    even though we know there is no proof,
    we don't take seriously the possibility
    that they have no model.

    For example,
    the set.theory fragment,
    -- {} exists
    -- x∪{y} exists
    -- same.element.sets x and y are equal
    proves arithmetic and Gödel.incompleteness

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Mon Jan 8 10:40:26 2024
    Le 05/01/2024 à 16:04, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/5/24 5:22 AM, WM wrote:
    immibis schrieb am Donnerstag, 4. Januar 2024 um 22:53:35 UTC+1:

    what point are you trying to make? infinity is strange

    But it is based on logic. This logic is violated in the seven points I
    made.

    Which are base on logic that doesn't handle infinity.

    This logic is indispensable.

    Yes, it is well know that infinite sets break some of the seemingly
    obvious properties that hold for finite sets.

    But it has not yet been recognized that ZF breaks indispensable laws of
    logic.

    YOU just don't seem to understand and accept that fact, and keep on
    making the ERROR of asuming it must.

    That is not an error. It shows that ZF could never acquire any relevance
    for reality where the basic laws of logic are referenced. It shows that ZF
    is only a religion to be believed by its proponents and poor captured
    students.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Mon Jan 8 12:18:54 2024
    Le 05/01/2024 à 19:32, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 1/4/2024 4:59 AM, WM wrote:

    7. The diagonal does not define a number

    An endless digit sequence without
    finite definition of the digits
    cannot define a real number.
    After every known digit
    almost all digits will follow.

    It is sufficient that
    an endless digit sequence without
    finite definition of the digits
    exist.

    No. Even and endless digit sequence does not describe an irrational
    number. The irrational number is the limit only. Compare 0.999... which
    does not contain 1 but only has the limit 1.

    There is at most one real number
    which is permitted by each
    finite initial sub.sequence of digits.

    There are infinitely many. Therefore it is impossible to decide which real number is described.

    Therefore,
    there is at most one real number
    which is permitted by each
    finite initial sub.sequence of digits.

    By each defined digit sequence infinitely many numbers are permitted.
    And the dark digits cannot describe any real number.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Mon Jan 8 07:21:19 2024
    On 1/8/24 5:40 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 05/01/2024 à 16:04, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/5/24 5:22 AM, WM wrote:
    immibis schrieb am Donnerstag, 4. Januar 2024 um 22:53:35 UTC+1:

    what point are you trying to make? infinity is strange

    But it is based on logic. This logic is violated in the seven points
    I made.

    Which are base on logic that doesn't handle infinity.

    This logic is indispensable.

    Maybe for your small mind.



    Yes, it is well know that infinite sets break some of the seemingly
    obvious properties that hold for finite sets.

    But it has not yet been recognized that ZF breaks indispensable laws of logic.


    No, it shows that some supposed laws of logic can't handle unbounded sets.


    YOU just don't seem to understand and accept that fact, and keep on
    making the ERROR of asuming it must.

    That is not an error. It shows that ZF could never acquire any relevance
    for reality where the basic laws of logic are referenced. It shows that
    ZF is only a religion to be believed by its proponents and poor captured students.

    Regards, WM



    In other words, you don't understand what it says so you ignore it.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Mon Jan 8 13:46:21 2024
    On 1/8/2024 7:18 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 05/01/2024 à 19:32, Jim Burns a écrit :

    An endless digit sequence without
    finite definition of the digits
    cannot define a real number.
    After every known digit
    almost all digits will follow.

    There is at most one real number
    which is permitted by each
    finite initial sub.sequence of digits.

    There are infinitely many.

    Assume there are two permitted points.
    Each power 10⁻ⁿ is larger than their distance,
    a positive distance d > 0 apart.

    β ≥ d > 0 is the least upper bound of
    distances which each 10⁻ⁿ is larger than.

    10β > β is not
    a distance which each 10⁻ⁿ is larger than.
    Thus b exists: 10⁻ᵇ < 10β

    β/10 < β is
    a distance which each 10⁻ⁿ is larger than.
    Thus, in particular,
    β/10 < 10⁻ᵇ⁻²

    However,
    (10⁻ᵇ)/100 < (10β)/100
    10⁻ᵇ⁻² < β/10
    Contradiction.

    Therefore,
    there _aren't_ two points which
    are permitted by each
    finite initial sub.sequence of
    the endless digit sequence.

    Therefore it is impossible to decide which
    real number is described.

    Whether or not we describe these points,
    these points _exist_
    no more than one point to each
    endless digit sequence.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Tue Jan 9 17:40:55 2024
    Le 08/01/2024 à 19:46, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 1/8/2024 7:18 AM, WM wrote:


    Therefore it is impossible to decide which
    real number is described.

    Whether or not we describe these points,
    these points _exist_
    no more than one point to each
    endless digit sequence.

    Dark numbers, dark points and dark parts of infinite sequences exist. But
    we cannot distinguish and use them. And we can prove that there are not
    more irrational numbers than rational numbers. Just today I showed some
    proofs to my students. One is this: Between ***every*** pair of irrational numbers there is a rational number. Another one, which was very well
    received, is the game Conquer the Binay Tree:

    You start with one cent, buy a path in the Binary Tree and get one cent
    for every covered node. Then you buy another path and get one cent for
    every node not yet covered by the first path. You will never earn less
    than one cent, because every path is distinct by at least one node from
    every other path. Therefore you will not get bankrupt. But if there were
    more paths than nodes, you would get bankrupt. Hence Cantor is defeated.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Tue Jan 9 14:34:11 2024
    On 1/9/2024 12:40 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 08/01/2024 à 19:46, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 1/8/2024 7:18 AM, WM wrote:

    An endless digit sequence without
    finite definition of the digits
    cannot define a real number.
    After every known digit
    almost all digits will follow.

    There is at most one real number
    which is permitted by each
    finite initial sub.sequence of digits.

    There are infinitely many.

    Therefore it is impossible to decide
    which real number is described.

    Whether or not we describe these points,
    these points _exist_
    no more than one point to each
    endless digit sequence.

    Dark numbers, dark points
    and dark parts of infinite sequences
    exist.

    Elsewhere, you have told us that
    darkᵂᴹ numbers and their ilk
    are never one step away from
    visibleᵂᴹ numbers and their ilk.

    I'll clarify.
    There is at most one point
    which is permitted by each
    finite initial sub.sequence of
    visibleᵂᴹ digits.

    Because,
    if there are two permitted points,
    there is a positive least upper bound β of
    distances < each visibleᵂᴹ 10⁻ⁿ
    β/10 < β < 10β
    and visibleᵂᴹ 10⁻ᵇ < 10β
    and visibleᵂᴹ 10⁻ᵇ⁻² > β/10
    but also
    10⁻ᵇ/100 < 10β/100
    10⁻ᵇ⁻² < β/10
    Contradiction.
    Thus,
    not two.

    Just today I showed some proofs to my students.

    If you are claiming your students for
    some form of peer.review, then
    you are accepting pre-calculus students as
    _peers_

    I won't object if you choose to do that.
    I just want to make sure you understand that
    they are who you are accepting as peers.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Wed Jan 10 00:49:16 2024
    On 1/9/2024 6:29 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On Tuesday, January 9, 2024
    at 11:34:19 AM UTC-8, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 1/9/2024 12:40 PM, WM wrote:

    Just today I showed some proofs to my students.

    If you are claiming your students for
    some form of peer.review, then
    you are accepting pre-calculus students as
    _peers_

    Everybody knows
    the entire point of pre-calculus is
    to make it clear that the usual notion of
    an Aristotelean continuum, [...]

    I could have said that better.

    In that post,
    the only thing I meant by "pre-calculus"
    was "having not yet been a calculus student".
    I wasn't thinking of "being a student in
    the course just before calculus".

    Calculus and WM's dark.number game
    make a poor fit together.
    I expect WM to agree with that much,
    even if he and I assign blame for
    the poor fit differently.

    I haven't actually heard from anyone that
    WM's students are not.yet.calculus.
    It only seems to me as though they must be.

    Sorry for any confusion.


    One sentence:

    Everybody knows
    the entire point of pre-calculus is
    to make it clear that
    the usual notion of
    an Aristotelean continuum,
    which is about
    the most usual sort of intuition about
    the continuum after constant motion,
    and
    the course-of-passage as through
    points in a line,
    is
    gently shushing that down for
    students who do have
    such an intuitive notion of
    analytical character,
    and then
    explaining for all
    that the usual laws of
    arithmetic and delta-epsilonics,
    together,
    make for defining infinite limit.

    Gently shushing down notions which are
    not the preferred notions
    is the purpose for which we hold classes.

    If it can be done,
    I think that
    giving the reasons that
    some other notion is preferred
    can be an excellent strategy for
    effective gentle.shushing.down.

    However,
    in some instances,
    we are, today, looking at preferences
    resulting from resolution of a long controversy
    between brilliant people
    encyclopedically educated in their field.

    Should we ask students,
    upon their first contact with that field,
    to reproduce
    the best of that field?

    If that is a reasonable ask,
    that would be wonderful to see.

    However,
    it might well not.be a reasonable ask.

    It might well be necessary for
    students to _trust_ that
    reasons exist for preferring
    one set of notions over
    another,
    to trust, at least,
    until they acquire their own
    brilliance and
    encyclopedic knowledge.

    My own preference is
    to share the beauty in
    these deep notions,
    with all and sundry,
    with those with only
    a momentary interest.

    However,
    I have to recognize that
    I can't always get what I want.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Wed Jan 10 19:04:19 2024
    Le 09/01/2024 à 20:34, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 1/9/2024 12:40 PM, WM wrote:

    Just today I showed some proofs to my students.

    If you are claiming your students for
    some form of peer.review, then
    you are accepting pre-calculus students as
    _peers_

    Nonsense. There are 8th semester informatics and engineering studens. They
    know mathematics very well (that which Cantor is not needed for, according
    to Feferman) but they do not use matheology. Try to show how the player
    gets bankrupt in the game "We conquer the Binary Tree".

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Wed Jan 10 19:14:29 2024
    Le 10/01/2024 à 06:49, Jim Burns a écrit :

    Calculus and WM's dark.number game
    make a poor fit together.

    Of course. Calculus uses potential infinity only. Dark numbers can exist
    only in actual infinity, the complement of potential infinity.
    Feferman's book In the light of logic answers the question: Is Cantor
    necessary for the maths of the real world? with a resounding no.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Wed Jan 10 19:49:31 2024
    On 1/10/24 2:14 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 10/01/2024 à 06:49, Jim Burns a écrit :

    Calculus and WM's dark.number game
    make a poor fit together.

    Of course. Calculus uses potential infinity only. Dark numbers can exist
    only in actual infinity, the complement of potential infinity.
    Feferman's book In the light of logic answers the question: Is Cantor necessary for the maths of the real world? with a resounding no.

    Regards, WM

    But you claim them to be part of the sets that are only "Potential
    Infinity", or are you retracting that claim. (All Natural Numbers are
    only by your definition "Potentially Infinite")

    All members of the Natural Numbers are Finite, so none of them are
    "Actually Infinite".

    The set of them has a SIZE that is infinite, but none of the members of
    it ever are.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Wed Jan 10 20:32:16 2024
    On 1/10/24 8:10 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On Wednesday, January 10, 2024 at 4:49:39 PM UTC-8, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 1/10/24 2:14 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 10/01/2024 à 06:49, Jim Burns a écrit :

    Calculus and WM's dark.number game
    make a poor fit together.

    Of course. Calculus uses potential infinity only. Dark numbers can exist >>> only in actual infinity, the complement of potential infinity.
    Feferman's book In the light of logic answers the question: Is Cantor
    necessary for the maths of the real world? with a resounding no.

    Regards, WM
    But you claim them to be part of the sets that are only "Potential
    Infinity", or are you retracting that claim. (All Natural Numbers are
    only by your definition "Potentially Infinite")

    All members of the Natural Numbers are Finite, so none of them are
    "Actually Infinite".

    The set of them has a SIZE that is infinite, but none of the members of
    it ever are.

    The order type of ordinals is an ordinal.

    Finite ordinals as the classes of each those not containing themselves, according to simple quantification or "the set of all sets that don't
    contain themselves", contains itself.

    Such are simple reasons why the infinite integers have an infinite integer.

    Yes I know that ZF two axioms of restriction of comprehension or "don't look" include one that is "there's an infinity that isn't thusly various".

    So, you might find it interesting that in more naive theories,
    it's those one-line proofs as above that do give that there are
    true infinites courtesy the unbounded its quantification.


    Then about MW's "I invoke the Absolute!", it's he's drunk
    then also that potential and actual infinities do have differences
    in real mathematics, one recalls "A Sober Mind Speaks".

    So, RD's "there is only one theory and it ignores all my problems"
    and MWs "there are at least two theories and they don't agree",
    seems for a sort of "yet somehow, there's a theory".

    ... With laws, plural, of large numbers.

    If you want a gentle introduction to set theory,
    try reading Quine's Set Theory then after it introduces
    the class-set distinction and x not in x and x not equals x,
    and why neither of those is first-order in ZF, quit.


    ... in a theory, ....


    I understand the multitude of different ways to define "Numbers", but
    their are a core set of fundamental numbers with basically agreed on definitions, and reasonable people don't try calling something that
    doesn't match the accepted definition as being one of those sets.

    "Natural Numbers" is such a set, and while there may be several ways of expressing its "generation", they all are essentially, you start with a
    base number, called Zero, and then you have an operation, called
    something like Successor, and the set of the Natural Numbers is the set
    of things you get by applying that operation an unlimited number of times.

    Thus, I admit to other number theories, they just are not the "standard" systems of Natural Numbers, Integers, Rational Numbers, or Real Numbers.
    (The Reals have a couple of different generational methods, but they
    result in the same set of numbers with the same basic properties).

    If you want to talk about other systems, feel free, just don't be
    "deceptive" (or lying) and try to use the name for one of the standard sets.

    And most of the "alternative" systems alternative have accepted names
    for them, so that should be used.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Thu Jan 11 07:43:33 2024
    On 1/10/2024 2:04 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 09/01/2024 à 20:34, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 1/9/2024 12:40 PM, WM wrote:

    Just today I showed some proofs
    to my students.

    If you are claiming your students for
    some form of peer.review, then
    you are accepting pre-calculus students as
    _peers_

    Nonsense.
    There are 8th semester informatics and
    engineering studens.

    Perhaps
    the informatics and engineering students of
    Wolfgang Mückenheim of Hochschule Augsburg
    remember their arithmetic.

    kᵢⱼ = i+(i+j-1)(i+j-2)/2

    For each pair ⟨i,j⟩ of visibleᵂᴹ numbers
    there is a unique visibleᵂᴹ number kᵢⱼ

    sₖᵢⱼ = max{h| (h-1)(h-2)/2 < kᵢⱼ}
    iₖᵢⱼ+jₖᵢⱼ = sₖᵢⱼ
    iₖᵢⱼ = kᵢⱼ-(sₖᵢⱼ-1)(sₖᵢⱼ-2)/2
    jₖᵢⱼ = sₖᵢⱼ(sₖᵢⱼ-1)/2-kᵢⱼ+1

    For each visibleᵂᴹ number kᵢⱼ
    there is a unique pair ⟨iₖᵢⱼ,jₖᵢⱼ⟩ of
    visibleᵂᴹ numbers
    ⟨iₖᵢⱼ,jₖᵢⱼ⟩ = ⟨i,j⟩

    There are as many visibleᵂᴹ numbers
    as pairs of visibleᵂᴹ numbers.
    Darkᵂᴹ numbers haven't entered the discussion.

    ----
    For each non-empty split F,H of ⟨0,1,…,n⟩
    some i‖i⁺¹ exists last‖first in F‖H
    F‖H = ⟨0,1,…,i⟩‖⟨i⁺¹,…,n⟩

    0‖n exists first‖last in ⟨0,1,…,n⟩

    ⟨0,1,…,n⟩ can't fit in ⟨1,…,n⟩
    ⟨0,1,…,n⟩ holds only visibleᵂᴹ numbers.

    ℕ contains each ⟨0,1,…,n⟩ and nothing else.
    ℕ\{0} contains each ⟨1,…,n⟩ and nothing else.

    ⟨0,1,…,n⟩ CAN fit in ⟨1,…,n,n⁺¹⟩
    ℕ CAN fit in ℕ\{0}

    If
    darkᵂᴹ numbers are the reason that
    ℕ CAN fit in ℕ\{0}
    then
    they must be
    darkᵂᴹ visibleᵂᴹ in ⟨0,1,…,n⟩ in ℕ

    In WM's scheme,
    _sets_ inform _numbers_ that
    the numbers are darkᵂᴹ
    but we're not permitted to refer to
    these darkᵂᴹ visibleᵂᴹ numbers,
    only to the sets they're in.

    Talking about
    numbers which are darkᵂᴹ
    is really nothing more than talking about
    sets holding numbers which are darkᵂᴹ

    The only use talking about darkᵂᴹ numbers has
    is as a bit of techno.babble
    to fill gaps in the discussion where,
    otherwise, explanation would be expected.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Thu Jan 11 21:38:18 2024
    Le 11/01/2024 à 13:43, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 1/10/2024 2:04 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 09/01/2024 à 20:34, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 1/9/2024 12:40 PM, WM wrote:

    Just today I showed some proofs
    to my students.

    If you are claiming your students for
    some form of peer.review, then
    you are accepting pre-calculus students as
    _peers_

    Nonsense.
    There are 8th semester informatics and
    engineering studens.

    Perhaps
    the informatics and engineering students of
    Wolfgang Mückenheim of Hochschule Augsburg
    remember their arithmetic.

    And now they know:

    kᵢⱼ = i+(i+j-1)(i+j-2)/2

    Every number defined like k does not belong to the domain covered by the smallest
    ℵo unit fractions or by the largest ℵo natural numbers.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Thu Jan 11 16:48:15 2024
    On 1/11/2024 11:49 AM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On Thursday, January 11, 2024
    at 4:43:40 AM UTC-8, Jim Burns wrote:

    [...]

    Then, the idea that there are
    "descriptive dynamics",
    has that
    basically all theories
    formally abstractly symbolically
    result sorts of descriptive theories
    in words, all one theory.

    There is a Swiss.Army.knife theory, which
    provides insight in many, many instances.

    I'm thinking of the theory of
    finite sequences of claims,
    claims which might be about any of
    many, many different domains of discussion.

    We have a lot of confidence that,
    in a finite sequence of claims,
    if there is a false claim,
    then there is a first.false claim.

    Join that to our ability to _see_
    in some sequences,
    that some claims are not.first.false,
    such as Q in ⟨ Q∨¬P P Q ⟩
    and
    we know we have, in some instances,
    finite sequences of not.first.false claims,
    which,
    by our Swiss.Army.knife theory,
    are finite sequences of not.false claims.

    Even if
    we can't see the objects of our claims,
    we know they are true claims.
    That seems magical to me --
    "magical" perhaps not the best word for
    mathematics, science, and engineering,
    but there it is.

    This Swiss.Army.knife theory of
    finite sequences of claims
    might be something like
    what you (RF) mean by One Theory.
    Or it might not be.

    ----
    An essential step in using the Swiss.Army.knife
    is description.
    We decide to learn about widgets.
    _We describe a widget_
    We follow with not.first.false claims
    about widgets, which,
    because they are in that sequence,
    we know are true about widgets.
    Success.

    That works because there are
    pre.known claims about widgets mixed in.
    That makes our post.known claims
    specific to widgets _which we want_
    since widgets are different from non.widgets.

    But the pre.known claims are widget theory,
    not the One Theory.
    If we replace claims about widgets with
    claims about anything,
    following claims not.first.false about anything
    shouldn't be telling us anything useful or
    interesting, should it?
    I don't see how it could.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Thu Jan 11 18:34:15 2024
    On 1/11/2024 4:38 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 11/01/2024 à 13:43, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 1/10/2024 2:04 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 09/01/2024 à 20:34, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 1/9/2024 12:40 PM, WM wrote:

    Just today I showed some proofs
    to my students.

    If you are claiming your students for
    some form of peer.review, then
    you are accepting pre-calculus students as
    _peers_

    Nonsense.
    There are 8th semester informatics and
    engineering studens.

    Perhaps
    the informatics and engineering students of
    Wolfgang Mückenheim of Hochschule Augsburg
    remember their arithmetic.

    And now they know:

    kᵢⱼ = i+(i+j-1)(i+j-2)/2

    Every number defined like k
    does not belong to the domain covered by
    the smallest ℵo unit fractions or by
    the largest ℵo natural numbers.

    Perhaps
    the informatics and engineering students of
    Wolfgang Mückenheim of Hochschule Augsburg
    remember that,
    in arithmetic,
    the unit fractions and natural numbers
    are closed under addition, subtraction,
    multiplication, and division.

    Since you (WM) have decided that
    you are talking about _not.arithmetic_
    this might be an especially apt time
    for your students to remember that
    a claim about _not.arithmetic_
    even if it were _true_
    doesn't contradict a claim about _arithmetic_

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to FromTheRafters on Thu Jan 11 19:56:35 2024
    On 1/11/2024 7:14 PM, FromTheRafters wrote:
    Jim Burns has brought this to us :
    On 1/11/2024 4:38 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 11/01/2024 à 13:43, Jim Burns a écrit :

    kᵢⱼ = i+(i+j-1)(i+j-2)/2

    Every number defined like k
    does not belong to the domain covered by
    the smallest ℵo unit fractions or by
    the largest ℵo natural numbers.

    Perhaps
    the informatics and engineering students of
    Wolfgang Mückenheim of Hochschule Augsburg
    remember that,
    in arithmetic,
    the unit fractions and natural numbers
    are closed under addition, subtraction,
    multiplication, and division.

    Since you (WM) have decided that
    you are talking about _not.arithmetic_
    this might be an especially apt time
    for your students to remember that
    a claim about _not.arithmetic_
    even if it were _true_
    doesn't contradict a claim about _arithmetic_

    Subtraction?

    I may have been a little loose in
    how I said that.

    The operations are closed in _arithmetic_
    except for division by 0.

    There is
    no single ℵ₀.set of smallest unit fractions and
    no single ℵ₀.set of largest natural numbers.

    There is,
    for each pair ⟨i,j⟩ of visibleᵂᴹ numbers
    a unique visibleᵂᴹ number kᵢⱼ
    and,
    for each visibleᵂᴹ number kᵢⱼ
    a unique pair ⟨iₖᵢⱼ,jₖᵢⱼ⟩ of visibleᵂᴹ numbers ⟨iₖᵢⱼ,jₖᵢⱼ⟩ = ⟨i,j⟩

    There are as many visibleᵂᴹ numbers
    as pairs of visibleᵂᴹ numbers.
    Darkᵂᴹ numbers haven't entered the discussion.

    kᵢⱼ = i+(i+j-1)(i+j-2)/2

    sₖᵢⱼ = max{h| (h-1)(h-2)/2 < kᵢⱼ}
    iₖᵢⱼ+jₖᵢⱼ = sₖᵢⱼ
    iₖᵢⱼ = kᵢⱼ-(sₖᵢⱼ-1)(sₖᵢⱼ-2)/2
    jₖᵢⱼ = sₖᵢⱼ(sₖᵢⱼ-1)/2-kᵢⱼ+1

    Because arithmetic.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Thu Jan 11 22:09:05 2024
    On 1/11/24 4:38 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 11/01/2024 à 13:43, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 1/10/2024 2:04 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 09/01/2024 à 20:34, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 1/9/2024 12:40 PM, WM wrote:

    Just today I showed some proofs
    to my students.

    If you are claiming your students for
    some form of peer.review, then
    you are accepting pre-calculus students as
    _peers_

    Nonsense.
    There are 8th semester informatics and
    engineering studens.

    Perhaps
    the informatics and engineering students of
    Wolfgang Mückenheim of Hochschule Augsburg
    remember their arithmetic.

    And now they know:

    kᵢⱼ = i+(i+j-1)(i+j-2)/2

    Every number defined like k does not belong to the domain covered by the smallest
    ℵo unit fractions or by the largest ℵo natural numbers.

    Regards, WM



    Which of those largest natural numbers can k not get to?

    What is the boundry that can not be passed?

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Fri Jan 12 00:09:28 2024
    On 1/11/2024 8:54 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On Thursday, January 11, 2024
    at 4:56:46 PM UTC-8, Jim Burns wrote:

    There are as many visibleᵂᴹ numbers
    as pairs of visibleᵂᴹ numbers.
    Darkᵂᴹ numbers haven't entered the discussion.
    kᵢⱼ = i+(i+j-1)(i+j-2)/2
    sₖᵢⱼ = max{h| (h-1)(h-2)/2 < kᵢⱼ}
    iₖᵢⱼ+jₖᵢⱼ = sₖᵢⱼ
    iₖᵢⱼ = kᵢⱼ-(sₖᵢⱼ-1)(sₖᵢⱼ-2)/2
    jₖᵢⱼ = sₖᵢⱼ(sₖᵢⱼ-1)/2-kᵢⱼ+1
    Because arithmetic.

    What you can do is
    define arithmetic just a little
    differently than usual, that instead
    of Peano/Presburger,
    addition and multiplication,
    and their inverses,
    is that what you do is
    start with increment and division.

    Julia Robinson has a paper showing how
    to define various arithmetical concepts
    from each other.

    Definability and decision problems in arithmetic

    | In this paper, we are concerned with
    | the arithmetical definability of certain notions
    | of integers and rationals in terms of other notions.
    | The results derived will be applied to obtain
    | a negative solution of corresponding decision problems.
    |
    | In Section 1, we show that addition of
    | positive integers can be defined arithmetically
    | in terms of multiplication and the unary operation
    | of successor S (where Sa = a + 1). Also, it is shown
    | that both addition and multiplication can be defined
    | arithmetically in terms of successor and
    | the relation of divisibility |
    | (where x|y means x divides y).
    |
    The Journal of Symbolic Logic,
    Volume 14, Issue 2, 23 June 1949, pp. 98 - 114
    DOI: https://doi.org/10.2307/2266510

    That is also interesting because
    some claims become easier or harder to prove,
    starting from order and divisibility or
    from addition and multiplication.

    If I recall correctly,
    unique prime factorization becomes easier
    starting from order and divisibility.

    Then there's as
    increment addition
    multiplication powers
    exponent tetration

    Once we have addition and multiplication,
    however we get them,
    the Chinese remainder theorem can be used
    to encode an arbitrarily.long finite sequence,
    and encoding finite sequences can be used
    to re.phrase recursive definitions
    non.recursively.

    That makes exponentials, factorials,
    tetration, and much, much more
    Free At No Extra Charge.

    Just saying.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Fri Jan 12 14:01:06 2024
    Le 12/01/2024 à 00:34, Jim Burns a écrit :

    Since you (WM) have decided that
    you are talking about _not.arithmetic_
    this might be an especially apt time
    for your students to remember that
    a claim about _not.arithmetic_
    even if it were _true_
    doesn't contradict a claim about _arithmetic_

    That should not hinder an inquisitive student to learn that arithmetic
    does not cover the domain of the smallest ℵo unit fractions and of the largest ℵo natural numbers.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Fri Jan 12 14:05:20 2024
    Le 12/01/2024 à 04:09, Richard Damon a écrit :

    Which of those largest natural numbers can k not get to?

    If I could name it I had made it v isible.

    What is the boundry that can not be passed?

    That is the difficult point: There is no fixed threshold. Most can't
    comprehend it. Potential infinity!

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Fri Jan 12 13:30:21 2024
    On 1/12/2024 9:01 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 12/01/2024 à 00:34, Jim Burns a écrit :

    Since you (WM) have decided that
    you are talking about _not.arithmetic_
    this might be an especially apt time
    for your students to remember that
    a claim about _not.arithmetic_
    even if it were _true_
    doesn't contradict a claim about _arithmetic_

    That should not hinder an inquisitive student
    to learn that
    arithmetic does not cover the domain of
    the smallest ℵo unit fractions and of
    the largest ℵo natural numbers.

    Do your students learn that it doesn't from
    their instructor, from you?

    If they don't,
    that is what strikes me as
    hindering the inquisitive student.

    ----
    We can make a claim true of
    each one of infinitely.many
    which we know is true by knowing
    _that is what we mean_ by
    "natural number" or "unit fraction"
    or something else.

    Also,
    we can make a claim not.first.false of
    each one of the same infinitely.many
    which we know is not.first.false by seeing
    the sequence of claims we make.
    For example, by seeing Q is after P and Q∨¬P

    We can make a finite sequence of claims
    in which each claim is not.first.false of
    each one of the same infinitely.many.
    This is more challenging, but the challenge
    is the reason that mathematicians are
    so famously well-paid.

    A finite sequence in which
    each claim is not.first.false about each
    is finite sequence in which
    each claim is not.false about each.

    That is something we already know
    _about finite sequences of claims_

    By that knowledge,
    we can increase our knowledge of other things:
    natural numbers, unit fractions, and so on
    _looking only at a sequence of claims_
    and NOT looking at
    natural numbers, unit fractions, and so on.

    ----
    We can make a claim that
    k can be counted to
    and know that it is true of
    each which can be counted to.

    We can follow that with the claim that
    k+1 can be counted to
    and see that there is no way in which
    k+1 can be counted to
    can be first.false.

    And, similarly, that
    k isn't the largest which can be counted to.

    That is how we know that
    nothing exists which is the largest which
    can be counted to,
    even though we are finite beings,
    even though we can't see the infinitely.many
    which can be counted to.

    We can see _the claims_
    and recognize that they're not.first.false.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Fri Jan 12 18:46:33 2024
    On 1/12/24 9:05 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 12/01/2024 à 04:09, Richard Damon a écrit :

    Which of those largest natural numbers can k not get to?

    If I could name it I had made it v isible.

    What is the boundry that can not be passed?

    That is the difficult point: There is no fixed threshold. Most can't comprehend it. Potential infinity!

    Regards, WM



    So, you have two distinct sets with no boundry between them?

    What makes them different?

    If there isn't a line that keeps the describable numbers out of your
    dark numbers, then aren't all your dark numbers describable?

    If there is a line, then there must be a highest describable number, so
    you can give it.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Sun Jan 14 16:48:16 2024
    Le 13/01/2024 à 00:46, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/12/24 9:05 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 12/01/2024 à 04:09, Richard Damon a écrit :

    Which of those largest natural numbers can k not get to?

    If I could name it I had made it v isible.

    What is the boundry that can not be passed?

    That is the difficult point: There is no fixed threshold. Most can't
    comprehend it. Potential infinity!

    So, you have two distinct sets with no boundry between them?

    The visible numbers are not a set but only a collection, because the
    membership is not fixed.

    What makes them different?

    This: You cannot use real numbers of the domain containing the ℵ
    smallest unit fractions and of the domain containing the ℵ largest
    natural numbers. It is obviously impossible to come closer to zero. There
    are always ℵ unit fractions between 0 and a number chosen by you. Same
    for ω, but, contrary to zero, ω is a vague end of the scale.

    If there isn't a line that keeps the describable numbers out of your
    dark numbers, then aren't all your dark numbers describable?

    Assume it. Then you can come close to zero such that nothing is between it
    and your chosen number. But that is a contradiction.

    If there is a line, then there must be a highest describable number, so
    you can give it.

    That is the point hard to swallow. There is no line.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Sun Jan 14 16:50:36 2024
    Le 13/01/2024 à 00:46, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/12/24 9:01 AM, WM wrote:
    arithmetic
    does not cover the domain of the smallest ℵo unit fractions and of the
    largest ℵo natural numbers.

    But what arithmetic didn't cover them?

    Addition, subtraction, multiplication, division, exponentiation,
    tetration.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Sun Jan 14 16:43:52 2024
    Le 12/01/2024 à 19:30, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 1/12/2024 9:01 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 12/01/2024 à 00:34, Jim Burns a écrit :

    Since you (WM) have decided that
    you are talking about _not.arithmetic_
    this might be an especially apt time
    for your students to remember that
    a claim about _not.arithmetic_
    even if it were _true_
    doesn't contradict a claim about _arithmetic_

    That should not hinder an inquisitive student
    to learn that
    arithmetic does not cover the domain of
    the smallest ℵo unit fractions and of
    the largest ℵo natural numbers.

    Do your students learn that it doesn't from
    their instructor, from you?

    They need not learn it, because it is clear to everybody, perhaps after a
    short hint: You cannot use real numbers of the domain containing the ℵ smallest unit fractions and of the domain containing the ℵ largest
    natural numbers.

    It is obviously impossible to come closer to zero. There are always ℵ
    unit fractions between 0 and a number chosen by you. Same for ω, but,
    contrary to zero, ω is a vague end of the scale.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Sun Jan 14 13:24:43 2024
    On 1/12/2024 10:18 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On Friday, January 12, 2024
    at 3:46:43 PM UTC-8, Richard Damon wrote:

    [...]

    Sorites and the Heap.

    Make a claim which is true of each
    and leap the Heap.

    There are no standard models of integers.

    The minimal inductive set is
    a standard standard model of integers.

    Are you currently considering
    non.standard standard models of integers?

    There are fragments,

    A fragment isn't a model.

    Granted, there are things other than
    the minimal inductive set.
    But, Shirley, that's not what you mean?

    there are extensions,

    An extension isn't standard.

    Granted, there are things other than
    the minimal inductive set.
    But, Shirley, that's not what you mean?

    the ordinary inductive set's
    a non-logical constant.

    The only place I remember seeing "non-logical"
    (which doesn't mean "illogical") used
    is with axioms _in addition to_ the logical axioms.

    We could call this sense of non-logical
    metalogical, after.logical, which makes it less
    likely to be mistaken for an admission of failure.

    If you (RF) don't mean metalogical, then
    I don't know what you mean by non-logical.


    The unformalizable goal of stating
    metalogical axioms is that everyone can say
    "Yes, that is what everyone means by X".
    That wouldn't be a _logical_ result, but
    it would be a fact about what everyone means.

    For the more obscure X,
    there isn't really an "everyone".
    There is the author, and
    there is what they mean by X

    However, natural numbers aren't obscure.


    For _what we mean by_ the non.negative integers,
    the minimal inductive set is a standard model.

    There are multiple models of integers.

    Have we drifted away from (up.post)
    There are no standard models of integers.
    ?

    What I think we mean, what I know I mean
    by a model of the non.negative integers
    is that it contain at least
    each standard non.negative integer,

    by a standard model of the non.negative integers
    is that it contains no extensions.

    If any model of the non.negative integers exists,
    then a standard model exists, provably.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Sun Jan 14 13:42:23 2024
    On 1/14/24 11:48 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 13/01/2024 à 00:46, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/12/24 9:05 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 12/01/2024 à 04:09, Richard Damon a écrit :

    Which of those largest natural numbers can k not get to?

    If I could name it I had made it v isible.

    What is the boundry that can not be passed?

    That is the difficult point: There is no fixed threshold. Most can't
    comprehend it. Potential infinity!

    So, you have two distinct sets with no boundry between them?

    The visible numbers are not a set but only a collection, because the membership is not fixed.

    What makes them different?

    This: You cannot use real numbers of the domain containing the ℵ
    smallest unit fractions and of the domain containing the ℵ largest
    natural numbers. It is obviously impossible to come closer to zero.
    There are always ℵ unit fractions between 0 and a number chosen by you. Same for ω, but, contrary to zero, ω is a vague end of the scale.

    Really? You can't figure out how to use number like 1/10 or 12?

    After all, those are part of the ℵ unit fractions between some unit
    fraction and 0 and above some Natural Number.

    There are no unit fractions smaller that ALL unit fractions or Natural
    Numbers greater than ALL Natural Numbers, so the domain of numbers that
    you can not use because of that condition is empty.


    If there isn't a line that keeps the describable numbers out of your
    dark numbers, then aren't all your dark numbers describable?

    Assume it. Then you can come close to zero such that nothing is between
    it and your chosen number. But that is a contradiction.

    You can come as close as you want.

    That doesn't means that you can reach the point that nothing is between.

    That would require the existance of a Highest Natural Number.

    That assumption is where the contradiction is, not that all Natural Numbers/Unit Fractions are visible.


    If there is a line, then there must be a highest describable number,
    so you can give it.

    That is the point hard to swallow. There is no line.

    Then all your "dark" numbers are also visible, and thus not Dark.

    Without a line, what keeps the visible numbers out of the set of "Dark" numbers?

    You are just hitting the flaw of naive set theory.


    Regards, WM



    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Sun Jan 14 19:23:58 2024
    On 1/14/2024 11:43 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 12/01/2024 à 19:30, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 1/12/2024 9:01 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 12/01/2024 à 00:34, Jim Burns a écrit :

    Since you (WM) have decided that
    you are talking about _not.arithmetic_
    this might be an especially apt time
    for your students to remember that
    a claim about _not.arithmetic_
    even if it were _true_
    doesn't contradict a claim about _arithmetic_

    That should not hinder an inquisitive student
    to learn that
    arithmetic does not cover the domain of
    the smallest ℵo unit fractions and of
    the largest ℵo natural numbers.

    Do your students learn that it doesn't from
    their instructor, from you?

    They need not learn it,

    Which is to say:
    No,
    you,
    Wolfgang Mückenheim of Hochschule Augsburg,
    do not tell your students that,
    when you talk about
    the smallest ℵ₀ unit fractions and
    the largest ℵ₀ natural numbers,
    you aren't talking about
    arithmetic.

    because it is clear to everybody,
    perhaps after a short hint:
    You cannot use real numbers

    Real numbers ℝ are the rationals ℚ and
    enough points between non.empty splits of ℚ
    that no function ℝ→ℝ which jumps is
    continuous at each point in ℝ

    Rationals ℚ are the integers ℤ and
    enough points that each non.0 division in ℤ
    has a solution in ℚ

    Integers ℤ are the naturals ℕ and
    enough points that each subtraction in ℕ
    has a solution in ℤ

    Naturals ℕ are each end of ordered ⟨0,…,k⟩
    such that,
    for each non.empty split F,H of ⟨0,…,k⟩
    i‖i⁺¹ exists last‖first in F‖H,
    and 0‖k exists first‖last in ⟨0,…,k⟩

    i⁺¹ is non.0 non.doppelgänger non.final.

    Also Known As arithmetic.

    You cannot use real numbers of
    the domain containing
    the ℵ smallest unit fractions and of
    the domain containing
    the ℵ largest natural numbers.

    Each element of ℝ is
    not the smallest unit fraction and
    not the largest natural number.

    It is obviously impossible
    to come closer to zero.

    No,
    it is obvious in arithmetic
    that each x ≠ 0 can come closer.
    To x/2 for example.

    There are always ℵ unit fractions between
    0 and a number [x] chosen by you.

    For each x > 0
    for each not-fitting-1-removed cardinality n
    the cardinality of unit fractions ⊆ (0,x]
    is not that cardinality.
    |…,⅟mₓ⁺²,⅟mₓ⁺¹| ≥ |⅟mₓ⁺²,⅟mₓ⁺¹| > |⅟mₓ⁺¹|
    |…,⅟mₓ⁺²,⅟mₓ⁺¹| ≥ |⅟mₓ⁺³,…,⅟mₓ⁺¹| > |⅟mₓ⁺²,⅟mₓ⁺¹|
    |…,⅟mₓ⁺²,⅟mₓ⁺¹| ≥ |⅟mₓ⁺⁴,…,⅟mₓ⁺¹| > |⅟mₓ⁺³,…,⅟mₓ⁺¹|
    |…,⅟mₓ⁺²,⅟mₓ⁺¹| ≥ |⅟mₓ⁺⁵,…,⅟mₓ⁺¹| > |⅟mₓ⁺⁴,…,⅟mₓ⁺¹|
    |…,⅟mₓ⁺²,⅟mₓ⁺¹| ≥ |⅟mₓ⁺⁶,…,⅟mxₓ⁺¹| > |⅟mₓ⁺⁵,…,⅟mₓ⁺¹|
    ...

    The cardinality of unit fractions ⊆ (0,x]
    _is not_ any not.fitting.1.removed cardinality n

    The cardinality of unit fractions ⊆ (0,x]
    _is_ fitting.1.removed |…,⅟mₓ⁺⁴,⅟mₓ⁺³,⅟mₓ⁺²,⅟mₓ⁺¹| = |…,⅟mₓ⁺⁴,⅟mₓ⁺³,⅟mₓ⁺²| = |…,⅟mₓ⁺⁴,⅟mₓ⁺³| =
    |…,⅟mₓ⁺⁴| =
    ... =
    ℵ₀

    Same for ω, but,
    contrary to zero, ω is a vague end of the scale.

    The cardinality of natural numbers ⊆ [x,∞)
    _is not_ any not.fitting.1.removed cardinality n
    |mₓ⁺¹,mₓ⁺²,…| ≥ |mₓ⁺¹,mₓ⁺²| > |mₓ⁺¹| |mₓ⁺¹,mₓ⁺²,…| ≥ |mₓ⁺¹,…,mₓ⁺³| > |mₓ⁺¹,mₓ⁺²| |mₓ⁺¹,mₓ⁺²,…| ≥ |mₓ⁺¹,…,mₓ⁺⁴| > |mₓ⁺¹,…,mₓ⁺³|
    |mₓ⁺¹,mₓ⁺²,…| ≥ |mₓ⁺¹,…,mₓ⁺⁵| > |mₓ⁺¹,…,mₓ⁺⁴|
    |mₓ⁺¹,mₓ⁺²,…| ≥ |mₓ⁺¹,…,mₓ⁺⁶| > |mₓ⁺¹,…,mₓ⁺⁵|
    ...

    The cardinality of natural numbers ⊆ [x,∞)
    _is_ fitting.1.removed
    |mₓ⁺¹,mₓ⁺²,mₓ⁺³,mₓ⁺⁴,…| = |mₓ⁺²,mₓ⁺³,mₓ⁺⁴,…| =
    |mₓ⁺³,mₓ⁺⁴,…| =
    |mₓ⁺⁴,…| =
    ... =
    ℵ₀ = |ω|

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Mon Jan 15 08:15:14 2024
    Le 14/01/2024 à 19:42, Richard Damon a écrit :

    There are no unit fractions smaller that ALL unit fractions

    But there are ℵ unit fraction smaller than all you can name.

    Assume it. Then you can come close to zero such that nothing is between
    it and your chosen number. But that is a contradiction.

    You can come as close as you want.

    By naming an x you can come close as you want in the measure of distance
    but not in the measure number of unit fractions between 0 and x.

    ∀eps > 0 ∀x ∈ (eps, 1]: NUF(x) = ℵo

    That doesn't means that you can reach the point that nothing is between.

    That would require the existance of a Highest Natural Number.

    Nevertheless you can reach 0.

    That assumption is where the contradiction is, not that all Natural Numbers/Unit Fractions are visible.

    That is the same. Fact is that you cannot name almost all numbers.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Mon Jan 15 08:24:55 2024
    Le 15/01/2024 à 01:23, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 1/14/2024 11:43 AM, WM wrote:


    You cannot use real numbers of
    the domain containing
    the ℵ smallest unit fractions and of
    the domain containing
    the ℵ largest natural numbers.

    Each element of ℝ is
    not the smallest unit fraction and
    not the largest natural number.

    Each element of ℝ that can be named.

    It is obviously impossible
    to come closer to zero.

    No,
    it is obvious in arithmetic
    that each x ≠ 0 can come closer.
    To x/2 for example.

    There is no boundary in the meaqsure of distance but there is a boundary
    in the measure of remaining elements between 0 and the chosen eps > 0.

    ∀eps > 0, ∀x ∈ (eps, 1]: NUF(x) = ℵo

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Mon Jan 15 07:48:20 2024
    On 1/15/24 3:15 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 14/01/2024 à 19:42, Richard Damon a écrit :

    There are no unit fractions smaller that ALL unit fractions

    But there are ℵ unit fraction smaller than all you can name.

    No, there are not. As I have shown, I can name any of them.


    Assume it. Then you can come close to zero such that nothing is
    between it and your chosen number. But that is a contradiction.

    You can come as close as you want.

    By naming an x you can come close as you want in the measure of distance
    but not in the measure number of unit fractions between 0 and x.

    No, the number of unit fractions between 0 and x will always be Alpha_0,
    the measure of Countable infinity, as there will ALWAYS be that many
    unit fractions between 0 and x (unless x is 0, then the number is 0)


    ∀eps > 0 ∀x ∈ (eps, 1]: NUF(x) = ℵo

    Right. There are always ℵo unit fractions below a positive number, so no number exists where NUF(x) == 1

    That wasn't for all "visible" numbers, that was for all "Numbers" (from
    one of the standard sets of numbers, like Rational or Reals)


    That doesn't means that you can reach the point that nothing is between.

    That would require the existance of a Highest Natural Number.

    Nevertheless you can reach 0.

    Only by leaving the set of unit fractions.


    That assumption is where the contradiction is, not that all Natural
    Numbers/Unit Fractions are visible.

    That is the same. Fact is that you cannot name almost all numbers.

    Except that you can.

    Show a set that I can not name a member of it.

    Your logic is just insufficient to handle unbounded sets.


    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Mon Jan 15 14:57:53 2024
    On 1/15/2024 3:24 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 15/01/2024 à 01:23, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 1/14/2024 11:43 AM, WM wrote:

    It is obviously impossible
    to come closer to zero.

    No,
    it is obvious in arithmetic
    that each x ≠ 0 can come closer.
    To x/2  for example.

    There is no boundary in
    the measure of distance
    but
    there is a boundary in
    the measure of remaining elements
    between 0 and the chosen eps > 0.

    ∀eps > 0, ∀x ∈ (eps, 1]: NUF(x) = ℵo

    In arithmetic,
    ∀eps > 0
    ∀k ∈ ℕ
    ∃mᵉᵖˢ ∈ ℕ:
    eps > ⅟mᵉᵖˢ > ⅟(mᵉᵖˢ+k+1) > 0
    k < NUF(eps)

    In arithmetic,
    ∀eps > 0
    ∀k ∈ ℕ
    k < NUF(eps)
    NUF(eps) ≮ NUF(eps)
    NUF(eps) ∉ ℕ

    In arithmetic,
    ∀eps > 0
    NUF(eps) ∉ ℕ

    In arithmetic,
    ¬∃mᵂᴹ ∈ ℕ:
    ∀eps > 0
    ∀k ∈ ℕ
    eps > ⅟mᵂᴹ > ⅟(mᵂᴹ+k+1) > 0

    there is a boundary in
    the measure of remaining elements
    between 0 and the chosen eps > 0.

    In arithmetic,
    there is a boundary in
    the cardinality of remaining elements
    between 0 and the chosen eps > 0.
    but
    it's not a positive boundary,
    the boundary is 0

    | Assume otherwise.
    | Assume 0 < β/2 < β < 2β
    | for remaining.element.card.boundary β
    |
    | β < 2β
    | NUF(2β) ∉ ℕ
    | ∀k ∈ ℕ
    | ∃mₖ ∈ ℕ:
    | 2β > ⅟mₖ > ⅟(mₖ+k+1) > 0
    | [1]
    | k < NUF(2β)
    |
    | β/2 < β
    | NUF(β/2) ∈ ℕ
    | ¬∀k ∈ ℕ
    | ∃mₖ ∈ ℕ:
    | β/2 > ⅟mₖ > ⅟(mₖ+k+1) > 0
    |
    | ∃k ∈ ℕ:
    | ¬(k < NUF(β/2))
    |
    | ∃k ∈ ℕ:
    | ∀m′ ∈ ℕ
    | ¬(β/2 > ⅟m′ > ⅟(m′+k+1) > 0)
    | β/2 ≤ ⅟m′ ∨ ¬(⅟m′ > ⅟(m′+k+1) > 0)
    | ⅟m′ > ⅟(m′+k+1)) > 0
    | β/2 ≤ ⅟m′
    |
    | ∀m′ ∈ ℕ
    | β/2 ≤ ⅟m′
    | [2]
    |
    | From [1]
    | ∀k ∈ ℕ
    | ∃mₖ ∈ ℕ:
    | 2β > ⅟mₖ
    | β/2 > ⅟(4mₖ)
    |
    | However, from [2]
    | in the case of m′ = 4mₖ
    | β/2 ≤ ⅟(4mₖ)
    | Contradiction.

    Therefore,
    in arithmetic,
    the remaining.element.measure.boundary β
    isn't positive.

    In arithmetic,
    ∀eps > 0:
    NUF(eps) ∉ ℕ

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Tue Jan 16 11:12:30 2024
    Le 15/01/2024 à 13:48, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/15/24 3:15 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 14/01/2024 à 19:42, Richard Damon a écrit :

    There are no unit fractions smaller that ALL unit fractions

    But there are ℵ unit fraction smaller than all you can name.

    No, there are not. As I have shown, I can name any of them.

    Then show it. Name a unit fraction that has not ℵ smaller ones.

    No, the number of unit fractions between 0 and x will always be Alpha_0,
    the measure of Countable infinity, as there will ALWAYS be that many
    unit fractions between 0 and x (unless x is 0, then the number is 0)

    The term is aleph_0, not alpha_0.
    The mathematics is this: if x is less than every positive number, then x
    is less than (0, oo). That is impossible for positive x, let alone for
    ℵo unit fractions.

    ∀eps > 0 ∀x ∈ (eps, 1]: NUF(x) = ℵo

    Right. There are always ℵo unit fractions below a positive number, so no number exists where NUF(x) == 1

    The statement says not below "a positive number" but below "every positive number", but that means below (0, oo) and is nonsense.

    Your logic is just insufficient to handle unbounded sets.

    My logic is based on mathematics. Your claims are not logic but dogmas of matheology in contradiction with mathematics.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Tue Jan 16 07:11:50 2024
    On 1/16/24 6:16 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 15/01/2024 à 20:57, Jim Burns a écrit :

    In arithmetic,
    ∀eps > 0:
    NUF(eps) ∉ ℕ

    In arithmetic

    ∀x ∈ (0, 1]: y < x ==> y =< 0, i.e., y is not positive.

    Regards, WM


    Except that the statement does't hold if, say, y was x/2.

    You also need to define the domain of x and y. If not specified it will
    be presumed something like The Reals.

    Your problem is you have the order of operations wrong in your logic,
    the Qualifier is run first, so when we look at the inequality, we have
    am x we can use.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Tue Jan 16 11:16:36 2024
    Le 15/01/2024 à 20:57, Jim Burns a écrit :

    In arithmetic,
    ∀eps > 0:
    NUF(eps) ∉ ℕ

    In arithmetic

    ∀x ∈ (0, 1]: y < x ==> y =< 0, i.e., y is not positive.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Tue Jan 16 07:12:11 2024
    On 1/16/24 6:12 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 15/01/2024 à 13:48, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/15/24 3:15 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 14/01/2024 à 19:42, Richard Damon a écrit :

    There are no unit fractions smaller that ALL unit fractions

    But there are ℵ unit fraction smaller than all you can name.

    No, there are not. As I have shown, I can name any of them.

    Then show it. Name a unit fraction that has not ℵ smaller ones.

    So, you don't unddrstand English and just working with Strawman.

    I never claimed there was a unit fraction that doesn't have aleph_0
    smaller ones.


    No, the number of unit fractions between 0 and x will always be
    Alpha_0, the measure of Countable infinity, as there will ALWAYS be
    that many unit fractions between 0 and x (unless x is 0, then the
    number is 0)

    The term is aleph_0, not alpha_0.
    The mathematics is this: if x is less than every positive number, then x
    is less than (0, oo). That is impossible for positive x, let alone for
    ℵo unit fractions.

    So, you just proved that there is no


    ∀eps > 0 ∀x ∈ (eps, 1]: NUF(x) = ℵo

    Right. There are always ℵo unit fractions below a positive number, so
    no number exists where NUF(x) == 1

    The statement says not below "a positive number" but below "every
    positive number", but that means below (0, oo) and is nonsense.


    So, you agree that NUF(x) = ℵo for all positive x and is never a finite value.

    Since for all eps > 0 NUF(x) == ℵo, there is no eps for which NUF(x) is smaller than that, not even a "dark" one.


    Your logic is just insufficient to handle unbounded sets.

    My logic is based on mathematics. Your claims are not logic but dogmas
    of matheology in contradiction with mathematics.

    Nope. YOUR claims are based on the dogma of WMism, not actual logic or mathematics.

    You can't get to actual fundamental statements that show your claims, so
    you are just shown to be a dogmatist.


    Regards, WM



    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Tue Jan 16 12:11:36 2024
    On 1/16/2024 6:16 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 15/01/2024 à 20:57, Jim Burns a écrit :

    In arithmetic,
    ∀eps > 0:
    NUF(eps) ∉ ℕ

    In arithmetic
    ∀x ∈ (0, 1]: y < x ==> y =< 0,
    i.e., y is not positive.

    In arithmetic,
    ∀eps > 0: eps > 0
    i.e., eps is positive.

    There is an implicit ∀y

    I don't know which you intend:

    (i)
    (∀x ∈ (0,1]: y < x) ⇒ y ≤ 0
    true

    if y is a lower bound of (0,1]
    then y ≤ glb(0,1] = 0

    0 ∉ (0,1]

    (ii)
    ∀x ∈ (0,1]: (y < x ⇒ y ≤ 0)
    false

    ∀y: ∀x ∈ (0,1]: (y < x ⇒ y ≤ 0)
    if and only if
    ¬∃y: ∃x ∈ (0,1]: (y < x ∧ 0 < y)
    if and only if
    ¬∃x ∈ (0,1]: ∃y ∈ (0,x)
    false
    Instead,
    ∃x ∈ (0,1]: ∃y ∈ (0,x)

    x ∈ ⋃{ (eps,1] | eps ∈ (0,1] }
    if and only if
    x ∈ (0,1]


    ∀eps > 0: NUF(eps) ∉ ℕ
    true






    Regards, WM


    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Dieter Heidorn@21:1/5 to Richard Damon on Tue Jan 16 21:19:57 2024
    Richard Damon schrieb:
    On 1/16/24 6:16 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 15/01/2024 à 20:57, Jim Burns a écrit :

    In arithmetic,
    ∀eps > 0:
    NUF(eps) ∉ ℕ

    In arithmetic

    ∀x ∈ (0, 1]: y < x ==> y =< 0, i.e., y is not positive.

    Regards, WM


    Except that the statement does't hold if, say, y was x/2.


    That's right. But what WM means is the following:

    for every y which is smaller than every x ∈ (0,1] : y <= 0.

    One of his problems is that he doesn't understand quantifiers and their
    proper application. Example: The correct statement about unit fractions
    1/n (where n∈ℕ)

    ∀ x ∈ (0,1] ∃^ℵo 1/n : 1/n < x

    he misunderstands in a way that is equivalent to the quantifier shift:

    ∃^ℵo 1/n ∀ x ∈ (0,1] : 1/n < x .

    Then he concludes:

    there are ℵo unit fractions left from zero.

    Discussing with WM you should always keep in mind: WM doesn't write
    about mathematics but his private system of ideas which are based on
    his inability to understand infinite sets and set theory.

    Dieter Heidorn

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Tue Jan 16 16:31:44 2024
    On 1/15/2024 12:52 AM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On Sunday, January 14, 2024
    at 10:24:52 AM UTC-8, Jim Burns wrote:

    [...]

    Here are some things
    you should be familiar with,
    if you talking about models,
    structures that embody all relations,
    of integers,
    here the natural or non-negative integers,
    for that model-theory and proof-theory are
    the same thing,
    in terms of mathematical proofs,
    insofar as that
    a model of all relation and structurally,
    is a proof,
    and that
    any proof has a corresponding model,
    and vice-versa.

    As I understand it,
    the semantic (model.theory) and
    the syntactic (proof.theory) points of view
    are two sides of the same coin.

    There are some very nice proofs showing
    how the two are related, but
    they aren't exactly the same thing.

    For a certain theory (syntax),
    there might or might not exist
    a structure which it describes (semantics).
    A structure which a theory describes
    is a model of the theory.

    Provably,
    if no contradiction follows from a theory,
    then a model of it exists.

    The proof constructs (shows exists) a model from
    the objects of the language of the theory.
    That's why I note that, even if a theory has a model,
    it still might not have the model you're thinking of.

    Every structure that satisfies a theory is
    a model of the theory.

    Perhaps significantly different structures
    satisfy the same theory (are models).

    Provably,
    if each model (semantics) which satisfies a theory
    satisfies an additional formula,
    then a proof (syntax) exists of that formula
    starting from the theory (syntax).

    ----
    Because there are formally undecidable formulas
    in the natural numbers,
    if any model exists,
    then more than one model exists.

    Also,
    if any inductive set exists,
    then a unique minimal inductive set exists,
    subset to each inductive set, and
    containing only each countable.to number.
    By any other word, a standard model.

    tl,;dr
    The natural numbers either
    are complete nonsense, top to bottom, or
    have a standard model and a non.standard model.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Wed Jan 17 11:43:40 2024
    Le 16/01/2024 à 13:11, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/16/24 6:16 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 15/01/2024 à 20:57, Jim Burns a écrit :

    In arithmetic,
    ∀eps > 0:
    NUF(eps) ∉ ℕ

    In arithmetic

    ∀x ∈ (0, 1]: y < x ==> y =< 0, i.e., y is not positive.


    Except that the statement does't hold if, say, y was x/2.

    The statement concerns all real numbers.

    You also need to define the domain of x and y. If not specified it will
    be presumed something like The Reals.

    Your problem is you have the order of operations wrong in your logic,
    the Qualifier is run first, so when we look at the inequality, we have
    am x we can use.

    The "less than" relation is independent of quantifier-exchange. If for
    every x ∈ (0, 1] there a smaller y, then there is an y smaller than
    every x ∈ (0, 1] and hence smaller than (0, 1]. Of course for ℵ
    elements y this is much clearer.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Wed Jan 17 11:49:42 2024
    Le 16/01/2024 à 21:19, Dieter Heidorn a écrit :
    The correct statement about unit fractions
    1/n (where n∈ℕ)

    ∀ x ∈ (0,1] ∃^ℵo 1/n : 1/n < x

    he misunderstands in a way that is equivalent to the quantifier shift:

    ∃^ℵo 1/n ∀ x ∈ (0,1] : 1/n < x .

    Then he concludes:

    there are ℵo unit fractions left from zero.

    Would be required to make your statement correct.

    For the less-than relation there is no quantifier magic.
    NUF(x) cannot grow anywhere from 0 to ℵo without passing finite values.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Wed Jan 17 11:53:39 2024
    Le 16/01/2024 à 18:11, Jim Burns a écrit :

    (i)
    (∀x ∈ (0,1]: y < x) ⇒ y ≤ 0
    true

    Yes, that is correct.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Wed Jan 17 07:55:54 2024
    On 1/17/24 6:49 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 16/01/2024 à 21:19, Dieter Heidorn a écrit :
    The correct statement about unit fractions
    1/n (where n∈ℕ)

        ∀ x ∈ (0,1]  ∃^ℵo 1/n : 1/n < x

    he misunderstands in a way that is equivalent to the quantifier shift:

        ∃^ℵo 1/n  ∀ x ∈ (0,1] : 1/n < x .

    Then he concludes:

        there are ℵo unit fractions left from zero.

    Would be required to make your statement correct.

    For the less-than relation there is no quantifier magic.
    NUF(x) cannot grow anywhere from 0 to ℵo without passing finite values.

    Regards, WM


    Why not?

    And what says those "values" that it happens at have to be in the set of
    Unit Fractions/rational/real numbers?

    If the "value" where NUF(x) == 1 isn't in the domain of Unit
    factions/Rational Numbers/ Real Numbers, then there is no need for your
    "dark" numbers, they are just visible numbers in some other system.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Wed Jan 17 14:09:53 2024
    Le 17/01/2024 à 13:55, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/17/24 6:49 AM, WM wrote:

    NUF(x) cannot grow anywhere from 0 to ℵo without passing finite values.

    Why not?

    Because of mathemtics. ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) = d_n > 0.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Wed Jan 17 11:29:25 2024
    On 1/16/2024 11:39 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On Tuesday, January 16, 2024
    at 2:29:07 PM UTC-8, Ross Finlayson wrote:

    [...]

    In proof theory, it's provable, that
    in classical logic,

    proof.theory ≠ set.theory
    proof ≠ set

    logic < (non.logical) set.theory
    set.theory = logic+set.description

    set.description = infinity∨¬infinity
    set.description = foundation∨¬foundation

    different.description ⟺ different.models

    one must always assert
    Empty, Infinity, and well-foundedness
    for the inference of the existence of any set,
    for otherwise inference may arrive at
    Russell's set via quantification.

    Russell's ∃{x|x∉x} ⟸ unrestricted.comprehension

    s/comprehension/specification+replacement

    ¬∃{x|x∉x} ⟸ classical
    On the other hand,
    revision.theory.of.truth+more?

    So,
    in classical logic,
    ZF's axioms aren't independent.

    Did you (RF) intend to make
    that abrupt change of topic there?

    That's not how I'd use "so"
    Cha​cun à son goût.

    Because models exist for
    Infinity
    ¬Infinity
    Foundation
    ¬Foundation
    Choice
    ¬Choice
    a (hypothetical) proof of
    necessary.Infinity
    necessary.Foundation
    necessary.Choice
    would be wrong.

    tl;dr
    Infinity, Foundation, Choice are
    independent.

    Of course, these days we know that
    that's "quasi-modal" logic.

    Uhm?
    You mean?
    https://philpapers.org/rec/GOLQEO-2
    Quasi-Modal Equivalence of Canonical Structures

    Yet, it's not the point here that
    "classical" logic isn't monotonic.

    Good to hear that it's not the point..
    Classical is monotonic.

    Yet, the idea that
    "there's isn't a standard model of the integers",
    and, also,
    "there are multiple non-standard models of integers",
    in set theory, and as well in number theory,
    has a lot going on with
    "there's an infinite integer in
    some infinitudes of integers".

    "has a lot going on with" = ?


    Consider a finite set,
    each element in its place.

    A place is removed,
    and not all elements have places.
    We say:
    the set's cardinality is finite.


    Consider only all finite cardinals,
    the ones which
    cannot fit in a place removed.

    For each finite cardinal,
    inserting another element makes
    a set which won't fit in its places,
    one with a different cardinality.
    Because finite.

    Insert more and it still won't fit.
    Insert all the cardinals and it still won't fit.

    For each finite cardinal,
    the cardinality of only all finite cardinals
    is not its cardinality.

    <drum.roll>
    the cardinality of only all finite cardinals
    is not a finite cardinality.
    It is an infinite cardinality.
    <cymbal.crash>

    Check:
    It isn't any cardinality which
    cannot fit in a place removed.
    It should fit in a place removed.

    0@[1] 1@[2] 2@[3] 3@[4] ...
    And check.

    Weird as it is to fit in a place removed,
    it must be so, or else
    all the finite cardinals aren't
    all the finite cardinals.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Wed Jan 17 13:35:54 2024
    On 1/17/2024 6:49 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 16/01/2024 à 21:19, Dieter Heidorn a écrit :

    [...]

    For the less-than relation
    there is no quantifier magic.

    For anti.symmetric relations, such as less.than,
    there is quantifier anti.magic.

    | Assume P(x,y) ⇔ ¬P(y,x)
    | Assume ∀x:∃y:P(x,y)
    |
    | ∀x:∃y:P(x,y)
    | if and only if
    | ¬∃x:∀y:¬P(x,y)
    | if and only if
    | ¬∃x:∀y:P(y,x)
    | relabel 'x''z','y''x','z''y'
    | ¬∃y:∀x:P(x,y)

    Therefore,
    P(x,y) ⇔ ¬P(y,x)
    ∀x:∃y:P(x,y)
    ⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯
    ¬∃y:∀x:P(x,y)
    anti.magic

    ∀x:∃y≠x: x<y
    ⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯
    ¬∃y:∀y≠x: x<y
    anti.magic

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Richard Damon on Wed Jan 17 14:35:45 2024
    On 1/17/2024 7:55 AM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 1/17/24 6:53 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 16/01/2024 à 18:11, Jim Burns a écrit :

    (i)
    (∀x ∈ (0,1]: y < x)  ⇒  y ≤ 0
    true

    Yes, that is correct.

    Except we show it isn't for y = x/2

    Well, for y = x/2, the antecedent is false,
    thus the implication is true.
    But WM probably isn't thinking of that.


    (∀x ∈ (0,1]: y < x) ⇒ y ≤ 0
    if and only if
    0 < y ⇒ (∃x ∈ (0,1]: x ≤ y)

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Fritz Feldhase on Wed Jan 17 19:53:47 2024
    Fritz Feldhase schrieb am Mittwoch, 17. Januar 2024 um 20:15:47 UTC+1:
    On Wednesday, January 17, 2024 at 12:49:48 PM UTC+1, WM wrote:

    For the less-than relation there is no quantifier magic.
    Was immer Deine "quantifier magic" auch sein soll; aber die (richtige) Reihenfolge der Quantoren ist wesentlich:

    An e IN: Em e IN: n < m (true)

    Em e IN: An e IN: n < m (false)

    Both are true, but the average person cannot look into the infinite.
    Therefore I have invented the simpler example with unit fractions.
    If for every x ∈ (0, 1] there are ℵ smaller unit fractions, then ℵ
    unit fractions are smaller than every x ∈ (0, 1] and lie left-hand side
    of the whole interval. Otherwise a first one would appear within the
    interval.

    Please note: Without ℵ unit fractions left-hand side of (0, 1], the
    above true statement cannot be true.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Wed Jan 17 20:36:11 2024
    On 1/17/24 2:35 PM, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 1/17/2024 7:55 AM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 1/17/24 6:53 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 16/01/2024 à 18:11, Jim Burns a écrit :

    (i)
    (∀x ∈ (0,1]: y < x)  ⇒  y ≤ 0
    true

    Yes, that is correct.

    Except we show it isn't for y = x/2

    Well, for y = x/2, the antecedent is false,
    thus the implication is true.
    But WM probably isn't thinking of that.



    What part of the antecedent (∀x ∈ (0,1]: y < x) is false?

    x is such that x ∈ (0,1], and y is such that y < x


    (∀x ∈ (0,1]: y < x)  ⇒  y ≤ 0
     if and only if
    0 < y  ⇒  (∃x ∈ (0,1]: x ≤ y)



    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Wed Jan 17 20:36:13 2024
    On 1/17/24 9:09 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 17/01/2024 à 13:55, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/17/24 6:49 AM, WM wrote:

    NUF(x) cannot grow anywhere from 0 to ℵo without passing finite values. >>
    Why not?

    Because of mathemtics. ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) = d_n > 0.
    Regards, WM

    And how does that say that NUF(x) can't grow to ℵo without passing
    finite values.

    That equation in fact proves that there can not be a smallest 1/n as the
    'level gap' below 1/n is only 1/(n+1) of the distance between 0 and 1/n,
    so there is room for at least n+1 more unit fractions below it.

    You need to find a point where the gap is as big as 1/n, and it never is.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Richard Damon on Thu Jan 18 00:15:22 2024
    On 1/17/2024 8:36 PM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 1/17/24 2:35 PM, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 1/17/2024 7:55 AM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 1/17/24 6:53 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 16/01/2024 à 18:11, Jim Burns a écrit :

    (i)
    (∀x ∈ (0,1]: y < x)  ⇒  y ≤ 0
    true

    Yes, that is correct.

    Except we show it isn't for y = x/2

    Well, for y = x/2, the antecedent is false,
    thus the implication is true.
    But WM probably isn't thinking of that.

    What part of the antecedent
    (∀x ∈ (0,1]: y < x) is false?

    Excuse me, I was thinking of something else.

    As I'm sure you know, if
    x ∈ (0,1] ⇒ y < x
    is false for any value of x,
    then all of
    (∀x ∈ (0,1]: y < x)
    is false,
    and all of
    (∀x ∈ (0,1]: y < x) ⇒ y ≤ 0
    is true.

    For y > 0 and x = min{y/2,1}
    x ∈ (0,1] ⇒ y < x
    is false
    (∀x ∈ (0,1]: y < x)
    is false, and
    (∀x ∈ (0,1]: y < x) ⇒ y ≤ 0
    is true.

    On the other hand,
    for y ≤ 0
    (∀x ∈ (0,1]: y < x) ⇒ y ≤ 0
    is true,
    whatever the case is for
    ∀x ∈ (0,1]: y < x

    In sum,
    (∀x ∈ (0,1]: y < x) ⇒ y ≤ 0
    is true, but
    its truth doesn't tell us about y


    I confess that I don't know
    what significance that formula has to WM.

    It's possible that, for WM,
    talking about
    (∀x ∈ (0,1]: y < x) ⇒ y ≤ 0
    replaces talking about
    ∀eps > 0: NUF(eps) ∉ ℕ

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Thu Jan 18 09:09:22 2024
    Le 18/01/2024 à 02:36, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/17/24 9:09 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 17/01/2024 à 13:55, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/17/24 6:49 AM, WM wrote:

    NUF(x) cannot grow anywhere from 0 to ℵo without passing finite values. >>>
    Why not?

    Because of mathemtics. ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) = d_n > 0.

    And how does that say that NUF(x) can't grow to ℵo without passing
    finite values.

    Because after every unit fraction the function NUF(x) is constant over d_n
    0.

    That equation in fact proves that there can not be a smallest 1/n as the 'level gap' below 1/n is only 1/(n+1) of the distance between 0 and 1/n,
    so there is room for at least n+1 more unit fractions below it.

    Nevertheless ***all*** unit fractions have gaps between each other. There
    is no exception.

    You need to find a point where the gap is as big as 1/n, and it never is.

    We cannot investigate individuals within the dark domain.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Thu Jan 18 09:12:58 2024
    Le 18/01/2024 à 02:36, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/17/24 2:35 PM, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 1/17/2024 7:55 AM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 1/17/24 6:53 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 16/01/2024 à 18:11, Jim Burns a écrit :

    (i)
    (∀x ∈ (0,1]: y < x)  ⇒  y ≤ 0
    true

    Yes, that is correct.

    Except we show it isn't for y = x/2

    Well, for y = x/2, the antecedent is false,
    thus the implication is true.
    But WM probably isn't thinking of that.



    What part of the antecedent (∀x ∈ (0,1]: y < x) is false?

    x is such that x ∈ (0,1], and y is such that y < x

    Only if y is less than all x ∈ (0,1], the implication holds. If the antecedent is violated, the implication is true nevertheless. But that is irrelevant.

    (∀x ∈ (0,1]: y < x)  ⇒  y ≤ 0

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Fritz Feldhase on Thu Jan 18 09:03:41 2024
    Fritz Feldhase schrieb am Mittwoch, 17. Januar 2024 um 21:27:13 UTC+1:
    On Wednesday, January 17, 2024 at 8:53:56 PM UTC+1, WM wrote:
    Fritz Feldhase schrieb am Mittwoch, 17. Januar 2024 um 20:15:47 UTC+1:

    die (richtige) Reihenfolge der Quantoren ist wesentlich:

    An e IN: Em e IN: n < m (true)

    Em e IN: An e IN: n < m (false)

    Both are true,
    Nope.

    Yes, a mistake. Both are wrong. But the first statement is true for
    *definable* numbers.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Thu Jan 18 09:15:13 2024
    Le 18/01/2024 à 06:15, Jim Burns a écrit :

    I confess that I don't know
    what significance that formula has to WM.

    If ∀x ∈ (0, 1]: NUF(x) = ℵo was true, it would prove negative unit fractions y.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Thu Jan 18 07:51:06 2024
    On 1/18/24 4:09 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 18/01/2024 à 02:36, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/17/24 9:09 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 17/01/2024 à 13:55, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/17/24 6:49 AM, WM wrote:

    NUF(x) cannot grow anywhere from 0 to ℵo without passing finite
    values.

    Why not?

    Because of mathemtics. ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) = d_n > 0.

    And how does that say that NUF(x) can't grow to ℵo without passing
    finite values.

    Because after every unit fraction the function NUF(x) is constant over d_n

    So? That doesn't mean that NUF(x) can't instantly grow to infinity
    between 0 and the range (0,1]

    0.

    That equation in fact proves that there can not be a smallest 1/n as
    the 'level gap' below 1/n is only 1/(n+1) of the distance between 0
    and 1/n, so there is room for at least n+1 more unit fractions below it.

    Nevertheless ***all*** unit fractions have gaps between each other.
    There is no exception.

    And again, we aren't talking BETWEEN unit fractions, but between 0 and
    (0,1].


    You need to find a point where the gap is as big as 1/n, and it never is.

    We cannot investigate individuals within the dark domain.

    You can not investigate the dark domain because it doesn't exist.


    Regards, WM



    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Thu Jan 18 07:24:48 2024
    On 1/18/2024 4:15 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 18/01/2024 à 06:15, Jim Burns a écrit :

    In sum,
    (∀x ∈ (0,1]: y < x) ⇒ y ≤ 0
    is true, but
    its truth doesn't tell us about y

    I confess that I don't know
    what significance that formula has to WM.

    If
    ∀x ∈ (0, 1]: NUF(x) = ℵo
    was true,
    it would prove negative unit fractions y.

    How does
    (∀x ∈ (0,1]: y < x) ⇒ y ≤ 0
    and
    ∀x ∈ (0,1]: NUF(x) = ℵ₀
    prove negative unit fractions y?

    ----
    In arithmetic,
    ∀k <ℵ₀: ∀j <ℵ₀: j+k <ℵ₀

    ∀k <ℵ₀: ∀i <ℵ₀: i < |{j+k | j <ℵ₀}|

    ∀k <ℵ₀: ¬∃i <ℵ₀: i = |{j+k | j <ℵ₀}|

    ∀k <ℵ₀: ¬( |{j+k | j <ℵ₀}| <ℵ₀ )

    ----
    In arithmetic,
    ∀k ∈ℕ₁: ∀j ∈ℕ: 0 < ⅟(j+k) ≤ 1

    ∀k ∈ℕ₁: {⅟(j+k) | j ∈ℕ} ⊆ (0,1] ∧
    ∀i ∈ℕ: i < |{⅟(j+k) | j ∈ℕ}|

    ∀k ∈ℕ₁: {⅟(j+k) | j ∈ℕ} ⊆ (0,1] ∧
    ¬∃i ∈ℕ: i = |{⅟(j+k) | j ∈ℕ}|

    ∀k ∈ℕ₁: {⅟(j+k) | j ∈ℕ} ⊆ (0,1] ∧
    ¬( |{⅟(j+k) | j ∈ℕ}| < |ℕ| )

    At what formula, if any, have we stopped
    using arithmetic?

    Keep in mind that
    _those formulas_ aren't dark.
    You can see them on your screen.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Thu Jan 18 16:48:36 2024
    Le 18/01/2024 à 13:44, FromTheRafters a écrit :

    Yes, there are gaps in Q+ with respect to the positive reals fractional parts.

    That means NUF(x) does not increase by more than 1 without stopping
    afterwards. It starts with 0 and not with ℵ.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Thu Jan 18 16:45:22 2024
    Le 18/01/2024 à 13:24, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 1/18/2024 4:15 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 18/01/2024 à 06:15, Jim Burns a écrit :

    In sum,
    (∀x ∈ (0,1]: y < x) ⇒ y ≤ 0
    is true, but
    its truth doesn't tell us about y

    I confess that I don't know
    what significance that formula has to WM.

    If
    ∀x ∈ (0, 1]: NUF(x) = ℵo
    was true,
    it would prove negative unit fractions y.

    How does
    (∀x ∈ (0,1]: y < x) ⇒ y ≤ 0
    and
    ∀x ∈ (0,1]: NUF(x) = ℵ₀
    prove negative unit fractions y?

    For every point x > 0 there are ℵ smaller unit fractions.

    There exists no point x > 0 without ℵ smaller unit fractions.

    There exist ℵ negative unit fractions.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Thu Jan 18 16:51:50 2024
    Le 18/01/2024 à 13:51, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/18/24 4:09 AM, WM wrote:

    Because after every unit fraction the function NUF(x) is constant over d_n

    So? That doesn't mean that NUF(x) can't instantly grow to infinity
    between 0 and the range (0,1]

    It does mean exactly this. Otherwise:

    If for every point x > 0 there are ℵ smaller unit fractions,
    then there exists no point x > 0 without ℵ smaller unit fractions.
    Then there exist ℵ negative unit fractions.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Thu Jan 18 17:30:53 2024
    Le 18/01/2024 à 18:02, FromTheRafters a écrit :
    WM wrote :
    Le 18/01/2024 à 13:44, FromTheRafters a écrit :

    Yes, there are gaps in Q+ with respect to the positive reals fractional
    parts.

    That means NUF(x) does not increase by more than 1 without stopping
    afterwards.

    No, it doesn't.

    In mathematics it does. ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) > 0

    It starts with 0 and not with ℵ.

    It is not an action.

    Hogwash. It is a function.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Thu Jan 18 13:55:21 2024
    On 1/18/2024 11:45 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 18/01/2024 à 13:24, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 1/18/2024 4:15 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 18/01/2024 à 06:15, Jim Burns a écrit :

    In sum,
    (∀x ∈ (0,1]: y < x)  ⇒  y ≤ 0
    is true, but
    its truth doesn't tell us about y

    I confess that I don't know
    what significance that formula has to WM.

    If
    ∀x ∈ (0, 1]: NUF(x) = ℵo
    was true,
    it would prove negative unit fractions y.

    How does
    (∀x ∈ (0,1]: y < x)  ⇒  y ≤ 0
    and
    ∀x ∈ (0,1]: NUF(x) = ℵ₀
    prove negative unit fractions y?

    For every point x > 0
    there are ℵ smaller unit fractions.

    There exists no point x > 0 without
    ℵ smaller unit fractions.


    https://sneltraining.nl/then-a-miracle-occurs/

    "then a miracle occurs"

    "I think you should be more explicit
    here in step two"

    There exist ℵ negative unit fractions.

    An ordinal after each final ordinal
    is not any of the final ordinals.
    Thus, it is non.final.

    A non.final ordinal, by definition,
    is followed by
    an ordinal with the same cardinality.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Thu Jan 18 15:28:46 2024
    On 1/18/2024 12:12 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On Wednesday, January 17, 2024
    at 1:07:02 PM UTC-8, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On Wednesday, January 17, 2024
    at 8:29:31 AM UTC-8, Jim Burns wrote:

    [...]
    [...]

    Here though,
    the notion of the Aristotle's continuum, is that
    the segment, is finite, but
    is equi-partitioned with infinitely-many.
    This is the most simple usual model of line-drawing or
    putting pencil to paper, drawing, and lifting it,
    relating exactly this model in space according to
    any model in time, in exactly the course-of-passage,
    in space through time.

    My vague sense of these issues is that
    Zeno argued very effectively that
    that simplest theory of the line is too simple.

    Our current theory of the line,
    a theory stress.tested beyond the dreams of Zeno,
    is that, in topological terms,
    the line is _one component_ that it can't be
    partitioned into two non.empty open sets.

    Without that being true,
    there can be curves y=f(x) which are continuous at
    each point of the line, but which, nonetheless,
    jump over lines between <x1,y1> and <x2,y2>

    Since jumping over isn't the sort of behavior
    which the things we consider curves get up to,
    it seems unavoidable for us to require
    _one component_

    One effect of there being only one component is
    that any countable series of points must have
    a split with no series.point between sides.
    But there must be a point.between,
    or there will be more than one component.

    One component implies a point.between, but
    a point.between which is not in the series.
    And so on, for each series of points.
    _Each_ series not holding all points
    implies that mere infinitely.small partitions
    aren't enough for a good theory of the line.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Thu Jan 18 20:26:53 2024
    On 1/18/24 11:51 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 18/01/2024 à 13:51, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/18/24 4:09 AM, WM wrote:

    Because after every unit fraction the function NUF(x) is constant
    over d_n

    So? That doesn't mean that NUF(x) can't instantly grow to infinity
    between 0 and the range (0,1]

    It does mean exactly this. Otherwise:

    If for every point x > 0 there are ℵ smaller unit fractions,
    then there exists no point x > 0 without ℵ smaller unit fractions.
    Then there exist ℵ negative unit fractions.

    Regards, WM


    How do you get from

    there exists no point x > 0 without ℵ smaller unit fractions.

    to

    Then there exist ℵ negative unit fractions.



    You don't seem to understand how mathematics works with transfinite
    numbers like ℵ

    Likely because you are trying to treat it as a finite number, which it
    isn't.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Fri Jan 19 08:35:57 2024
    Le 18/01/2024 à 19:39, FromTheRafters a écrit :
    WM formulated on Thursday :
    Le 18/01/2024 à 18:02, FromTheRafters a écrit :
    WM wrote :
    Le 18/01/2024 à 13:44, FromTheRafters a écrit :

    Yes, there are gaps in Q+ with respect to the positive reals fractional >>>>> parts.

    That means NUF(x) does not increase by more than 1 without stopping
    afterwards.

    No, it doesn't.

    In mathematics it does. ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) > 0

    It starts with 0 and not with ℵ.

    It is not an action.

    Hogwash. It is a function.

    Then map it, done. No start here and finish there involved.

    The start is NUF(x) = 0 for an arbitrary x =< 0.
    Math proves ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) > 0.
    This excludes an increase from 0 to more than 1 at some point.
    Finish is NUF(x) = ℵ for arbitrary x >= 1.

    Regards, WM

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Fri Jan 19 08:48:13 2024
    Le 19/01/2024 à 02:26, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/18/24 11:48 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 18/01/2024 à 13:44, FromTheRafters a écrit :

    Yes, there are gaps in Q+ with respect to the positive reals
    fractional parts.

    That means NUF(x) does not increase by more than 1 without stopping
    afterwards. It starts with 0 and not with ℵ.

    And then hits a gap in space between 0 and (0,1] where it jumps at not
    unit fractions.

    No. There is no gap in space. And NUF jumps only at unit fractions.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Fri Jan 19 08:31:38 2024
    Le 19/01/2024 à 02:26, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/18/24 11:51 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 18/01/2024 à 13:51, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/18/24 4:09 AM, WM wrote:

    Because after every unit fraction the function NUF(x) is constant
    over d_n

    So? That doesn't mean that NUF(x) can't instantly grow to infinity
    between 0 and the range (0,1]

    It does mean exactly this. Otherwise:

    If for every point x > 0 there are ℵ smaller unit fractions,
    then there exists no point x > 0 without ℵ smaller unit fractions.
    Then there exist ℵ negative unit fractions.

    How do you get from

    there exists no point x > 0 without ℵ smaller unit fractions.

    to

    Then there exist ℵ negative unit fractions.

    There are ℵ unit fractions in total. No point of (0, 1] has ℵ at its right-hand side, because every point has ℵ at its left-hand side. The interval (0, 1] is nothing but all its points. Therefore ℵ unit
    fractions are at the left-hand side of the interval (0, 1].


    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Fri Jan 19 08:45:32 2024
    Le 18/01/2024 à 19:55, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 1/18/2024 11:45 AM, WM wrote:

    For every point x > 0
    there are ℵ smaller unit fractions.

    There exists no point x > 0 without
    ℵ smaller unit fractions.


    "I think you should be more explicit
    here in step two"

    No, this is simply a reformulation based on logic.
    If all have property P, then none exists without property P.

    There exist ℵ negative unit fractions.

    An ordinal after each final ordinal
    is not any of the final ordinals.
    Thus, it is non.final.

    A non.final ordinal, by definition,
    is followed by
    an ordinal with the same cardinality.

    Waffle.

    There are ℵ unit fractions in total. No point of (0, 1] has ℵ at its right-hand side, because every point has ℵ at its left-hand side. The interval (0, 1] is nothing but all its points. Therefore ℵ unit
    fractions are at the left-hand side of the interval (0, 1].


    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Fri Jan 19 08:50:48 2024
    Le 19/01/2024 à 02:26, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/18/24 4:12 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 18/01/2024 à 02:36, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/17/24 2:35 PM, Jim Burns wrote:

    (i)
    (∀x ∈ (0,1]: y < x)  ⇒  y ≤ 0
    true

    Yes, that is correct.

    Except we show it isn't for y = x/2

    Well, for y = x/2, the antecedent is false,
    thus the implication is true.
    But WM probably isn't thinking of that.

    What part of the antecedent (∀x ∈ (0,1]: y < x) is false?

    x is such that x ∈ (0,1], and y is such that y < x

    Only if y is less than all x ∈ (0,1], the implication holds. If the
    antecedent is violated, the implication is true nevertheless. But that
    is irrelevant.

    I never claimed that y was less than ALL x, only any particular x.

    But the antecedent concerns y smaller than all x.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Fri Jan 19 05:33:11 2024
    On 1/19/2024 3:45 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 18/01/2024 à 19:55, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 1/18/2024 11:45 AM, WM wrote:

    For every point x > 0
    there are ℵ smaller unit fractions.

    There exists no point x > 0 without
    ℵ smaller unit fractions.


    "I think you should be more explicit
    here in step two"

    No, this is simply
    a reformulation based on logic.
    If all have property P,
    then none exists without property P.

    I think you should be more explicit
    in the step from
    | There exists no point x > 0 without
    | ℵ smaller unit fractions.
    to
    | There exist ℵ negative unit fractions.

    There exist ℵ negative unit fractions.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Fri Jan 19 10:54:23 2024
    On 1/19/24 3:50 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 19/01/2024 à 02:26, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/18/24 4:12 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 18/01/2024 à 02:36, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/17/24 2:35 PM, Jim Burns wrote:

    (i)
    (∀x ∈ (0,1]: y < x)  ⇒  y ≤ 0
    true

    Yes, that is correct.

    Except we show it isn't for y = x/2

    Well, for y = x/2, the antecedent is false,
    thus the implication is true.
    But WM probably isn't thinking of that.

    What part of the antecedent (∀x ∈ (0,1]: y < x) is false?

    x is such that x ∈ (0,1], and y is such that y < x

    Only if y is less than all x ∈ (0,1], the implication holds. If the
    antecedent is violated, the implication is true nevertheless. But
    that is irrelevant.

    I never claimed that y was less than ALL x, only any particular x.

    But the antecedent concerns y smaller than all x.

    Regards, WM




    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Fri Jan 19 17:38:46 2024
    Le 19/01/2024 à 16:54, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/19/24 3:48 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 19/01/2024 à 02:26, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/18/24 11:48 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 18/01/2024 à 13:44, FromTheRafters a écrit :

    Yes, there are gaps in Q+ with respect to the positive reals
    fractional parts.

    That means NUF(x) does not increase by more than 1 without stopping
    afterwards. It starts with 0 and not with ℵ.

    And then hits a gap in space between 0 and (0,1] where it jumps at not
    unit fractions.

    No. There is no gap in space. And NUF jumps only at unit fractions.

    So you say, but can't show how to do that.

    I need not do that or show how to do that. NUF is well defined so.

    As to "No Gap" it depends on your definition of "gap", as due to the
    density of the Reals and Rationals, ssince between any two elements of
    those sets, there are an infinite number of other elements, any
    operation based on "counting" can see a gap.

    Between 0 ad the real interval (0, 1] there is nothing.

    Therefore I use the formulation: There is no x > 0 without ℵ smaller
    unit fractions (following from set theory: Every x > 0 has ℵ smaller
    unit fractions). This formulation covers all points of (0, 1] without any exception. Therefore it claims negative unit fractions. Contradiction.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Fri Jan 19 17:30:01 2024
    Le 19/01/2024 à 16:54, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/19/24 3:31 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 19/01/2024 à 02:26, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/18/24 11:51 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 18/01/2024 à 13:51, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/18/24 4:09 AM, WM wrote:

    Because after every unit fraction the function NUF(x) is constant
    over d_n

    So? That doesn't mean that NUF(x) can't instantly grow to infinity
    between 0 and the range (0,1]

    It does mean exactly this. Otherwise:

    If for every point x > 0 there are ℵ smaller unit fractions,
    then there exists no point x > 0 without ℵ smaller unit fractions.
    Then there exist ℵ negative unit fractions.

    How do you get from

    there exists no point x > 0 without ℵ smaller unit fractions.

    to

    Then there exist ℵ negative unit fractions.

    There are ℵ unit fractions in total. No point of (0, 1] has ℵ at its
    right-hand side, because every point has ℵ at its left-hand side. The
    interval (0, 1] is nothing but all its points. Therefore ℵ unit
    fractions are at the left-hand side of the interval (0, 1].

    You can't use a property of the individual members to the set.

    That is a myth of set theory which sometimes is valid and sometimes is
    not. But here we need no set theory at all. If this property holds for all points, then it holds for the interval.

    Yes, for all x in the set, there are ℵ unit fractions to its left.

    That doesn't apply to the "Set" (0,1], since the set isn't a number.

    I use n interval and I use the geometrical property "is left-hand side
    of".

    Note, the claim that (0,1] is nothing but all its points you make
    elsewhere isn't a valid claim, as a set is a different thing then its members, which is part of the logic behind a set can't contain itself.

    That logic is irrelevant here, because I use geometry of points and
    intervals without reference to sets, just correct mathematics, so to say.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Fri Jan 19 12:59:17 2024
    On 1/19/24 12:38 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 19/01/2024 à 16:54, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/19/24 3:48 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 19/01/2024 à 02:26, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/18/24 11:48 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 18/01/2024 à 13:44, FromTheRafters a écrit :

    Yes, there are gaps in Q+ with respect to the positive reals
    fractional parts.

    That means NUF(x) does not increase by more than 1 without stopping
    afterwards. It starts with 0 and not with ℵ.

    And then hits a gap in space between 0 and (0,1] where it jumps at
    not unit fractions.

    No. There is no gap in space. And NUF jumps only at unit fractions.

    So you say, but can't show how to do that.

    I need not do that or show how to do that. NUF is well defined so.

    But nothing in NUF(x) says that in needs to have a value of 1 at any
    actual real number.


    As to "No Gap" it depends on your definition of "gap", as due to the
    density of the Reals and Rationals, ssince between any two elements of
    those sets, there are an infinite number of other elements, any
    operation based on "counting" can see a gap.

    Between 0 ad the real interval (0, 1] there is nothing.

    Only if your domain of interest are the finites.


    Therefore I use the formulation: There is no x > 0 without ℵ smaller
    unit fractions (following from set theory: Every x > 0 has ℵ smaller
    unit fractions). This formulation covers all points of (0, 1] without
    any exception. Therefore it claims negative unit fractions. Contradiction.


    Nope.

    Yes, EVERY x > 0 has an infinite number of smaller unit fractions.

    all that proves is that there is no smallest unit fraction.

    You can't seem to understand unbounded sets, likely because your brain
    power is too limited.

    Regards, WM



    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Fri Jan 19 18:02:15 2024
    Le 19/01/2024 à 16:54, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/19/24 3:35 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 18/01/2024 à 19:39, FromTheRafters a écrit :
    WM formulated on Thursday :
    Le 18/01/2024 à 18:02, FromTheRafters a écrit :
    WM wrote :
    Le 18/01/2024 à 13:44, FromTheRafters a écrit :

    Yes, there are gaps in Q+ with respect to the positive reals
    fractional parts.

    That means NUF(x) does not increase by more than 1 without stopping >>>>>> afterwards.

    No, it doesn't.

    In mathematics it does. ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) > 0

    It starts with 0 and not with ℵ.

    It is not an action.

    Hogwash. It is a function.

    Then map it, done. No start here and finish there involved.

    The start is NUF(x) = 0 for an arbitrary x =< 0. Math proves ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n
    - 1/(n+1) > 0.
    This excludes an increase from 0 to more than 1 at some point.

    It excludes an increase from 0 to more than 1 at any finite point.

    Yes, of course. Any.

    Not at any point.

    Unit fractions sit only at finite points. Only there NUF can grow.

    Finish is NUF(x) = ℵ for arbitrary x >= 1.

    No, for any arbitrary finite x > 0.

    Wrong. For an arbitrary eps > 0.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to But what on Fri Jan 19 13:03:19 2024
    On 1/19/24 12:30 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 19/01/2024 à 16:54, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/19/24 3:31 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 19/01/2024 à 02:26, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/18/24 11:51 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 18/01/2024 à 13:51, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/18/24 4:09 AM, WM wrote:

    Because after every unit fraction the function NUF(x) is constant >>>>>>> over d_n

    So? That doesn't mean that NUF(x) can't instantly grow to infinity >>>>>> between 0 and the range (0,1]

    It does mean exactly this. Otherwise:

    If for every point x > 0 there are ℵ smaller unit fractions,
    then there exists no point x > 0 without ℵ smaller unit fractions. >>>>> Then there exist ℵ negative unit fractions.

    How do you get from

    there exists no point x > 0 without ℵ smaller unit fractions.

    to

    Then there exist ℵ negative unit fractions.

    There are ℵ unit fractions in total. No point of (0, 1] has ℵ at its >>> right-hand side, because every point has ℵ at its left-hand side. The
    interval (0, 1] is nothing but all its points. Therefore ℵ unit
    fractions are at the left-hand side of the interval (0, 1].

    You can't use a property of the individual members to the set.

    That is a myth of set theory which sometimes is valid and sometimes is
    not. But here we need no set theory at all. If this property holds for
    all points, then it holds for the interval.

    Says what theory?

    Maye you are using an incorrect theour that doesn't understand the
    distinction?


    Yes, for all x in the set, there are ℵ unit fractions to its left.

    That doesn't apply to the "Set" (0,1], since the set isn't a number.

    I use n interval and I use the geometrical property "is left-hand side of".

    But what says that (0,1] HAS a "left hand side"?


    Note, the claim that (0,1] is nothing but all its points you make
    elsewhere isn't a valid claim, as a set is a different thing then its
    members, which is part of the logic behind a set can't contain itself.

    That logic is irrelevant here, because I use geometry of points and
    intervals without reference to sets, just correct mathematics, so to say.

    No, you use incorrect mathematics.

    Mathematics (and Geometry) is based on logic.

    You need to show what logic your theory is working from, and how it
    supports your claims.


    Regards, WM





    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Fri Jan 19 13:26:40 2024
    On 1/19/2024 3:45 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 18/01/2024 à 19:55, Jim Burns a écrit :

    An ordinal after each final ordinal
    is not any of the final ordinals.
    Thus, it is non.final.

    A non.final ordinal, by definition,
    is followed by
    an ordinal with the same cardinality.

    Waffle.

    α+1 is the ordinal next.after α
    The set of ordinals preceding α+1 is
    the set of ordinals preceding α and α

    Represent an ordinal α as
    the set of ordinals preceding α
    ∀β: β ∈ α ⟺ β < α
    0 = {}
    1 = {0}
    2 = (0,1}
    ...
    ω = {0,1,2,…}
    ω+1 = {0,1,2,…;ω}
    ...

    α+1 = α∪{α}

    If
    no 1.to.1 map exists from
    the set α+1 of ordinals preceding α+1 to
    the set α of ordinals preceding α
    ¬(α+1 ⇉ α)
    then
    set α+1 has a larger cardinality than set α
    |α+1| > |α|

    If
    set α+1 has a larger cardinality than set α
    then
    α is a final ordinal.
    αᑉ⁺¹

    Define ω as
    the set of final ordinals
    ω = {α| αᑉ⁺¹}

    ω is not a final ordinal.

    | Assume otherwise.
    | Assume ω is a final ordinal.
    |
    | No 1.to.1 map exists from
    | the set ω+1 of ordinals preceding ω+1 to
    | the set ω of ordinals preceding ω
    | ¬(ω+1 ⇉ ω)
    | ¬({0,1,2,…;ω} ⇉ {0,1,2,…})
    |
    | However,
    | ω+1 = {0,1,2,…;ω} only holds final ordinals,
    | thus only elements of the set ω
    | Identity α ⟼ α is 1.to.1 and
    | it is from ω+1 to ω
    | ω+1 ⇉ ω
    | Contradiction.

    Therefore,
    ω is not a final ordinal.
    {0,1,2,…;ω} ⇉ {0,1,2,…}

    There are ℵ unit fractions in total.

    Also, there are ℵ₀ unit fractions in part.
    ... = |⅟ℕ∩(0,⅟k)| = |⅟ℕ∩(0,⅟k⁺¹)| = ...

    No point of (0, 1] has ℵ at its right-hand side,
    because every point has ℵ at its left-hand side.

    Each point of (0,1] has, to its right,
    unit fractions with a finite ordinal, and
    to its left, unit fractions with an ordinal
    _after_ each final ordinal, thus non.final.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Fri Jan 19 13:22:02 2024
    On 1/19/24 1:02 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 19/01/2024 à 16:54, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/19/24 3:35 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 18/01/2024 à 19:39, FromTheRafters a écrit :
    WM formulated on Thursday :
    Le 18/01/2024 à 18:02, FromTheRafters a écrit :
    WM wrote :
    Le 18/01/2024 à 13:44, FromTheRafters a écrit :

    Yes, there are gaps in Q+ with respect to the positive reals
    fractional parts.

    That means NUF(x) does not increase by more than 1 without
    stopping afterwards.

    No, it doesn't.

    In mathematics it does. ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) > 0

    It starts with 0 and not with ℵ.

    It is not an action.

    Hogwash. It is a function.

    Then map it, done. No start here and finish there involved.

    The start is NUF(x) = 0 for an arbitrary x =< 0. Math proves ∀n ∈ ℕ: >>> 1/n - 1/(n+1) > 0.
    This excludes an increase from 0 to more than 1 at some point.

    It excludes an increase from 0 to more than 1 at any finite point.

    Yes, of course. Any.

    Not at any point.

    Unit fractions sit only at finite points. Only there NUF can grow.

    Nothing in its definition says that.

    That assumes that unit fractions are indexable from their smallest value
    end, which they are not.


    Finish is NUF(x) = ℵ for arbitrary x >= 1.

    No, for any arbitrary finite x > 0.

    Wrong. For an arbitrary eps > 0.

    Only FINITE eps.

    if eps is not finite, but some transfinite small number, your
    definitions don't apply. In the transfinitely small gap between 0 and
    (0,1] NUF(x) isn't defined, and can jump.


    Regards, WM



    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Fri Jan 19 19:22:46 2024
    Le 19/01/2024 à 19:26, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 1/19/2024 3:45 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 18/01/2024 à 19:55, Jim Burns a écrit :

    An ordinal after each final ordinal
    is not any of the final ordinals.
    Thus, it is non.final.

    A non.final ordinal, by definition,
    is followed by
    an ordinal with the same cardinality.

    Waffle.

    α+1 is the ordinal next.after α
    The set of ordinals preceding α+1 is
    the set of ordinals preceding α and α

    Represent an ordinal α as
    the set of ordinals preceding α
    ∀β: β ∈ α ⟺ β < α
    0 = {}
    1 = {0}
    2 = (0,1}
    ...
    ω = {0,1,2,…}
    ω+1 = {0,1,2,…;ω}

    See? The last ones are not definable. They have no FISON.

    No point of (0, 1] has ℵ at its right-hand side,
    because every point has ℵ at its left-hand side.

    Each point of (0,1] has, to its right,
    unit fractions with a finite ordinal, and
    to its left, unit fractions with an ordinal
    _after_ each final ordinal, thus non.final.

    The interval (0, 1] has in this respect the same property as all its
    points. Geometry. No matheologial nonsense, no quantifier magic.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Fri Jan 19 19:26:32 2024
    Le 19/01/2024 à 19:22, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/19/24 1:02 PM, WM wrote:

    Unit fractions sit only at finite points. Only there NUF can grow.

    Nothing in its definition says that.

    Try again.

    That assumes that unit fractions are indexable from their smallest value
    end, which they are not.

    It assumes that all unit fractions are existing and are indexed by their denominator.


    Finish is NUF(x) = ℵ for arbitrary x >= 1.

    No, for any arbitrary finite x > 0.

    Wrong. For an arbitrary eps > 0.

    Only FINITE eps.

    if eps is not finite, but some transfinite small number, your
    definitions don't apply. In the transfinitely small gap between 0 and
    (0,1] NUF(x) isn't defined, and can jump.

    No, there are no indexed unit fractions in this gap (and there is no such
    gap).

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Fri Jan 19 15:33:02 2024
    On 1/19/2024 2:22 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 19/01/2024 à 19:26, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 1/19/2024 3:45 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 18/01/2024 à 19:55, Jim Burns a écrit :

    An ordinal after each final ordinal
    is not any of the final ordinals.
    Thus, it is non.final.

    A non.final ordinal, by definition,
    is followed by
    an ordinal with the same cardinality.

    Waffle.

    α+1 is the ordinal next.after α
    The set of  ordinals preceding α+1  is
    the set of  ordinals preceding α and α

    Represent an ordinal α as
    the set of ordinals preceding α
    ∀β: β ∈ α  ⟺  β < α
    0 = {}
    1 = {0}
    2 = (0,1}
    ...
    ω = {0,1,2,…}
    ω+1 = {0,1,2,…;ω}

    See?
    The last ones are not definable.
    They have no FISON.

    ω is the set of final ordinals.
    ω = {α ∈ Ord| | ¬(α+1 ⇉ α)}

    The last final ordinal not.exists.

    | Assume otherwise.
    | Assume ¬(λ+1 ⇉ λ) ∧ λ+2 ⇉ λ+1
    |
    | Exists g: λ+2 ⇉ λ+1
    |
    | Define f: λ+1 ⇉ λ
    | if g(α) ≠ λ+1
    | then f(α) = g(α)
    | else f(α) = g(λ+1)
    |
    | f is 1.to.1 from λ+1 to λ
    |
    | However, ¬(λ+1 ⇉ λ)
    | No such map exists.
    | Contradiction.

    Therefore,
    the last final ordinal not.exists.

    The last ones are not definable.
    They have no FISON.

    They not.exist.
    "They have no FISON" is true the same way
    "The present king of France is bald" is true.
    In the least useful way possible.

    Am I right to think that
    you (Wolfgang Mückenheim of Hochschule Augsburg)
    don't object to reasoning from contradictions?

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Fri Jan 19 15:51:05 2024
    On 1/18/2024 10:09 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On Thursday, January 18, 2024
    at 12:28:54 PM UTC-8, Jim Burns wrote:

    Our current theory of the line,
    a theory stress.tested beyond the dreams of Zeno,
    is that, in topological terms,
    the line is _one component_ that it can't be
    partitioned into two non.empty open sets.

    Well there are lots of topologies.

    There is one meaning I intend for "component",
    as used in topology.area.of.study.

    One meaning across all
    topologies.set.collections.designated.the.opens.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Fri Jan 19 16:48:24 2024
    On 1/19/24 2:26 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 19/01/2024 à 19:22, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/19/24 1:02 PM, WM wrote:

    Unit fractions sit only at finite points. Only there NUF can grow.

    Nothing in its definition says that.

    Try again.

    You try again. Where does the definiton of NUF(x) say what you are claiming.

    It only has values define at finite value. Nothing in the definiton of
    NUF(x) talks about the difference of NUF(x) and a prior NUF(x)


    That assumes that unit fractions are indexable from their smallest
    value end, which they are not.

    It assumes that all unit fractions are existing and are indexed by their denominator.

    which indexes them from 1/1, which is the LARGEST value of x given to NUF(x)



    Finish is NUF(x) = ℵ for arbitrary x >= 1.

    No, for any arbitrary finite x > 0.

    Wrong. For an arbitrary eps > 0.

    Only FINITE eps.

    if eps is not finite, but some transfinite small number, your
    definitions don't apply. In the transfinitely small gap between 0 and
    (0,1] NUF(x) isn't defined, and can jump.

    No, there are no indexed unit fractions in this gap (and there is no
    such gap).

    and no reason NUF(x) can't jump to infinity for every unit fraction.



    Regards, WM




    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Fri Jan 19 22:33:02 2024
    Le 19/01/2024 à 23:26, FromTheRafters a écrit :
    WM wrote :
    Le 19/01/2024 à 19:26, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 1/19/2024 3:45 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 18/01/2024 à 19:55, Jim Burns a écrit :

    An ordinal after each final ordinal
    is not any of the final ordinals.
    Thus, it is non.final.

    A non.final ordinal, by definition,
    is followed by
    an ordinal with the same cardinality.

    Waffle.

    α+1 is the ordinal next.after α
    The set of ordinals preceding α+1 is
    the set of ordinals preceding α and α

    Represent an ordinal α as
    the set of ordinals preceding α
    ∀β: β ∈ α ⟺ β < α
    0 = {}
    1 = {0}
    2 = (0,1}
    ...
    ω = {0,1,2,…}
    ω+1 = {0,1,2,…;ω}

    See? The last ones are not definable. They have no FISON.

    Last ones? These are ordinals, ω has an IISON.

    Definabl numbers have FISONs.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Fri Jan 19 22:49:29 2024
    Le 19/01/2024 à 21:33, Jim Burns a écrit :

    "They have no FISON" is true the same way
    "The present king of France is bald" is true.
    In the least useful way possible.

    Wrong. There is no present king but, assuming actual infinity, there is
    ω.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Fri Jan 19 22:54:17 2024
    Le 19/01/2024 à 22:48, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/19/24 2:26 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 19/01/2024 à 19:22, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/19/24 1:02 PM, WM wrote:

    Unit fractions sit only at finite points. Only there NUF can grow.

    Nothing in its definition says that.

    Try again.

    You try again. Where does the definiton of NUF(x) say what you are claiming.

    NUF(x) counts the unit fractions between 0 and x.

    It only has values define at finite value. Nothing in the definiton of
    NUF(x) talks about the difference of NUF(x) and a prior NUF(x)

    This formula does: ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) = d_n > 0


    That assumes that unit fractions are indexable from their smallest
    value end, which they are not.

    It assumes that all unit fractions are existing and are indexed by their
    denominator.

    which indexes them

    Yes.

    from 1/1,

    No, the index has no direction. It is but a number, namely the
    denominator.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Fri Jan 19 18:18:47 2024
    On 1/19/24 5:49 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 19/01/2024 à 21:33, Jim Burns a écrit :

    "They have no FISON" is true the same way
    "The present king of France is bald" is true.
    In the least useful way possible.

    Wrong. There is no present king but, assuming actual infinity, there is ω.

    Regards, WM

    Which isn't a Natural Number.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mild Shock@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Sat Jan 20 01:11:09 2024
    Ross Finlayson schrieb:
    It's pretty simple that anything in proof theory has a model in model theory.

    You are a complete moron. A proof theoretical statement
    is an existential statement of the form:

    T |- A <=>

    ∃j T |- j: A

    T is syntactically derivable from A when there is a
    judgement j, i.e. a deduction of A from T. A model
    theoretical statement is an universal statement of the form

    T |= A <=>

    ∀M (M[T]=1 => M[A]=1)

    T is semantically derivable from A when every model
    M that satisfies T also satisfies A.


    There is no theorem anywhere in classical proof theory and
    model theory that would say a proof is a model.

    There is something in non-classical proof theory where
    a judgegement indicates a model.

    And then there is Gödels completness theorem, which says
    that if the is no judgement then there is a counter model.

    What are you talking about peanut brain?

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mild Shock@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Sat Jan 20 01:13:31 2024
    peanut brain, you need some real spanking. You are talking
    nonsense all day long all day in. What are you trying
    the British Museum approach. Hope that you one day say s
    something sensible , you monkey with a type writer.

    Mild Shock schrieb:
    Ross Finlayson schrieb:
    It's pretty simple that anything in proof theory has a model in model
    theory.

    You are a complete moron. A proof theoretical statement
    is an existential statement of the form:

    T |- A <=>

    ∃j T |- j: A

    T is syntactically derivable from A when there is a
    judgement j, i.e. a deduction of A from T. A model
    theoretical statement is an universal statement of the form

    T |= A <=>

    ∀M (M[T]=1 => M[A]=1)

    T is semantically derivable from A when every model
    M that satisfies T also satisfies A.


    There is no theorem anywhere in classical proof theory and
    model theory that would say a proof is a model.

    There is something in non-classical proof theory where
    a judgegement indicates a model.

    And then there is Gödels completness theorem, which says
    that if the is no judgement then there is a counter model.

    What are you talking about peanut brain?


    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mild Shock@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Sat Jan 20 01:18:13 2024
    Idiot brainless spam without any content.
    Just random nonsense stringed together.

    Rossy Boy the ape sitting in the Britsh Museum
    in front of his typewriter.

    Ross Finlayson schrieb:
    On Friday, January 19, 2024 at 12:51:15 PM UTC-8, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 1/18/2024 10:09 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On Thursday, January 18, 2024
    at 12:28:54 PM UTC-8, Jim Burns wrote:

    Our current theory of the line,
    a theory stress.tested beyond the dreams of Zeno,
    is that, in topological terms,
    the line is _one component_ that it can't be
    partitioned into two non.empty open sets.
    Well there are lots of topologies.
    There is one meaning I intend for "component",
    as used in topology.area.of.study.

    One meaning across all
    topologies.set.collections.designated.the.opens.




    Why not?

    I'm unfamiliar with this usage of, "component".
    Can you detail its definition?

    Of course you know that "open" and "closed" aren't
    together a binary property, in topology.

    Then just saying so, Dedekind cuts only follow
    equivalence classes of sequences that are Cauchy,
    and initial ordinals only follow equivalence classes
    of sets that are cardinals, and furthermore vary
    according to the statuses of CH and GCH. I.e.
    any definition you provide has to be written in
    terms of equivalence classes of sequences, or series
    if you will that are Cauchy.

    Anyways can you help me know where to find
    a definition of "component" or whether it's yours.

    A definition of "continuous domain" is easier to find these days.


    I'm glad I sat a mathematics degree, it covered
    many things expected to be known by all competent formalists.


    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mild Shock@21:1/5 to Mild Shock on Sat Jan 20 01:19:17 2024
    I'm glad I sat a mathematics degree

    I didn't know that they give math degrees
    in mexican border prisons.

    Mild Shock schrieb:
    Idiot brainless spam without any content.
    Just random nonsense stringed together.

    Rossy Boy the ape sitting in the Britsh Museum
    in front of his typewriter.

    Ross Finlayson schrieb:
    On Friday, January 19, 2024 at 12:51:15 PM UTC-8, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 1/18/2024 10:09 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On Thursday, January 18, 2024
    at 12:28:54 PM UTC-8, Jim Burns wrote:

    Our current theory of the line,
    a theory stress.tested beyond the dreams of Zeno,
    is that, in topological terms,
    the line is _one component_ that it can't be
    partitioned into two non.empty open sets.
    Well there are lots of topologies.
    There is one meaning I intend for "component",
    as used in topology.area.of.study.

    One meaning across all
    topologies.set.collections.designated.the.opens.




    Why not?

    I'm unfamiliar with this usage of, "component".
    Can you detail its definition?

    Of course you know that "open" and "closed" aren't
    together a binary property, in topology.

    Then just saying so, Dedekind cuts only follow
    equivalence classes of sequences that are Cauchy,
    and initial ordinals only follow equivalence classes
    of sets that are cardinals, and furthermore vary
    according to the statuses of CH and GCH.  I.e.
    any definition you provide has to be written in
    terms of equivalence classes of sequences, or series
    if you will that are Cauchy.

    Anyways can you help me know where to find
    a definition of "component" or whether it's yours.

    A definition of "continuous domain" is easier to find these days.


    I'm glad I sat a mathematics degree, it covered
    many things expected to be known by all competent formalists.



    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Sat Jan 20 11:00:00 2024
    Le 20/01/2024 à 00:18, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/19/24 5:54 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 19/01/2024 à 22:48, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/19/24 2:26 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 19/01/2024 à 19:22, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/19/24 1:02 PM, WM wrote:

    Unit fractions sit only at finite points. Only there NUF can grow.

    Nothing in its definition says that.

    Try again.

    You try again. Where does the definiton of NUF(x) say what you are
    claiming.

    NUF(x) counts the unit fractions between 0 and x.

    And why does that say it can have the value of 1?

    That would require there to be a last unit fraction, and thus a highest Natural Number, which doesn't exist.

    The sequence of unit fractions ends before zero. Therefore there is a last
    one or more last ones. Since all have gaps, there is one last one.

    No, the index has no direction. It is but a number, namely the denominator.

    But it does, it indexes them from 1, and thus 1/1

    Indexed DO have direction, since the first number is not the successor
    of any number.

    The first number has no direction, the last number has no direction, no
    index has a direction. They are simply there or are not there. Actual
    infinity says that all are there. That is presumed.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Sat Jan 20 07:29:58 2024
    On 1/20/24 6:00 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 20/01/2024 à 00:18, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/19/24 5:54 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 19/01/2024 à 22:48, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/19/24 2:26 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 19/01/2024 à 19:22, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/19/24 1:02 PM, WM wrote:

    Unit fractions sit only at finite points. Only there NUF can grow. >>>>>>
    Nothing in its definition says that.

    Try again.

    You try again. Where does the definiton of NUF(x) say what you are
    claiming.

    NUF(x) counts the unit fractions between 0 and x.

    And why does that say it can have the value of 1?

    That would require there to be a last unit fraction, and thus a
    highest Natural Number, which doesn't exist.

    The sequence of unit fractions ends before zero. Therefore there is a
    last one or more last ones. Since all have gaps, there is one last one.

    Nope. You don't understand unbounded sets.

    Note "More last ones" just means they continue.


    No, the index has no direction. It is but a number, namely the
    denominator.

    But it does, it indexes them from 1, and thus 1/1

    Indexed DO have direction, since the first number is not the successor
    of any number.

    The first number has no direction, the last number has no direction, no
    index has a direction. They are simply there or are not there. Actual infinity says that all are there. That is presumed.

    No, the first has a direction, the dirrection of the "next" operator.

    First has a next but no previous, so it establishes a direction.

    In fact, every number has a next that establishes the direction that
    indexing runs in.

    You don't seem to know the meaning of the words, or are just ignoring
    the meaning because it is inconvient for your ideas (which makes you a
    liar).



    Regards, WM



    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Sat Jan 20 07:47:42 2024
    On 1/19/2024 6:29 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On Friday, January 19, 2024
    at 12:51:15 PM UTC-8, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 1/18/2024 10:09 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On Thursday, January 18, 2024
    at 12:28:54 PM UTC-8, Jim Burns wrote:

    Our current theory of the line,
    a theory stress.tested beyond the dreams of Zeno,
    is that, in topological terms,
    the line is _one component_ that it can't be
    partitioned into two non.empty open sets.

    Well there are lots of topologies.

    There is one meaning I intend for "component",
    as used in topology.area.of.study.

    One meaning across all
    topologies.set.collections.designated.the.opens.

    I'm unfamiliar with this usage of, "component".
    Can you detail its definition?

    We need "topological space" "disconnected" and
    "connected component"

    | A topological space is the most general type of
    | a mathematical space that allows for the definition of
    | limits, continuity, and connectedness. [...]
    |
    | A topology on a set X may be defined as
    | a collection τ of subsets of X, called open sets
    | and satisfying the following axioms:
    |
    | 1. The empty set and X itself belong to τ
    | 2. Any arbitrary (finite or infinite) union of
    | members of τ belongs to τ
    | 3. The intersection of any finite number of
    | members of τ belongs to τ
    [1]

    | A topological space X is said to be disconnected if
    | it is the union of two disjoint non-empty open sets.
    | Otherwise, X is said to be connected. [...]
    |
    | The connected component of a point x in X is
    | the union of all connected subsets of X that contain x
    | it is the unique largest (with respect to ⊆)
    | connected subset of X that contains x
    [2]

    I said: ℝ has one component.
    Better: ℝ is connected.

    Delete ℼ from ℝ and ℝ\{ℼ} is disconnected.
    ℝ\{ℼ} = (-∞,ℼ)∪(ℼ,+∞)

    It's possible to map
    (-∞,ℼ) ⟶ 0 and (ℼ,+∞) ⟶ 1
    and be continuous at each point in ℝ\{ℼ}
    But that's not what we want
    when we ask for a continuous function.

    In order to get what we want,
    we must include ℼ in our discussion,
    even if we never use ℼ
    We must include uncountably.many points,
    which even an endless process of naming can't use.

    They must be there, used or unused, in order to
    be able talk about continuous functions
    with it meaning what we want.

    [1]
    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Topological_space

    [2]
    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Connected_space

    Of course you know that "open" and "closed" aren't
    together a binary property, in topology.

    Point x is in the interior of set S if
    some open set Oₓ which holds x is entirely in S

    Point x is in the exterior of set S if
    some open set O′ₓ which holds x is entirely not-in S

    Point x is in the boundary of set S if
    if it isn't in its interior or its exterior.

    A closed set contains all of its boundary.
    An open set contains none of its boundary.

    And then, there are the sets containing
    neither all nor none.


    For some sets, their boundary is the empty set.
    They contain all and none of the empty set.
    They are closed and open.
    They are called clopen sets,
    which proves mathematicians have a sense of humor.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Dieter Heidorn@21:1/5 to Richard Damon on Sat Jan 20 17:13:47 2024
    Richard Damon schrieb:
    On 1/20/24 6:00 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 20/01/2024 à 00:18, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/19/24 5:54 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 19/01/2024 à 22:48, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/19/24 2:26 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 19/01/2024 à 19:22, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/19/24 1:02 PM, WM wrote:

    Unit fractions sit only at finite points. Only there NUF can grow. >>>>>>>
    Nothing in its definition says that.

    Try again.

    You try again. Where does the definiton of NUF(x) say what you are
    claiming.

    NUF(x) counts the unit fractions between 0 and x.

    And why does that say it can have the value of 1?

    That would require there to be a last unit fraction, and thus a
    highest Natural Number, which doesn't exist.

    The sequence of unit fractions ends before zero. Therefore there is a
    last one or more last ones. Since all have gaps, there is one last one.

    Nope. You don't understand unbounded sets.

    Note "More last ones" just means they continue.





    No, the index has no direction. It is but a number, namely the
    denominator.

    But it does, it indexes them from 1, and thus 1/1

    Indexed DO have direction, since the first number is not the
    successor of any number.

    The first number has no direction, the last number has no direction,
    no index has a direction. They are simply there or are not there.
    Actual infinity says that all are there. That is presumed.

    No, the first has a direction, the dirrection of the "next" operator.

    First has a next but no previous, so it establishes a direction.

    In fact, every number has a next that establishes the direction that
    indexing runs in.


    Perhaps it would be better to use the term "ordered set" instead of "direction". See Cantor:

    ----------------------------------------------------------------------
    "We call an aggregate M 'simply ordered' if a definite 'order of
    precedence' (Rangordnung) rules over its elements m, so that, of
    every two elements m_1 and m_2 one takes the 'lower' and the other
    the 'higher' rank, and so that, if of three elements m_1, m_2 , and
    m_3, m_1, say, is of lower rank than m_2, and m_2 is of lower rank
    than m_3, then m_1 is of lower rank than m_3.
    The relation of two elements m_1 and m_2 in which m_1 has the lower
    rank in the given order of precedence and m_2 the higher, is expressed
    by the formulae :

    (1) m_1 <' m_2 , m_2 '> m_1 .

    Thus, for example, every aggregate P of points defined on a straight
    line is a simply ordered aggregate if, of every two points p_1 and p_2 belonging to it, that one whose co-ordinate (an origin and a positive
    direction having been fixed upon) is the lesser is given the lower
    rank."

    (Georg Cantor: Contributions to the founding of the theory of
    transfinite numbers. Dover Publications, 1915; p.110) ----------------------------------------------------------------------

    Dieter Heidorn

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Sat Jan 20 11:24:10 2024
    On 1/19/2024 5:49 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 19/01/2024 à 21:33, Jim Burns a écrit :

    "They have no FISON" is true the same way
    "The present king of France is bald" is true.
    In the least useful way possible.

    Wrong.
    There is no present king but,
    assuming actual infinity,
    there is ω.

    ω is defined to be the set of final.ordinals
    ω isn't a final.ordinal.
    No final.ordinal has.no.FISON.
    No element.of.ω has.no.FISON.
    No final.ordinal is the last final.ordinal.
    No element.of.ω is the last element.of.ω

    ω isn't a final ordinal
    |
    | Assume otherwise.
    | Assume ω is a final ordinal
    |
    | ω is the set of final.ordinals.
    | ω+1 = {0,1,2,…;ω} ⊆ ω
    | ≡: ω+1 ⇉ ω 1.to.1
    | |ω| = |ω+1|
    | ω isn't a final ordinal.
    | Contradiction.

    No final.ordinal is the last final.ordinal.
    |
    | Assume otherwise.
    | Assume λ is the last final.ordinal.
    | |λ| < |λ+1| = |λ+2|
    |
    | |λ+1| = |λ+2|
    | exists g: λ+2 ⇉ λ+1 1.to.1
    |
    | Define f: λ+1 ⇉ λ
    | such that
    | if g(α) ≠ λ+1
    | then f(α) = g(α)
    | else f(α) = g(λ+1)
    |
    | exists f: λ+1 ⇉ λ 1.to.1
    | |λ| = |λ+1|
    |
    | However,
    | |λ| < |λ+1|
    | not.exists f: λ+1 ⇉ λ 1.to.1
    | Contradiction.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Sat Jan 20 19:49:31 2024
    On 1/20/2024 1:05 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On Saturday, January 20, 2024
    at 4:47:48 AM UTC-8, Jim Burns wrote:

    [...]

    So, line-reals follow the integer continuum,
    a unit magnitude of an integer,
    for the integer part, and non-integer part,
    of a real number, of the linear continuum.

    Of course,
    their establishment as continuous domains, involves
    their relations, in function theory,
    and topology.

    What I consider essential:

    Natural numbers are not too big to fail at
    matching nearby natural numbers.
    There are no 1.to.1 maps from 1.inserted.
    ¬(⟨0,…,k⟩ ⇇ ⟨0,…,k,k+1⟩) ⟺ k ∈ ℕ

    Rational numbers do not have an inherent scale.
    ∀p ∈ ℚ: ∀n ∈ ℕ₁: p/n ∈ ℚ ∧ n⋅p ∈ ℚ

    Real numbers do not have functions.which.jump
    and are continuous everywhere.
    For each non.empty split F,H of ℝ
    exists x ∈ ℝ between F and H


    These claims are sufficient to begin,
    for our purposes, for _those_ purposes:
    not.matching, scaling, not.jumping.

    They can be augmented by
    claims which are not.first.false

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Sun Jan 21 08:34:39 2024
    Le 20/01/2024 à 17:24, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 1/19/2024 5:49 PM, WM wrote:

    ω is defined to be the set of final.ordinals
    ω isn't a final.ordinal.

    And many finite ordinals before ω are no final ordinals too. They have no FISONs. They are dark.

    No final.ordinal has.no.FISON.

    By definition.

    No element.of.ω has.no.FISON.

    Wrong. This would imply that no element of (0, 1] has less than ℵ LHS
    unit fractions, but the interval has no LHS unit fractions. A beautiful contradiction in geometry.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Sun Jan 21 08:25:40 2024
    Le 20/01/2024 à 13:29, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/20/24 6:00 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 20/01/2024 à 00:18, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/19/24 5:54 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 19/01/2024 à 22:48, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/19/24 2:26 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 19/01/2024 à 19:22, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/19/24 1:02 PM, WM wrote:

    Unit fractions sit only at finite points. Only there NUF can grow. >>>>>>>
    Nothing in its definition says that.

    Try again.

    You try again. Where does the definiton of NUF(x) say what you are
    claiming.

    NUF(x) counts the unit fractions between 0 and x.

    And why does that say it can have the value of 1?

    That would require there to be a last unit fraction, and thus a
    highest Natural Number, which doesn't exist.

    The sequence of unit fractions ends before zero. Therefore there is a
    last one or more last ones. Since all have gaps, there is one last one.

    Nope.

    Note "More last ones" just means they continue.

    They cannot continue beyond zero. More last ones would mean many between 0
    and (0, 1]. Your infinitesimals.

    The first number has no direction, the last number has no direction, no
    index has a direction. They are simply there or are not there. Actual
    infinity says that all are there. That is presumed.

    No, the first has a direction, the dirrection of the "next" operator.

    The operator does not belong to the number.

    First has a next but no previous, so it establishes a direction.

    The set has an order, may be called a direction, but not any number.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Sun Jan 21 08:03:44 2024
    On 1/21/24 3:25 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 20/01/2024 à 13:29, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/20/24 6:00 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 20/01/2024 à 00:18, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/19/24 5:54 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 19/01/2024 à 22:48, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/19/24 2:26 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 19/01/2024 à 19:22, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/19/24 1:02 PM, WM wrote:

    Unit fractions sit only at finite points. Only there NUF can grow. >>>>>>>>
    Nothing in its definition says that.

    Try again.

    You try again. Where does the definiton of NUF(x) say what you are >>>>>> claiming.

    NUF(x) counts the unit fractions between 0 and x.

    And why does that say it can have the value of 1?

    That would require there to be a last unit fraction, and thus a
    highest Natural Number, which doesn't exist.

    The sequence of unit fractions ends before zero. Therefore there is a
    last one or more last ones. Since all have gaps, there is one last one.

    Nope.

    Note "More last ones" just means they continue.

    They cannot continue beyond zero. More last ones would mean many between
    0 and (0, 1]. Your infinitesimals.

    But they do extend from what ever point you are at towards zero, and
    there is an unbounded number of them, so you never get to the last one,
    as such a thing doesn't exist.


    The first number has no direction, the last number has no direction,
    no index has a direction. They are simply there or are not there.
    Actual infinity says that all are there. That is presumed.

    No, the first has a direction, the dirrection of the "next" operator.

    The operator does not belong to the number.

    No, but it creates numbers, and establishes a direction of the number
    sequence.


    First has a next but no previous, so it establishes a direction.

    The set has an order, may be called a direction, but not any number.

    Then why did YOU try to establish a "forward" direction from the "last"
    (you call it lowest) number?

    NUF(x) == 1 requires that you can find a lowest x that is a unit
    fraction that only has a forward towards larger unit fractions, (lower
    natural numbers), but we know that every natural number has a higher
    natural number, and thus every unit fraction has a lower unit fraction,
    and thus no unit fraction is at the point where NUF(x) == 1.

    Your whole logic is based on the idea that there must be a "last"
    natural number, (to make a smallest unit fraction) but ZFC says such a
    thing does not exist.


    Regards, WM




    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Sun Jan 21 14:58:08 2024
    On 1/21/2024 3:34 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 20/01/2024 à 17:24, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 1/19/2024 5:49 PM, WM wrote:

    ω is defined to be the set of final.ordinals
    ω isn't a final.ordinal.

    And many finite ordinals before ω are
    no final ordinals too.

    Each ordinal is represented as
    the set of ordinals preceding it.
    α ∈ β ⟺ α < β

    ω is defined to be the set of final.ordinals.
    Each ordinal is represented as
    the set of ordinals preceding it.

    | ∀α:( α ∈ ω ⟺ ¬(α ⇇ α∪{α}) )
    is the same as
    | ∀α:( α < ω ⟺ ¬(α ⇇ α∪{α}) )

    | α is in ω iff α is not.final
    is the same as
    | α is before ω iff α is not.final

    ¬∃α < ω: ¬¬(α ⇇ α∪{α})
    No not.final.ordinal is before ω

    They have no FISONs.
    They are dark.

    They are not in/before ω

    I think that,
    when you (WM) see "infinite"
    you think "ridiculously.big",
    a thought I think at least partly because,
    when you (WM) try to give a counter.example to Cantor,
    you describe some ridiculously.big
    (final) number.which.inserting.another.does.not.fit.

    That's not what "infinite" means.
    Infinitely.many is more than each
    (final) number.which.inserting.another.does.not.fit,
    even ridiculously.big ones.

    No final.ordinal has.no.FISON.

    By definition.

    No element.of.ω has.no.FISON.

    Wrong.

    And yet,
    final.ordinal == element.of.ω

    How can one be true and the other false?

    This would imply that
    no element of (0, 1] has less than
    ℵ LHS unit fractions, but
    the interval has no LHS unit fractions.

    In (0,x]
    for each
    (final) number.which.inserting.another.does.not.fit,
    there are more unit fractions than that.
    |⅟ℕ₁∩(0,x]| ∉ ω

    In (x,1]
    there is some
    (final) number.which.inserting.another.does.not.fit
    number of unit fractions.
    |⅟ℕ₁∩(x,1]| ∈ ω

    In (-∞,0]
    there are no unit fractions.
    |⅟ℕ₁∩(-∞,0]| = 0

    A beautiful contradiction in geometry.

    Yes,
    the set ω of final.ordinals is not a final.ordinal.

    However,
    that isn't a contradiction.
    We get that by augmenting what we mean
    with only not.first.false claims.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Mon Jan 22 08:02:41 2024
    Le 21/01/2024 à 14:03, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/21/24 3:25 AM, WM wrote:

    The sequence of unit fractions ends before zero. Therefore there is a
    last one or more last ones. Since all have gaps, there is one last one. >>>
    Nope.

    Note "More last ones" just means they continue.

    They cannot continue beyond zero. More last ones would mean many between
    0 and (0, 1]. Your infinitesimals.

    But they do extend from what ever point you are at towards zero, and
    there is an unbounded number of them, so you never get to the last one,
    as such a thing doesn't exist.

    Anyhow you cannot name all, because "all" implies that none is missing.

    The first number has no direction, the last number has no direction,
    no index has a direction. They are simply there or are not there.
    Actual infinity says that all are there. That is presumed.

    No, the first has a direction, the dirrection of the "next" operator.

    The operator does not belong to the number.

    No, but it creates numbers, and establishes a direction of the number sequence.

    Yes, a direction of the sequence but not of any number.


    First has a next but no previous, so it establishes a direction.

    The set has an order, may be called a direction, but not any number.

    Then why did YOU try to establish a "forward" direction from the "last"
    (you call it lowest) number?

    Because the sequence has an order.

    Your whole logic is based on the idea that there must be a "last"
    natural number, (to make a smallest unit fraction) but ZFC says such a
    thing does not exist.

    My logic is based on mathematics:
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) > 0
    ∀1/n ∈ ℝ: (∀x ∈ (0,1]: 1/n < x) ⇒ 1/n ≤ 0.
    ∀x ∈ (0, 1] ∃^ℵo 1/n < x

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Mon Jan 22 08:16:52 2024
    Le 21/01/2024 à 20:58, Jim Burns a écrit :

    Infinitely.many is more than each
    (final) number.

    Infinity is more than can be expressed by finite numbers. But all visible numbers are measured by the last temporarily last final or visible number,
    and therefore are far less than ω or ℵ.
    ∀n ∈ ℕ_def: |ℕ \ {1, 2, 3, ..., n}| = ℵ.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Mon Jan 22 07:13:43 2024
    On 1/22/2024 3:16 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 21/01/2024 à 20:58, Jim Burns a écrit :

    Infinitely.many is more than each
    (final) number.

    Infinity is more than
    can be expressed by finite numbers.

    ω is the set of finite (final) ordinals.
    ω is an infinite (not.final) ordinal.
    α ∈ ω ⟺ ¬(a ⇇ a+1)
    ω ⇇ ω+1


    ordinal β is the set of preceding ordinals
    α ∈ β ⟺ α < β

    α+1 means α∪{α}

    α ⇇ β
    means
    exists 1.to.1 map to α from β
    means
    ¬(|α| < |β|)

    α ∈ ω ⟺ |α| < |α+1|
    ¬(|ω| < |ω+1|)

    |α| < |β| ⊻ α ⇇ β

    non.empty ordinal.set S holds a first
    S ⊆ Ord ∧ S≠{} :⇒
    ∃α∈S ∀β∈S α≤β

    But all visible numbers are measured by
    the last temporarily last
    final or visible number,

    No final number n measures all final numbers.
    final: |n| < |n+1| < |n+2|

    and therefore are far less than ω or ℵ.
    ∀n ∈ ℕ_def: |ℕ \ {1, 2, 3, ..., n}| = ℵ.

    ∀n ∈ ℕ:
    ℕ\{1,…,n} ⇇ ℕ
    ℕ\{1,…,n} ⇉ ℕ

    ∀n ∈ ℕ:
    ¬(|ℕ\{1….,n}| < |ℕ|)
    ¬(|ℕ\{1,…,n}| > |ℕ|)
    |ℕ\{1,…,n}| = |ℕ|

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Mon Jan 22 07:54:52 2024
    On 1/22/24 3:16 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 21/01/2024 à 20:58, Jim Burns a écrit :

    Infinitely.many is more than each
    (final) number.

    Infinity is more than can be expressed by finite numbers. But all
    visible numbers are measured by the last temporarily last final or
    visible number, and therefore are far less than ω or ℵ.
    ∀n ∈ ℕ_def: |ℕ \ {1, 2, 3, ..., n}| = ℵ.

    Regards, WM

    But there is no "last" even temporarily.

    All you are saying really is that any chosen finite initial sequence of
    the Natural Numbers leaves most of the Natural Numbers out.

    So?

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to Which still on Mon Jan 22 07:52:49 2024
    On 1/22/24 3:02 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 21/01/2024 à 14:03, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/21/24 3:25 AM, WM wrote:

    The sequence of unit fractions ends before zero. Therefore there is
    a last one or more last ones. Since all have gaps, there is one
    last one.

    Nope.

    Note "More last ones" just means they continue.

    They cannot continue beyond zero. More last ones would mean many
    between 0 and (0, 1]. Your infinitesimals.

    But they do extend from what ever point you are at towards zero, and
    there is an unbounded number of them, so you never get to the last
    one, as such a thing doesn't exist.

    Anyhow you cannot name all, because "all" implies that none is missing.

    And none are from the set that I can give a name to.

    Of course I can't name an infinite number of them at once, but that
    doesn't mean there are some that I can not name individually.

    You are just using a wrong tool to define definable.


    The first number has no direction, the last number has no
    direction, no index has a direction. They are simply there or are
    not there. Actual infinity says that all are there. That is presumed. >>>>
    No, the first has a direction, the dirrection of the "next" operator.

    The operator does not belong to the number.

    No, but it creates numbers, and establishes a direction of the number
    sequence.

    Yes, a direction of the sequence but not of any number.

    Which still says you can't "start" at the end that has no end.



    First has a next but no previous, so it establishes a direction.

    The set has an order, may be called a direction, but not any number.

    Then why did YOU try to establish a "forward" direction from the
    "last" (you call it lowest) number?

    Because the sequence has an order.

    Right from 1/1 and up.

    It doesn't have a "last" to start going the other way.


    Your whole logic is based on the idea that there must be a "last"
    natural number, (to make a smallest unit fraction) but ZFC says such a
    thing does not exist.

    My logic is based on mathematics:
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) > 0
    ∀1/n ∈ ℝ: (∀x ∈ (0,1]: 1/n < x) ⇒ 1/n ≤ 0.
    ∀x ∈ (0, 1] ∃^ℵo 1/n < x

    Regards, WM


    Which no where says there is a smallest number, in fact, we can prove
    that there can't be.

    In fact, your middle line proves that there is no 1/n that is less than
    all numbers (0,1] as there is no 1/n that is <= 0. Which of course
    doesn't actually prove anything as we knew that 1/n will be > 0 for all n.


    Not sure what you are trying to say with ∃^ℵo 1/n < x but if you are
    trying to say there are always an ℵo number of unit fraction below any positive number, yes there are, which means there can not be a smallest
    unit fraction.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Mon Jan 22 22:29:18 2024
    Le 22/01/2024 à 13:52, Richard Damon a écrit :
    ℵo number of unit fraction below any
    positive number, yes there are

    Even below all of your infinitesimals?

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Mon Jan 22 22:32:24 2024
    Le 22/01/2024 à 13:54, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/22/24 3:16 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 21/01/2024 à 20:58, Jim Burns a écrit :

    Infinitely.many is more than each
    (final) number.

    Infinity is more than can be expressed by finite numbers. But all
    visible numbers are measured by the last temporarily last final or
    visible number, and therefore are far less than ω or ℵ.
    ∀n ∈ ℕ_def: |ℕ \ {1, 2, 3, ..., n}| = ℵ.

    But there is no "last" even temporarily.

    There is a last known prime number temporarily.
    Same with the last visible natnumbers.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Mon Jan 22 23:00:11 2024
    On 1/22/24 5:29 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 22/01/2024 à 13:52, Richard Damon a écrit :
    ℵo number of unit fraction below any positive number, yes there are

    Even below all of your infinitesimals?

    Regards, WM



    No, that should below any positive finite number, but then you keep on switching between excluding the transfinite and allowing them, because
    you don't know what you are talking about.

    Once we move from finite to transfinite there are no unit fractions.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Tue Jan 23 11:32:21 2024
    Le 23/01/2024 à 05:00, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/22/24 5:32 PM, WM wrote:

    ∀n ∈ ℕ_def: |ℕ \ {1, 2, 3, ..., n}| = ℵ.

    But there is no "last" even temporarily.

    There is a last known prime number temporarily.
    Same with the last visible natnumbers.

    Again with "known".

    There may be a last expressed d Natural Number, you can't even get away
    with "Known" there, as we know all of the numbers exist, even if we
    don't know yet which are prime.

    You don't know all of the numbers individually.

    Knowledge of the properties of specific numbers is different then them
    having the properites.

    So it is.

    All the Prime Numbers are Prime Nubers, we just can't name all of them
    since we don't know which ones they are out of the set of Natural Numbers.

    So it is.

    We do know which of the Natural Numbers are Natural Numbers, that is all
    of them, and thus all are visible.

    No. You know about the set, not about the individuals.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Tue Jan 23 11:29:25 2024
    Le 23/01/2024 à 05:00, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/22/24 5:29 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 22/01/2024 à 13:52, Richard Damon a écrit :
    ℵo number of unit fraction below any positive number, yes there are

    Even below all of your infinitesimals?

    No, that should below any positive finite number, but then you keep on switching between excluding the transfinite and allowing them,

    I do not switch, but you agree to the existence of ℵo unit fractions
    which cannot be found. You call them infinitesimal. That is nonsense. But
    you have recognized at least that invisible unit fractions exist.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Tue Jan 23 08:12:35 2024
    On 1/23/24 6:29 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 23/01/2024 à 05:00, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/22/24 5:29 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 22/01/2024 à 13:52, Richard Damon a écrit :
    ℵo number of unit fraction below any positive number, yes there are

    Even below all of your infinitesimals?

    No, that should below any positive finite number, but then you keep on
    switching between excluding the transfinite and allowing them,

    I do not switch, but you agree to the existence of ℵo unit fractions
    which cannot be found. You call them infinitesimal. That is nonsense.
    But you have recognized at least that invisible unit fractions exist.

    Regards, WM


    I didn't say they could not be found, you just think that is what I said
    as you don't seem to understand logical statement.


    There is nothing "nonsense" about infinitesimals, they are a fully
    developed number system. Now, your logic system and brain may not
    comprehend them, but that is YOUR problem, not theirs,

    Your definition of NUF(x) does not imply that NUF(x) needs to have any
    value other than 0 or Aleph0, and claiming that some unit fractions are "missing" where it has a finite, non-zero falue is just incorrect.


    There is no "smallest" unit fraction, but they are unboundedly small

    All Unit Fractions are "Defined" and "Visible" since that holds for all
    Natural Numbers too.

    Your logic is presuming the existance of something that doesn't exist,
    and thus has exploded in a sea of contradictions, and creates incorrect results.

    PERIOD.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Tue Jan 23 08:13:00 2024
    On 1/23/24 6:29 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 23/01/2024 à 05:00, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/22/24 5:29 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 22/01/2024 à 13:52, Richard Damon a écrit :
    ℵo number of unit fraction below any positive number, yes there are

    Even below all of your infinitesimals?

    No, that should below any positive finite number, but then you keep on
    switching between excluding the transfinite and allowing them,

    I do not switch, but you agree to the existence of ℵo unit fractions
    which cannot be found. You call them infinitesimal. That is nonsense.
    But you have recognized at least that invisible unit fractions exist.

    Regards, WM


    I didn't say they could not be found, you just think that is what I said
    as you don't seem to understand logical statement.

    Your definition of NUF(x) does not imply that NUF(x) needs to have any
    value other than 0 or Aleph0, and claiming that some unit fractions are "missing" where it has a finite, non-zero falue is just incorrect.


    There is no "smallest" unit fraction, but they are unboundedly small

    All Unit Fractions are "Defined" and "Visible" since that holds for all
    Natural Numbers too.

    Your logic is presuming the existance of something that doesn't exist,
    and thus has exploded in a sea of contradictions, and creates incorrect results.

    PERIOD.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Tue Jan 23 16:47:40 2024
    Le 23/01/2024 à 14:12, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/23/24 6:29 AM, WM wrote:

    I do not switch, but you agree to the existence of ℵo unit fractions
    which cannot be found. You call them infinitesimal. That is nonsense.
    But you have recognized at least that invisible unit fractions exist.

    I didn't say they could not be found,

    The increase from 0 to ℵ cannot be discerned. Or can you distinguish the first unit fractions? Note that never two sit at the same x.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Tue Jan 23 16:55:52 2024
    Le 23/01/2024 à 14:12, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/23/24 6:32 AM, WM wrote:


    You don't know all of the numbers individually.

    Maybe not, since it is an infinite set, but I can know any of them, and
    know of all of them.

    Not those the unit fractions of which lie between 0 and (0, 1], according
    to your impression. How would you distinguish them?

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Tue Jan 23 15:13:20 2024
    On 1/22/2024 5:29 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 22/01/2024 à 13:52, Richard Damon a écrit :

    ℵo number of unit fraction below
    any positive number, yes there are

    Even below all of your infinitesimals?

    After all final ordinals, not.final ordinals.


    ℝ ∋ x > 0
    ℕ ∋ mₓ < ⅟x ≤ mₓ⁺¹
    ⅟ℕₓ ∋ ⅟mₓ⁺¹ ≤ x

    ∀k ∈ ℕ₁:
    ∃uₖ ∈ ⅟ℕₓ:
    uₖ=⅟mₓ⁺ᵏ ∧
    ¬∃k₂ ∈ ℕ₁:
    k₂≠k ∧
    ⅟mₓ⁺ᵏ² = uₖ = ⅟mₓ⁺ᵏ

    ⅟ℕₓ ⇇ ℕ₁ 1.to.1
    ¬(|⅟ℕₓ| > |ℕ₁|)

    ∀u ∈ ⅟ℕₓ:
    ∃kᵤ ∈ ℕ₁:
    kᵤ = (⅟u)-mₓ ∧
    ¬∃u₂ ∈ ⅟ℕₓ:
    u₂≠u ∧
    (⅟u₂)-mₓ = kᵤ = (⅟u)-mₓ

    ⅟ℕₓ ⇉ ℕ₁ 1.to.1
    ¬(|⅟ℕₓ| < |ℕ₁|)

    ¬(|⅟ℕₓ| > |ℕ₁|)
    ¬(|⅟ℕₓ| < |ℕ₁|)
    |⅟ℕₓ| = |ℕ₁|

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Tue Jan 23 22:27:44 2024
    Le 23/01/2024 à 19:07, FromTheRafters a écrit :
    WM wrote on 1/23/2024 :
    Le 23/01/2024 à 14:12, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/23/24 6:32 AM, WM wrote:


    You don't know all of the numbers individually.

    Maybe not, since it is an infinite set, but I can know any of them, and
    know of all of them.

    Not those the unit fractions of which lie between 0 and (0, 1], according to >> your impression. How would you distinguish them?

    There aren't any unit fractions between zero and the interval
    mentioned.

    Of course not. But then there are not ℵo unit fractions smaller than
    every x > 0.

    Assume the contrary
    1. ∀ x ∈ (0, 1]: ∃^oo y ∈ {1/n : n e IN}: y < x
    and
    2. ∀ y ∈ {1/n : n e IN}: 0 < y .
    Then
    3. ∀ x ∈ (0, 1]: ∃^oo y ∈ {1/n : n e IN}: 0 < y < x
    would follow. But that is wrong because
    3'. ∀ x ∈ [0, 1]: ∃^oo y ∈ {1/n : n e IN}: 0 < y < x
    is obviously wrong, but [0, 1] has only one point more than (0, 1].

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Tue Jan 23 22:30:57 2024
    Le 23/01/2024 à 21:13, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 1/22/2024 5:29 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 22/01/2024 à 13:52, Richard Damon a écrit :

    ℵo number of unit fraction below
    any positive number, yes there are

    Even below all of your infinitesimals?

    After all final ordinals, not.final ordinals.


    ℝ ∋ x > 0
    ℕ ∋ mₓ < ⅟x ≤ mₓ⁺¹
    ⅟ℕₓ ∋ ⅟mₓ⁺¹ ≤ x

    ∀k ∈ ℕ₁:
    ∃uₖ ∈ ⅟ℕₓ:
    uₖ=⅟mₓ⁺ᵏ ∧
    ¬∃k₂ ∈ ℕ₁:
    k₂≠k ∧
    ⅟mₓ⁺ᵏ² = uₖ = ⅟mₓ⁺ᵏ

    ⅟ℕₓ ⇇ ℕ₁ 1.to.1
    ¬(|⅟ℕₓ| > |ℕ₁|)

    ∀u ∈ ⅟ℕₓ:
    ∃kᵤ ∈ ℕ₁:
    kᵤ = (⅟u)-mₓ ∧
    ¬∃u₂ ∈ ⅟ℕₓ:
    u₂≠u ∧
    (⅟u₂)-mₓ = kᵤ = (⅟u)-mₓ

    ⅟ℕₓ ⇉ ℕ₁ 1.to.1
    ¬(|⅟ℕₓ| < |ℕ₁|)

    ¬(|⅟ℕₓ| > |ℕ₁|)
    ¬(|⅟ℕₓ| < |ℕ₁|)
    |⅟ℕₓ| = |ℕ₁|

    Contradiction

    There are not ℵo unit fractions smaller than every x > 0.

    Assume the contrary
    1. ∀ x ∈ (0, 1]: ∃^oo y ∈ {1/n : n e IN}: y < x
    and
    2. ∀ y ∈ {1/n : n e IN}: 0 < y .
    Then
    3. ∀ x ∈ (0, 1]: ∃^oo y ∈ {1/n : n e IN}: 0 < y < x
    would follow. But that is wrong because
    3'. ∀ x ∈ [0, 1]: ∃^oo y ∈ {1/n : n e IN}: 0 < y < x
    is obviously wrong, but [0, 1] has only one point more than (0, 1].

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Tue Jan 23 22:02:16 2024
    On 1/23/24 11:55 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 23/01/2024 à 14:12, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/23/24 6:32 AM, WM wrote:


    You don't know all of the numbers individually.

    Maybe not, since it is an infinite set, but I can know any of them,
    and know of all of them.

    Not those the unit fractions of which lie between 0 and (0, 1],
    according to your impression. How would you distinguish them?

    Regards, WM

    There are NO unit fractions between 0 and (0,1], how could there be. (0,
    1] includes ALL finite numbers x where 0 < x <= 1

    So, why do I need to distinguish numbers that just don't exist?


    Let me riddle you a few questions,

    Do you accept the principle of Induction?

    If so, do you accept that 0 is definable/visible?

    (if not, why not)

    Do you accept that if the number n is definable/visible, then so will be
    n+1?

    (if not, what number doesn't this hold for. since this is for a n that
    IS definable/visible, you should be able to name it)

    If you accept these, then you have to accept that ALL Natural Numbers
    are definable/visible by the necessary consequence of these properties.

    And thus also the Unit Fractions.

    If you don't accept the principle of Induction, you can't be using ZFC,
    as the principle of Induction is provable from the axioms of ZFC, and if
    you don't have ZFC, how are you getting your Natural Numbers?

    Also, if you don't hav ZFC, of course you can't complain that ZFC
    doesn't answer some of your questions, as you are assuming ZFC isn't in
    your logic system.

    This puts a bit of a damper on your arguements.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Wed Jan 24 15:57:03 2024
    Le 24/01/2024 à 04:02, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/23/24 5:27 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 23/01/2024 à 19:07, FromTheRafters a écrit :
    WM wrote on 1/23/2024 :
    Le 23/01/2024 à 14:12, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/23/24 6:32 AM, WM wrote:


    You don't know all of the numbers individually.

    Maybe not, since it is an infinite set, but I can know any of them,
    and know of all of them.

    Not those the unit fractions of which lie between 0 and (0, 1],
    according to your impression. How would you distinguish them?

    There aren't any unit fractions between zero and the interval mentioned.

    Of course not. But then there are not ℵo unit fractions smaller than
    every x > 0.

    Assume the contrary
    1. ∀ x ∈ (0, 1]: ∃^oo y ∈ {1/n : n e IN}: y < x
    and
    2. ∀ y ∈ {1/n : n e IN}: 0 < y .
    Then
    3. ∀ x ∈ (0, 1]: ∃^oo y ∈ {1/n : n e IN}: 0 < y < x would follow. But
    that is wrong because
    3'. ∀ x ∈ [0, 1]: ∃^oo y ∈ {1/n : n e IN}: 0 < y < x
    is obviously wrong, but [0, 1] has only one point more than (0, 1].

    Nope.

    You can't talk about "1" point out of an infinite number.

    Of course I can unless they are dark. But 0 is not dark.

    Both sets (0, 1] and [0, 1] have the same number of points, aleph0

    Yes, infinitely many.

    Yes, the "difference" of the sets is just one point, but that doesn't
    mean there can't be an infinite number of points less that every number
    in (0, 1].

    But it means that one point cannot exorcize an infinity of points which
    fit into (0, 1] when 0 is added.

    You are just using incorrect logic. It may SEEM logical to you, but it
    fails.

    It is logic of mathematics. What fails is ZF.

    Try to actually PROVE that statement with logic that works for unbounded sets.

    There is only one correct logic. It is applied above and works for
    unbounded sets. ZF does not work for unbounded sets.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Wed Jan 24 16:01:56 2024
    Le 24/01/2024 à 04:02, Richard Damon a écrit :

    Of course you can't distinguish the first unit fraction form zero, as
    there isn't a "first" unit fraction from zero!

    NUF(0) = 0 and NUF(1) = greater. Hence there is a point where the first
    unit fraction must sit or where more than one must sit. That kind of logic cannot be defeated by the fools of matheology.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Chris M. Thomasson on Wed Jan 24 14:39:14 2024
    On 1/23/2024 10:22 PM, Chris M. Thomasson wrote:
    On 1/23/2024 7:02 PM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 1/23/24 11:55 AM, WM wrote:

    Not those the unit fractions of which
    lie between 0 and (0, 1],
    according to your impression.
    How would you distinguish them?

    There are NO unit fractions between 0 and (0,1],
    how could there be.
    (0, 1] includes ALL
    finite numbers x where 0 < x <= 1
    So, why do I need to distinguish numbers that
    just don't exist?

    I must be misunderstanding you? :
    0---->1/2---->1
    1/2-->3/4---->1
    ?

    It's a nonsense claim, so
    "That can't be what is meant"
    would be an understandable take.

    d is between 0 and (0,1] means
    for each x e (0,1]: 0 < d < x

    d not.exists
    Ax e (0,1]: 0 < d < x
    ~Ex e (0,1]: 0 < x =< d
    Nonsense.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Chris M. Thomasson on Wed Jan 24 14:56:22 2024
    On 1/24/2024 2:35 PM, Chris M. Thomasson wrote:
    On 1/24/2024 2:08 AM, FromTheRafters wrote:

    Why does WM seem to think
    there is a smallest unit fraction next to zero?
    In my example:
    0---->1/2----->1
    Well, what about:
    0---->1/4----->1/2

    WM seems to think that
    there is a smallest unit fraction right after zero.
    I am wondering why...
    Perhaps, he is a moron?

    Perhaps he is the the grip of a mania.

    Perhaps, one day, long, long ago,
    before he had learned how quantifiers work,
    he spotted what he thought was a mistake
    on the part of Big Mathematics (imaginary),
    and,
    ever since then,
    he has devoted his life to proving
    his obvious genius (imaginary).

    I have come to the opinion that
    the most important skill taught in math classes,
    the most difficult to learn,
    the rarest outside of Big Mathematics,
    is to say
    "Oops. I was wrong."

    WM seems to have been out sick
    on the day, long, long ago, they taught that.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Dieter Heidorn@21:1/5 to Chris M. Thomasson on Wed Jan 24 21:16:32 2024
    Chris M. Thomasson schrieb:
    On 1/24/2024 2:08 AM, FromTheRafters wrote:
    It happens that Chris M. Thomasson formulated :
    On 1/23/2024 7:02 PM, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 1/23/24 11:55 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 23/01/2024 à 14:12, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/23/24 6:32 AM, WM wrote:


    You don't know all of the numbers individually.

    Maybe not, since it is an infinite set, but I can know any of
    them, and know of all of them.

    Not those the unit fractions of which lie between 0 and (0, 1],
    according to your impression. How would you distinguish them?

    Regards, WM

    There are NO unit fractions between 0 and (0,1], how could there be.
    (0, 1] includes ALL finite numbers x where 0 < x <= 1

    So, why do I need to distinguish numbers that just don't exist?

    I must be misunderstanding you? :

    0---->1/2---->1

    1/2-->3/4---->1

    ?

      ---->1/2---->1

    Zero is *NOT* in the interval.

    Why does WM seem to think there is a smallest unit fraction next to
    zero?

    His "argument" is:

    1. the distance of two points on the real axis, representing two
    successive unit fractions

    d_n := 1/n - 1/(n+1) = 1/(n*(n+1))

    is always greater zero:

    ∀ n∈ℕ : d_n > 0

    2. starting at zero the unit fractions are "linear ordered".

    So WM's conclusion is: there must be a "first unit fraction".

    WM seems to think that there is a smallest unit fraction right after
    zero. I am wondering why... Perhaps, he is a moron?

    That's right. He even can't understand, that for every natural number n
    there is a successor n + 1, so for every unit fraction there is a
    successor 1/(n+1).

    His problem is: He can't deal with infinite sets. So he always
    introduces a "cut" - i.e. he divides the infinite set in two parts:
    a finite one and a "dark part", consisting of "not nameable (or distinguishable) numbers".
    For the set of unit fractions he uses as described the introduction of a
    "first unit fraction" after zero to divide the infinite set of unit
    fractions in the "dark part" and the finite part, which starts with the
    "first unit fraction".

    Shortly spoken: He talks nothing but rubbish.

    Dieter Heidorn

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Wed Jan 24 15:33:47 2024
    On 1/23/2024 5:30 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 23/01/2024 à 21:13, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 1/22/2024 5:29 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 22/01/2024 à 13:52, Richard Damon a écrit :

    ℵo number of unit fraction below
    any positive number, yes there are

    Even below all of your infinitesimals?

    After all final ordinals, not.final ordinals.


    ℝ ∋ x > 0
    ℕ ∋ mₓ < ⅟x ≤ mₓ⁺¹
    ⅟ℕₓ ∋ ⅟mₓ⁺¹ ≤ x

    ∀k ∈ ℕ₁:
    ∃uₖ ∈ ⅟ℕₓ:
      uₖ=⅟mₓ⁺ᵏ  ∧
    ¬∃k₂ ∈ ℕ₁:
       k₂≠k ∧
       ⅟mₓ⁺ᵏ² = uₖ = ⅟mₓ⁺ᵏ

    ⅟ℕₓ ⇇ ℕ₁ 1.to.1
    ¬(|⅟ℕₓ| > |ℕ₁|)

    ∀u ∈ ⅟ℕₓ:
    ∃kᵤ ∈ ℕ₁:
      kᵤ = (⅟u)-mₓ  ∧
    ¬∃u₂ ∈ ⅟ℕₓ:
       u₂≠u ∧
       (⅟u₂)-mₓ = kᵤ = (⅟u)-mₓ

    ⅟ℕₓ ⇉ ℕ₁ 1.to.1
    ¬(|⅟ℕₓ| < |ℕ₁|)

    ¬(|⅟ℕₓ| > |ℕ₁|)
    ¬(|⅟ℕₓ| < |ℕ₁|)
    |⅟ℕₓ| = |ℕ₁|

    Contradiction

    There are not
    ℵo unit fractions smaller than every x > 0.

    Assume the contrary
    1. ∀ x ∈ (0, 1]:
    ∃^oo y ∈ {1/n : n e IN}:
    y < x

    For each positive point x
    infinitely.many unit.fractions are between 0 and x
    Yes.
    ∀x ∈ (0,1]: |⅟ℕₓ| = |ℕ₁|

    and
    2. ∀ y ∈ {1/n : n e IN}:
    0 < y .

    Yes.

    Then
    3. ∀ x ∈ (0, 1]:
    ∃^oo y ∈ {1/n : n e IN}:
    0 < y < x
    would follow.

    Yes. It follows.

    But that is wrong because
    3'. ∀ x ∈ [0, 1]:
    ∃^oo y ∈ {1/n : n e IN}:
    0 < y < x
    is obviously wrong,

    (3') is the conjunction of (3) and (3₀)
    | 3₀
    | ∃^oo y ∈ {1/n : n e IN}:
    | 0 < y < 0

    (3₀) is obviously false,
    which makes their conjunction false,
    whether the other conjunct is true or false.

    How would that work,
    for false (3)∧(3₀) to make (3) false?
    Suppose, instead, that (3) is (1+1=2)
    Would false (1+1=2)∧(3₀)
    also make (1+1=2) false?

    but [0, 1] has only one point more than (0, 1].

    Why does (3₀) false make (3) false?

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Wed Jan 24 22:10:23 2024
    Le 24/01/2024 à 20:56, Jim Burns a écrit :

    I have come to the opinion that
    the most important skill taught in math classes,
    the most difficult to learn,
    the rarest outside of Big Mathematics,
    is to say
    "Oops. I was wrong."

    Why don't you apply your skill?

    When NUF(0) = 0 and NUF(1) > 0, then there must be a first point where NUF grows.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Wed Jan 24 16:42:11 2024
    On 1/24/2024 3:17 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On Wednesday, January 24, 2024
    at 11:56:30 AM UTC-8, Jim Burns wrote:

    If you can't split a line into points,
    and can't draw points into a line,

    Can't I?
    Okay, then I won't do that.

    Instead,
    I will learn about lines and points by
    describing what we mean by "lines and points"
    and then
    augmenting our description with
    claims not.first.false about lines and points.

    Some claims we can _see_ are not.first.false
    For example, claim Q is not.first.false in
    ⟨ Q∨¬P P Q ⟩
       1   1 1
       1   0 1
       0   1 0
       1   0 0

    Some claim.sequences are only not.first.false.

    A finite only.first.false claim.sequence
    is only true.

    Whatever I can or can't do with lines and points,
    I can make claims and see they're not.first.false.

    If you can't split a line into points,
    and can't draw points into a line,
    what makes you think that
    axiomatizing the gaplessness of
    the complete ordered field
    is a good idea?

    It is a useful idea.
    When I look at how much it's used,
    I feel pretty confident of that judgment.

    Or is it just wishful thinking,
    of the contradictory sort?

    If there exists anything satisfying our description,
    then it is not of the contradictory sort. (theorem)

    That is what constructions are for.
    A construction doesn't build mathematical objects
    like we build skyscrapers.
    It proves something exists satisfying a description.

    Suppose that we have already agreed somehow that
    the power set 𝒫(ℚ) of the rationals
    is not of the contradictory sort.

    The restriction of 𝒫(ℚ) to edgeless.foresplits of ℚ
    is something which satisfies our description of ℝ
    (theorem)

    In particular, the union of a bounded non.empty set
    of edgeless.foresplits is an edgeless.foresplit, and
    is a bound of that set, and is less than any other bound.
    Edgeless.foresplits have the Least Upper Bound Property.

    Thus, accepting the existence of the set of
    edgeless foresplits makes necessary accepting
    the non.contradictory nature of the complete line,
    _even if_ edgelss foresplits are nothing like
    what we thought we were talking about.

    The Least Upper Bound property of
    the standard complete ordered field,
    is a non-logical/proper axiom.

    The Three Corner Property of a right triangle
    is a non.logical/proper axiom,
    one which we'll probably need to assert
    if we plan to reason about right triangles.

    I might be misunderstanding.
    Are you objecting to the assertion
    "This is what we are talking about"?
    If you are, what is your objection?

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Wed Jan 24 22:14:06 2024
    Le 24/01/2024 à 21:16, Dieter Heidorn a écrit :

    1. the distance of two points on the real axis, representing two
    successive unit fractions

    d_n := 1/n - 1/(n+1) = 1/(n*(n+1))

    is always greater zero:

    ∀ n∈ℕ : d_n > 0

    What is wrong about that?

    2. starting at zero the unit fractions are "linear ordered".

    Aren't they?

    So WM's conclusion is: there must be a "first unit fraction".

    Or many. Anyhow, in no case the inset can be discerned.

    That's right. He even can't understand, that for every natural number n
    there is a successor n + 1, so for every unit fraction there is a
    successor 1/(n+1).

    When NUF(0) = 0 and NUF(1) > 0, then there must be a first point where NUF grows. How else can the increase be explained?

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Wed Jan 24 22:17:49 2024
    Le 24/01/2024 à 21:33, Jim Burns a écrit :

    For each positive point x
    infinitely.many unit.fractions are between 0 and x
    Yes.

    That means by choosing a positive point you cannot distinguish almost all
    unit fractions. By what means can you distinguish them?

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Wed Jan 24 20:04:32 2024
    On 1/24/24 11:01 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 24/01/2024 à 04:02, Richard Damon a écrit :

    Of course you can't distinguish the first unit fraction form zero, as
    there isn't a "first" unit fraction from zero!

    NUF(0) = 0 and NUF(1) = greater. Hence there is a point where the first
    unit fraction must sit or where more than one must sit. That kind of
    logic cannot be defeated by the fools of matheology.

    Regards, WM


    Nope.

    You can't actually prove that NUF(x) can't change by more than one
    between 0 and the finite positive numbers.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Wed Jan 24 22:35:13 2024
    On 1/24/24 9:42 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On Wednesday, January 24, 2024 at 5:04:52 PM UTC-8, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 1/24/24 5:10 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 24/01/2024 à 20:56, Jim Burns a écrit :

    I have come to the opinion that
    the most important skill taught in math classes,
    the most difficult to learn,
    the rarest outside of Big Mathematics,
    is to say
    "Oops. I was wrong."

    Why don't you apply your skill?

    When NUF(0) = 0 and NUF(1) > 0, then there must be a first point where
    NUF grows.

    Regards, WM


    Why?

    Your logic system doesn't seem to know how to handle unbounded sets.

    Please DEFINE your actual logic system.

    You mean the universe of logical objects, like a Comenius language?

    Well what you do is start with the canon of the technical philosophy about reason,
    after you have a nice intuitive objective view impersonally personally,
    then you go over it again, until there are no logical paradoxes left,
    and make room for a theory, of truth, in theory, theory.

    Then that's considered with other perfection and the sublime,
    and simple models like model theory and proof theory,
    and sequents and tableau, derivation rules and strokes,
    are pretty much constructive.

    "Axiomless natural deduction arriving at logic and mathematics, ...",
    science and the probabilistic part of our phenomenological perception, including an object-sense for a number-sense, word-sense, and time-sense.

    It's called rationality via reason and vice versa.




    But ZFC, which is what he is talking about, is a formal logic system
    built on axioms and the like.

    Your Axiomless system sounds like pure philosophy, and not really
    topical for "sci.math".

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Thu Jan 25 10:39:34 2024
    Le 25/01/2024 à 02:04, Richard Damon a écrit :

    You can't actually prove that NUF(x) can't change by more than one
    between 0 and the finite positive numbers.

    Simply apply mathematics:
    1) NUF increases from 0 to more.
    2) ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) > 0
    Done.

    Rematk: And if NUF would change by more than one unit fraction between 0
    and (0, 1], then you could not distinguish these unit fractions.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Thu Jan 25 10:42:38 2024
    Le 25/01/2024 à 02:04, Richard Damon a écrit :

    Have you listed your axioms and logical inference rules anywhere?

    I need only one logical axiom besides mathematics.

    If NUF is 0 at one point and larger at another one, then it must have
    increased between these points.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Fritz Feldhase on Thu Jan 25 11:09:34 2024
    Fritz Feldhase schrieb am Donnerstag, 25. Januar 2024 um 01:11:08 UTC+1:
    On Wednesday, January 24, 2024 at 11:14:15 PM UTC+1, WM wrote:

    So WM's conclusion is: there must be a "first unit fraction".

    Or many.
    Thanks for the correction.
    That's right. He even can't understand, that for every natural number n there is a successor n + 1, so for [any] unit fraction [say, 1/n] there is a

    ["]successor["] 1/(n + 1) [which is smaller than 1/n].

    Was sagst Du d a z u, Mückenheim, ist es nicht s o?

    It is true for the potentially infinite collection of definable numbers.
    It is not true for the whole actually infinite set because dark numbers
    are not discernible.
    But they are numbers too. Therefore they obey ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1)
    0 . Therefore there is a first one after 0.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Thu Jan 25 07:22:34 2024
    On 1/25/24 5:39 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 25/01/2024 à 02:04, Richard Damon a écrit :

    You can't actually prove that NUF(x) can't change by more than one
    between 0 and the finite positive numbers.

    Simply apply mathematics:
    1) NUF increases from 0 to more.
    2) ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) > 0 Done.

    Rematk: And if NUF would change by more than one unit fraction between 0
    and (0, 1], then you could not distinguish these unit fractions.

    Regards, WM

    Except NUF isn't defined by "increase" it is defined by counting
    something that is unbounded.

    Thus when you "cross" the "bound" of the unbounded, it can jump.

    That is basic mathematics of unbounded sets.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Thu Jan 25 12:36:02 2024
    Le 25/01/2024 à 13:22, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/25/24 5:42 AM, WM wrote:

    I need only one logical axiom besides mathematics.

    If NUF is 0 at one point and larger at another one, then it must have
    increased between these points.

    So, you don't understand how logic works.

    My logic works fine.

    There are many mathematics, based on the axioms you choose for them.

    There is one mathematics and many nonsense matheologies.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Thu Jan 25 12:40:44 2024
    Le 25/01/2024 à 13:22, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/25/24 5:39 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 25/01/2024 à 02:04, Richard Damon a écrit :

    You can't actually prove that NUF(x) can't change by more than one
    between 0 and the finite positive numbers.

    Simply apply mathematics:
    1) NUF increases from 0 to more.
    2) ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) > 0 Done.

    Remark: And if NUF would change by more than one unit fraction between 0
    and (0, 1], then you could not distinguish these unit fractions.

    Except NUF isn't defined by "increase" it is defined by counting
    something that is unbounded.

    It is defined by counting single points 1/n.

    Thus when you "cross" the "bound" of the unbounded, it can jump.

    Even if so you could not discern the unit fractions within this jump.

    That is basic mathematics of unbounded sets.

    That turns out to be inconsistent, in contradiction with solid
    mathematics.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Thu Jan 25 09:57:55 2024
    On 1/24/2024 5:17 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 24/01/2024 à 21:33, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 1/22/2024 5:29 PM, WM wrote:

    Assume the contrary
    1. ∀ x ∈ (0, 1]:
    ∃^oo y ∈ {1/n : n e IN}:
    y < x

    For each positive point x
    infinitely.many unit.fractions are between 0 and x
    Yes.
    ∀x ∈ (0,1]: |⅟ℕₓ| = |ℕ₁|

    That means
    by choosing a positive point
    you cannot distinguish almost all unit fractions.
    By what means can you distinguish them?

    You:
    Then
    3. ∀ x ∈ (0, 1]:
    ∃^oo y ∈ {1/n : n e IN}:
    0 < y < x
    would follow.
    But that is wrong because
    3'. ∀ x ∈ [0, 1]:
    ∃^oo y ∈ {1/n : n e IN}:
    0 < y < x
    is obviously wrong,

    (3′)
    | ∀x ∈ [0, 1]:
    | ∃^oo y ∈ {1/n : n e IN}:
    | 0 < y < x
    |
    is equivalent to
    (3)
    | ∀x ∈ (0, 1]:
    | ∃^oo y ∈ {1/n : n e IN}:
    | 0 < y < x
    |
    and
    (3₀)
    | ∃^oo y ∈ {1/n : n e IN}:
    | 0 < y < 0

    (3₀) is false.
    (3₀)∧(3) is false.

    From where do you (WM) get that
    (3) is false?

    (3₀) (3) (3₀)∧(3)
     1    1      1  0    1      0  *  1    0      0  0    0      0  *

    (3₀) (3) (3₀)∧(3)
     0    1      0  *  0    0      0  *

    ----
    For each positive point x
    infinitely.many unit.fractions are between 0 and x
    Yes.

    That means
    by choosing a positive point
    you cannot distinguish almost all unit fractions.
    By what means can you distinguish them?

    My claims are for
    points which are chosen and
    points which are not chosen and
    points which are distinguished and
    points which are not distinguished.
    My claims are for
    points which exist.

    Describe
    a point which exists.
    Augment the description with
    claims not.first.false.about
    a point which exists.

    We know that a finite claim.sequence of
    claims not.first.false.about
    a point which exists
    is a finite claim.sequence of
    claims not.false.about
    a point which exists.

    That knowledge is based on
    what we know about finite claim.sequences. and
    what we see are not.first.false claims.

    ----
    Assume the contrary
    1. ∀ x ∈ (0, 1]:
    ∃^oo y ∈ {1/n : n e IN}:
    y < x

    For each positive point x
    infinitely.many unit.fractions are between 0 and x
    Yes.
    ∀x ∈ (0,1]: |⅟ℕₓ| = |ℕ₁|

    for each final k (1 more can't fit)
    for each positive point x
    at least k+1 unit fractions are between 0 and x
    ∀k ∈ ℕᶠⁱⁿᵃˡ:
    ¬(⟨⅟mₓ⁺ᵏ,…,⅟mₓ⁺¹⟩ ⇇ ⟨⅟mₓ⁺ᵏ⁺¹,⅟mₓ⁺ᵏ,…,⅟mₓ⁺¹⟩)
    ⟨⅟mₓ⁺ᵏ⁺¹,⅟mₓ⁺ᵏ,…,⅟mₓ⁺¹⟩ ⊆ ⅟ℕ∩(0,x]

    for each final k (1 more can't fit)
    for each positive point x
    card of unit.fractions between 0 and k
    isn't k (1 more can't fit)
    ∀k ∈ ℕᶠⁱⁿᵃˡ:
    ¬(⟨⅟mₓ⁺ᵏ,…,⅟mₓ⁺¹⟩ ⇇ ⅟ℕ∩(0,x])

    for each positive point x
    card of unit.fractions between 0 and k
    isn't final (1 more can fit)
    |⅟ℕ∩(0,x]| ∉ ℕᶠⁱⁿᵃˡ
    ⅟ℕ∩(0,x] ⇇ (⅟ℕ∩(0,x])∪{ℼ}


    After final.ordinals are not.final.ordinals.
    ∀x ∈ (0,1]: NUF(x) = ℵ₀

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Thu Jan 25 14:08:22 2024
    On 1/24/2024 5:10 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 24/01/2024 à 20:56, Jim Burns a écrit :

    I have come to the opinion that
    the most important skill taught in math classes,
    the most difficult to learn,
    the rarest outside of Big Mathematics,
    is to say
    "Oops. I was wrong."

    Why don't you apply your skill?

    When NUF(0) = 0 and NUF(1) > 0,
    then there must be a first point where
    NUF grows.

    For each ⅟k ∈ ⅟ℕ∩(0,x]
    exists ⅟k/2 ∈ ⅟ℕ∩(0,x/2] and
    not.exists ⅟k₂ ∈ ⅟ℕ∩(0,x]: ⅟k₂≠⅟k ∧ ⅟k₂/2=⅟k/2

    ⅟ℕ∩(0,x/2] ⇇ ⅟ℕ∩(0,x] 1.to.1

    |⅟ℕ∩(0,x/2]| ≥ |⅟ℕ∩(0,x]|

    NUF does not grow anywhere in (0,1]

    After all final.ordinals (one.more not.fits) are
    only not.final.ordinals (one.more fits).

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Thu Jan 25 13:37:34 2024
    On 1/24/2024 7:52 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On Wednesday, January 24, 2024
    at 1:42:17 PM UTC-8, Jim Burns wrote:

    [...]

    Dedekind cuts your edgeless.foresplits, have here
    that there are Aristotle cuts without
    needing the bit of legerdemain, there,
    and furthermore
    real numbers of the complete ordered field in
    standard real analysis are
    equivalence classes of sequences with
    the property that they are Cauchy.

    In order to prove that the usual formulation
    under which skipping functions must be discontinuous
    is not of the contradictory variety,
    it is sufficient to prove that
    something, anything of that description exists.

    Equivalence classes of the Cauchy sequences of rationals
    serve that purpose.

    Also, the edgeless.foresplits of rationals
    serve that purpose.
    There are other constructions which
    serve that purpose, too.

    If you don't grant the power set of the rationals
    or specification of its edgeless.foresplit subset,
    then there are other issues we should address first.

    If you grant them, then we are done.
    The edgeless.foresplit subset of 𝒫(ℚ) is ℝ,
    for the purpose of proving the usual formulation of ℝ
    is not of the contradictory kind.
    Even if there are other ways to prove the same thing.

    I.e. Dedekind cuts are only defined by
    a real numbers' continuous domain already.

    For edgeless.foresplits of ℝ, true.
    For edgeless.foresplits of ℚ, no.

    Define ELFSꟴ(F) :⇔
    ℚ ⊇ F ≠ {}
    ℚ ⊇ H := ℚ\F ≠ {}
    ∀y ∈ F, ∀z ∈ H: y < z
    ¬∃x ∈ F: ∀y ∈ F: y ≤ x

    ℝᵉˡᶠˢ := {F ⊆ ℚ| ELFSꟴ(F)} ⊆ 𝒫(ℚ)
    ℝᵉˡᶠˢ is _the_ complete ordered field.
    Other objects are _the_ complete ordered field, too.
    The use of "the" indicates uniqueness,
    but only uniqueness up to isometry.

    Furthermore thanks to trichotomy,
    partitions, of a copy of the real numbers
    to two partitions,
    are only as many as the set itself,
    not its powerset.

    (I think you want s/partitions/splits/)

    There are more splits of Q than elements of Q.
    Consider F = {p ∈ ℚ| p < 0 ∨ p² < 2 }

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Thu Jan 25 18:48:55 2024
    On 1/25/24 7:40 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 25/01/2024 à 13:22, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/25/24 5:39 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 25/01/2024 à 02:04, Richard Damon a écrit :

    You can't actually prove that NUF(x) can't change by more than one
    between 0 and the finite positive numbers.

    Simply apply mathematics:
    1) NUF increases from 0 to more.
    2) ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) > 0 Done.

    Remark: And if NUF would change by more than one unit fraction
    between 0 and (0, 1], then you could not distinguish these unit
    fractions.

    Except NUF isn't defined by "increase" it is defined by counting
    something that is unbounded.

    It is defined by counting single points 1/n.

    Except you need to start somewhere, and there is no smallest 1/n to
    start with.


    Thus when you "cross" the "bound" of the unbounded, it can jump.

    Even if so you could not discern the unit fractions within this jump.

    There doesn't need to be, that is the effect of "unbounded"


    That is basic mathematics of unbounded sets.

    That turns out to be inconsistent, in contradiction with solid mathematics.

    Nope, IGNORING it is inconsistent.


    Regards, WM



    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Thu Jan 25 18:33:43 2024
    On 1/25/2024 4:03 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On Thursday, January 25, 2024
    at 10:37:41 AM UTC-8, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 1/24/2024 7:52 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:

    Dedekind cuts your edgeless.foresplits, have here
    that there are Aristotle cuts without
    needing the bit of legerdemain, there,
    and furthermore
    real numbers of the complete ordered field in
    standard real analysis are
    equivalence classes of sequences with
    the property that they are Cauchy.

    In order to prove that the usual formulation
    under which skipping functions must be discontinuous
    is not of the contradictory variety,
    it is sufficient to prove that
    something, anything of that description exists.

    Equivalence classes of the Cauchy sequences of rationals
    serve that purpose.

    Also, the edgeless.foresplits of rationals
    serve that purpose.
    There are other constructions which
    serve that purpose, too.

    If you don't grant the power set of the rationals
    or specification of its edgeless.foresplit subset,
    then there are other issues we should address first.

    If you grant them, then we are done.
    The edgeless.foresplit subset of 𝒫(ℚ) is ℝ,
    for the purpose of proving the usual formulation of ℝ
    is not of the contradictory kind.
    Even if there are other ways to prove the same thing.

    I.e. Dedekind cuts are only defined by
    a real numbers' continuous domain already.

    For edgeless.foresplits of ℝ, true.
    For edgeless.foresplits of ℚ, no.

    Define ELFSꟴ(F) :⇔
    ℚ ⊇ F ≠ {}
    ℚ ⊇ H := ℚ\F ≠ {}
    ∀y ∈ F, ∀z ∈ H: y < z
    ¬∃x ∈ F: ∀y ∈ F: y ≤ x

    ℝᵉˡᶠˢ := {F ⊆ ℚ| ELFSꟴ(F)} ⊆ 𝒫(ℚ)
    ℝᵉˡᶠˢ is _the_ complete ordered field.
    Other objects are _the_ complete ordered field, too.
    The use of "the" indicates uniqueness,
    but only uniqueness up to isometry.

    Furthermore thanks to trichotomy,
    partitions, of a copy of the real numbers
    to two partitions,
    are only as many as the set itself,
    not its powerset.

    (I think you want s/partitions/splits/)

    There are more splits of Q than elements of Q.
    Consider F = {p ∈ ℚ| p < 0 ∨ p² < 2 }

    I think you mean "I wish it wasn't", but,
    if pigs had wings they'd still bump their ass.

    Excuse me that's crass but mostly the point
    is that no, Dedekind cuts are not sufficient.

    Dedekind cuts of the finite.over.finite rationals
    are sufficient as a model of
    the points.between.splits reals.

    There is a proof of that.

    The proof includes:

    Edgeless.ℚ.foresplits are trichotomous (⊆)

    Edgeless.ℚ.foresplits are transitive (⊆)

    The union ⋃S of
    bounded non.empty set S of edgeless.ℚ.foresplits
    is an edgeless.ℚ.foresplit

    ⋃S is greater.than.or.equal.to (⊆) each set in S

    ⋃S is less.than.or.equal.to (⊆) each set (each bound) which
    is greater.than.or.equal.to (⊆) each set in S

    ⋃S the least upper bound of S exists.

    Included, too:

    Definitions of + - * / for edgeless.ℚ.foresplits
    which agree with corresponding rationals.
    And we already have the definition of ≤ as ⊆

    The reals in the complete ordered field have
    the usual + - * / < and least upper bounds.

    The edgeless.ℚ.foresplits have
    the usual + - * / < and least upper bounds.

    That's sufficient. Game over.

    Now, "the rationals are HUGE", is a thing.

    The rationals have HUGE numerators and
    denominators. HUGE doesn't reach INFINITY.

    0<0+1 1<1+1 2<2+1 ... HUGE<HUGE+1 ...
    However,
    INFINITY=INFINITY+1

    I think you mean "I wish it wasn't", but,
    if pigs had wings they'd still bump their ass.

    Which part of my post do you refer to here?

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Fri Jan 26 09:51:58 2024
    Le 25/01/2024 à 15:57, Jim Burns a écrit :

    ∀x ∈ (0,1]: NUF(x) = ℵ₀

    ℵ₀ unit fractions having a certain extension, do not fit between 0 and every x > 0.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Fri Jan 26 10:00:26 2024
    Le 26/01/2024 à 00:48, Richard Damon a écrit :

    Except you need to start somewhere, and there is no smallest 1/n to
    start with.

    If there is no start, then there are no unit fractions.


    Thus when you "cross" the "bound" of the unbounded, it can jump.

    Even if so you could not discern the unit fractions within this jump.

    There doesn't need to be, that is the effect of "unbounded"

    There is no need. However it is fact: Numbers that cannot be
    distinguished.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Fri Jan 26 09:56:16 2024
    Le 25/01/2024 à 20:08, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 1/24/2024 5:10 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 24/01/2024 à 20:56, Jim Burns a écrit :

    I have come to the opinion that
    the most important skill taught in math classes,
    the most difficult to learn,
    the rarest outside of Big Mathematics,
    is to say
    "Oops. I was wrong."

    Why don't you apply your skill?

    When NUF(0) = 0 and NUF(1) > 0,
    then there must be a first point where
    NUF grows.

    NUF does not grow anywhere in (0,1]

    But since all unit fractions lie in this interval, NUF cannot grow
    elsewhere.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Fri Jan 26 07:32:12 2024
    On 1/26/24 5:00 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 26/01/2024 à 00:48, Richard Damon a écrit :

    Except you need to start somewhere, and there is no smallest 1/n to
    start with.

    If there is no start, then there are no unit fractions.

    But they do start at the other end, at 1/1, the problem is the
    "smallest" would be an end to and endless sequence.

    That only happens if the infinite set of Natural Numbers is actually Finite.



    Thus when you "cross" the "bound" of the unbounded, it can jump.

    Even if so you could not discern the unit fractions within this jump.

    There doesn't need to be, that is the effect of "unbounded"

    There is no need. However it is fact: Numbers that cannot be distinguished.

    Regards, WM

    Numbers that can not be distinguished do not exist.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Fri Jan 26 07:58:22 2024
    On 1/26/2024 4:56 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 25/01/2024 à 20:08, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 1/24/2024 5:10 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 24/01/2024 à 20:56, Jim Burns a écrit :

    I have come to the opinion that
    the most important skill taught in math classes,
    the most difficult to learn,
    the rarest outside of Big Mathematics,
    is to say
    "Oops. I was wrong."

    Why don't you apply your skill?
    When NUF(0) = 0 and NUF(1) > 0,
    then there must be a first point where NUF grows.

    NUF does not grow anywhere in (0,1]

    But since all unit fractions lie in this interval,
    NUF cannot grow elsewhere.

    Q.
    Where/when does a right triangle
    grow its third corner?
    A.
    Nowhere/never.
    It doesn't grow its third corner.

    It _has_ its third corner
    as part of its right.triangle.ness.
    Being not.with.third.corner forces
    being not.right.triangle.

    Not.right.triangle right.triangles are
    _attractive_ from the point of view of
    someone absent from school that day
    they taught how to say "Oops. I was wrong."
    They see confirmation of their intuitions,
    no matter what their intuitions might be,
    because a contradiction can confirm _anything_
    And its denial too. Ex falso quodlibet.

    The more traditional approach cannot see
    the genius of always having one's prejudices
    confirmed, blinded by the desire to find
    solutions that merely avoid disaster.

    ----
    NUF does not grow anywhere in (0,1]

    But since all unit fractions lie in this interval,
    NUF cannot grow elsewhere.

    Q.
    Where/when does NUF grow to a0?
    A.
    Nowhere/never.
    Like right triangles.

    ⅟ℕ₁ = {unit fraction in (0,1]}
    ⅟ℕₓ = {unit fraction in (0,x]}

    ⅟k ⟼ ⅟k 1.to.1 ⅟ℕₓ ⇉ ⅟ℕ₁
    |⅟ℕₓ| ≤ |⅟ℕ₁|

    for mₓ-1 < ⅟x ≤ mₓ
    ⅟k/mₓ ⟻ ⅟k 1.to.1 ⅟ℕₓ ⇇ ⅟ℕ₁
    |⅟ℕₓ| ≥ |⅟ℕ₁|

    |⅟ℕₓ| ≤ |⅟ℕ₁|
    |⅟ℕₓ| ≥ |⅟ℕ₁|
    |⅟ℕₓ| = |⅟ℕ₁|

    NUF does not grow anywhere in (0,1]

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Fri Jan 26 15:37:47 2024
    Le 26/01/2024 à 13:58, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 1/26/2024 4:56 AM, WM wrote:

    NUF does not grow anywhere in (0,1]

    But since all unit fractions lie in this interval,
    NUF cannot grow elsewhere.

    Q.
    Where/when does a right triangle
    grow its third corner?

    A silly question showing that you have not comprehended the whole problem. Three corners can be thought of simultaneously or not. But unit fractions cannot sit at the same point x. Therefore the function cannot grow from 0
    to 2 without passing one.

    It _has_ its third corner
    as part of its right.triangle.ness.

    But NUF(x) has nothing except the unit fractions passed over after 0.

    NUF does not grow anywhere in (0,1].

    And Bob disappears. EOD.
    Come back when you will have understood the problem.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Fri Jan 26 18:06:11 2024
    Le 26/01/2024 à 13:32, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/26/24 5:00 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 26/01/2024 à 00:48, Richard Damon a écrit :

    Except you need to start somewhere, and there is no smallest 1/n to
    start with.

    If there is no start, then there are no unit fractions.

    But they do start at the other end, at 1/1, the problem is the
    "smallest" would be an end to and endless sequence.

    If they are vexisting, then we can start at both ends.

    That only happens if the infinite set of Natural Numbers is actually Finite.

    The unit fractions end at 0.



    Thus when you "cross" the "bound" of the unbounded, it can jump.

    Even if so you could not discern the unit fractions within this jump.

    There doesn't need to be, that is the effect of "unbounded"

    There is no need. However it is fact: Numbers that cannot be distinguished.

    Numbers that can not be distinguished do not exist.

    Distinguish the numbers whereby NUF grows to ℵ.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Fri Jan 26 13:30:59 2024
    On 1/25/2024 9:15 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On Thursday, January 25, 2024
    at 3:33:50 PM UTC-8, Jim Burns wrote:

    [...]

    Anyways you know
    my longstanding rejection of Dedekind cuts

    I try to keep in mind
    the possibility of minds changing.
    It is my ray of sunshine in a
    sometimes.very.dark world.

    I try to keep in mind that
    your longstanding position might no longer stand.

    Dedekind cuts
    because defined on the reals,

    That is still incorrect for
    ℝ defined as the edgeless.Q.foresplits,
    a subset of the power set of rationals.

    ℝ := {F ⊆ ℚ| F ᣔ<ᘁ F ᣔ<ᣔ ℚ\F }\{∅,ℚ}
    ℝ ⊆ 𝒫(ℚ)

    F ᣔ<ᘁ F ⟺
    ∀p ∈ F: ∃p′ ∈ F: p < p′ ⟺
    ¬∃p ∈ F: ∀p′ ∈ F: p′ =< p

    F ᣔ<ᣔ ℚ\F ⟺
    ∀p ∈ F: ∀q ∈ ℚ\F: p < q

    Dedekind cuts because countable,

    That is still incorrect.
    The usual proofs of uncountability still apply to
    {F ⊆ ℚ| F ᣔ<ᘁ F ᣔ<ᣔ ℚ\F }\{∅,ℚ}

    Consider an endless finitely.indexed sequence
    ⟨ F₁ F₂ F₃ ... ⟩ of edgeless.ℚ.foresplits.

    There is an endless finitely.indexed sequence
    ⟨ (F₁₁,F₁₂) (F₂₁,F₂₂) (F₁₃,F₂₃) ... ⟩ of
    nested intervals with end points ordered as in
    ⟨ F₁ F₂ F₃ ... ⟩

    If Fᵦ is in each (Fₖ₁,Fₖ₂) and in ⟨ F₁ F₂ F₃ ... ⟩
    then Fᵦ follows
    infinitely.many endpoints in ⟨ F₁ F₂ F₃ ... ⟩
    But ⟨ F₁ F₂ F₃ ... ⟩ is only finitely indexed.
    Nothing in ⟨ F₁ F₂ F₃ ... ⟩ follows infinitely.many.
    Fᵦ in each (Fₖ₁,Fₖ₂) and in ⟨ F₁ F₂ F₃ ... ⟩
    not.exists.

    However,
    exists Fᵦ = ⋃S where
    S = {edgeless.ℚ.foresplit left of some (Fₖ₁,Fₖ₂)}
    Fᵦ is in each (Fₖ₁,Fₖ₂) and
    in {F ⊆ ℚ| F ᣔ<ᘁ F ᣔ<ᣔ ℚ\F }\{∅,ℚ}
    but not.in ⟨ F₁ F₂ F₃ ... ⟩

    This ⟨ F₁ F₂ F₃ ... ⟩ doesn't hold each of
    {F ⊆ ℚ| F ᣔ<ᘁ F ᣔ<ᣔ ℚ\F }\{∅,ℚ}

    Generalizing,
    each ⟨ F₁ F₂ F₃ ... ⟩ doesn't hold each of
    {F ⊆ ℚ| F ᣔ<ᘁ F ᣔ<ᣔ ℚ\F }\{∅,ℚ}

    {F ⊆ ℚ| F ᣔ<ᘁ F ᣔ<ᣔ ℚ\F }\{∅,ℚ}
    is uncountable.

    material implication because
    ex falso quodlibet,

    In material implication
    P,P⇒Q ⊢ Q
    Q is not.first.false.

    In a finite claim sequence in which
    each claim is not.first.false,
    each claim is not.false.

    However,
    if P,P⇒Q ⊢ Q is ex falso
    _we do not have_ each claim not.first.false
    Q is still not.first.false,
    but
    the _sequence_ is not _each_ not.first.false.

    Ex falso quodlibet gives us nothing.
    How could it give us something objectionable?

    ordinal assignment of cardinals
    because undecideable CH,

    There are things we know and
    there are things we don't know.
    Identifying a claim (CH) as something we don't know
    doesn't make things we know unknown.

    Are you saying it does?
    Please explain.

    and these sorts things.

    So, how do you get
    Least Upper Bound established again?

    ℝ := {F ⊆ ℚ| F ᣔ<ᘁ F ᣔ<ᣔ ℚ\F }\{∅,ℚ}

    for bounded non.empty S, lub S = ⋃S

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Arithmetic on Fri Jan 26 14:12:23 2024
    On 1/26/2024 10:37 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 26/01/2024 à 13:58, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 1/26/2024 4:56 AM, WM wrote:

    NUF does not grow anywhere in (0,1]

    But since all unit fractions lie in this interval,
    NUF cannot grow elsewhere.

    Q.
    Where/when does a right triangle
    grow its third corner?

    A silly question showing that
    you have not comprehended the whole problem.
    Three corners can be thought of simultaneously or not.

    There is nothing in the description of a right triangle
    which requires it or its corners to be thought of or
    not.thought of.

    Describe a right triangle,
    thought of or not.thought of.
    Augment the description with
    claims not.first.false about a right triangle.
    thought of or not.thought of.
    More claims known about a right triangle.
    thought of or not.thought of.

    But unit fractions cannot sit at the same point x.

    For each final.ordinal k
    for each positive point x
    too many unit fractions are in (0,x]
    to fit in ⟨1,…,k⟩
    ¬(⟨1,…,k⟩ ⇇ ⅟ℕₓ)

    For each positive point x
    the unit.fractions in (0,x]
    do not have a final ordinal
    The unit fractions in (0,x] have
    a not.final ordinal.

    Therefore the function cannot
    grow from 0 to 2 without passing one.

    k < k⁺¹
    k⋅⅟k⋅⅟k⁺¹ < k⁺¹⋅⅟k⋅⅟k⁺¹
    ⅟k⁺¹ < ⅟k

    Arithmetic says
    no ⅟k is first.

    And Bob disappears.

    After all final ordinals are not.final ordinals.
    If Bob disappears, it is from a not.final ordinal.
    |ℕ∪{Bob}| = |ℕ|

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Fri Jan 26 16:59:30 2024
    On 1/26/2024 3:41 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On Friday, January 26, 2024
    at 10:31:06 AM UTC-8, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 1/25/2024 9:15 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:

    So, how do you get
    Least Upper Bound established again?

    ℝ := {F ⊆ ℚ| F ᣔ<ᘁ F ᣔ<ᣔ ℚ\F }\{∅,ℚ}
    for bounded non.empty S, lub S = ⋃S

    After,
    in descriptive set theory,
    the existence of a complete ordered field,
    which is a stipulation of existence in the standard
    that the equivalence classes of sequences with
    the property that they are Cauchy so model a thing,
    _after_, then one might aver
    that the real numbers each partition
    the rational numbers,
    partitions inequality related to given real number,
    uncountable,
    not "just the rationals", countable.

    You are incorrect.

    One model of the real numbers is
    the equivalence classes of
    Cauchy sequences of rationals.

    Their existence is not _stipulated_ in set theory,
    it is _proved_
    "proved not stipulated" is what makes them
    a construction of ℝ from/in set theory.

    That isn't the only construction of ℝ https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Construction_of_the_real_numbers

    Any construction of ℝ proves that
    the complete ordered field is not
    a contradictory collection of requirements,
    assuming it's true that
    whatever the construction began with
    exists.
    Sets, for example.

    (Note that a two.set _partition_ of ℝ doesn't need to be
    each of one < each of the other, merely disjoint.
    That's why I refer to splits.)

    0) the standard reals have cardinality c
    1) the rationals are not gapless and
    have cardinality < c

    The power set 𝒫(ℚ) of the rationals
    has cardinality 𝒫(ℕ) ≥ |ℝ| > |ℕ|

    The edgeless.ℚ.foresplits are elements of 𝒫(ℚ) not ℚ

    2) the long-line of
    all expressions of real-valued formula has
    cardinality > c

    I bet you (RF) aren't going to tell me
    what you mean by that.

    so it results that

    0) the rationals don't have enough partitions
    because transfinite pigeonhole

    There are splits of rationals which
    don't have rationals last.before or first.after.
    Almost all of them don't, actually.

    The splits are sets of rationals, not rationals.
    There are more sets than rationals.
    There is, in particular,
    a union for each bounded non.empty collection of
    edgeless.ℚ.foresplits,
    which is the least upper bound of the collection,
    whence "model".

    1) the reals subsume having partitions about them,
    these are individuals

    I insist the Dedekind cuts are what they are,
    not, what they are not,
    which is that they are:
    defined by the real numbers a complete ordered field:

    Then give this some name other than "Dedekind cuts":
    {F ⊆ ℚ| F ᣔ<ᘁ F ᣔ<ᣔ ℚ\F }\{∅,ℚ}

    Whatever you name it,
    it is provably a model of ℝ
    Look!
    The existence of ℝ is not a prerequisite for it.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Fri Jan 26 19:50:28 2024
    On 1/26/24 1:06 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 26/01/2024 à 13:32, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/26/24 5:00 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 26/01/2024 à 00:48, Richard Damon a écrit :

    Except you need to start somewhere, and there is no smallest 1/n to
    start with.

    If there is no start, then there are no unit fractions.

    But they do start at the other end, at 1/1, the problem is the
    "smallest" would be an end to and endless sequence.

    If they are vexisting, then we can start at both ends.

    Only if they HAVE both ends.

    Being "unbounded" and "infinite in number" means they have only one end,


    That only happens if the infinite set of Natural Numbers is actually
    Finite.

    The unit fractions end at 0.

    No, they end just above 0. 0 is not a unit fraction.




    Thus when you "cross" the "bound" of the unbounded, it can jump.

    Even if so you could not discern the unit fractions within this jump. >>>>
    There doesn't need to be, that is the effect of "unbounded"

    There is no need. However it is fact: Numbers that cannot be
    distinguished.

    Numbers that can not be distinguished do not exist.

    Distinguish the numbers whereby NUF grows to ℵ.


    They don't exist, PEIOD,

    Prove that they do,

    REAL PROOF, not just hand wave arguing.

    Regards, WM



    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Sat Jan 27 10:50:02 2024
    Le 27/01/2024 à 01:50, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/26/24 1:06 PM, WM wrote:

    If they are existing, then we can start at both ends.

    Only if they HAVE both ends.

    They have, and we can if all points exist.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Sat Jan 27 10:47:55 2024
    Le 26/01/2024 à 20:12, Jim Burns a écrit :

    Arithmetic says
    no ⅟k is first.

    Obviously that would violate NUF(x) in connection with
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) > 0.
    Therefore Peano works only on visible numbers.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Fritz Feldhase on Sat Jan 27 11:27:09 2024
    Fritz Feldhase schrieb am Samstag, 27. Januar 2024 um 07:10:56 UTC+1:
    On Saturday, January 27, 2024 at 1:50:37 AM UTC+1, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 1/26/24 1:06 PM, WM wrote:

    The unit fractions end at 0. [WM]

    No, they end just above 0. [RD]

    No, THE SEQUENCE OF UNIT FRACTIONS

    1/1, 1/2, 1/3, ...

    doesn't "end" at all.

    At zero it has ended.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Sat Jan 27 10:25:53 2024
    On 1/27/24 5:50 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 27/01/2024 à 01:50, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/26/24 1:06 PM, WM wrote:

    If they are existing, then we can start at both ends.

    Only if they HAVE both ends.

    They have, and we can if all points exist.

    Regards, WM

    Sp, what it that highest natural number?

    You just claimed it exists.

    And if you do name it, what is that number + 1?

    Why isn't it also a Natural Number.


    Your "logic" is just flawed, and you are assuming the existance of
    things that are impossible.

    You seem to have a problem that you are trying to define make "existing"
    also mean needing to be finite, but also let the set of Natural Numbers
    "exist" which puts your system into contradiction of an infinite thing
    being finite, so you try to "hide" that contradiction in "darkness".


    As I have been saying, you logic just doesn't work with unbounded sets.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Sat Jan 27 15:22:01 2024
    On 1/26/2024 9:32 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On Friday, January 26, 2024
    at 1:59:37 PM UTC-8, Jim Burns wrote:

    [...]

    About
    "the complete ordered field being complete",
    and Eudoxus/Dedekind/Cauchy,
    and why they're insufficient,
    and why Least Upper Bound property of
    the equivalence classes of sequences that are Cauchy,
    that have the property of being Cauchy,
    is a stipulation, not a derivation,
    after all the definable ones,
    if you start with Dedekind cuts
    it is, because you forget, because
    the _model_ in the _model theory_ must always embody
    _all its relations_, and,
    the assignment to partitions of rationals,
    by real numbers of course
    or else it wouldn't be suitable at all,
    you will so assert Least Upper Bound
    to make gaplessness,
    then
    it was just an artifice and a convenience,
    not a contrivance.

    Second verse, same as the first.
    With commentary.

    About
    "the complete ordered field being complete",
    and Eudoxus/Dedekind/Cauchy,
    and why they're insufficient,
    and why Least Upper Bound property of
    the equivalence classes of sequences that are Cauchy,
    that have the property of being Cauchy,
    is a stipulation, not a derivation,

    The least upper bound property for
    equivalence classes of Cauchy Sequences of rationals
    is derived from
    the stipulation that
    it is all and only
    equivalence classes of Cauchy Sequences of rationals
    for which
    the least upper bound property is being asserted.

    after all the definable ones,
    if you start with Dedekind cuts
    it is, because you forget, because
    the _model_ in the _model theory_ must always embody
    _all its relations_, and,
    the assignment to partitions of rationals,
    by real numbers of course

    No.
    That is the whole point.
    NOT by real numbers. _Of course_

    We _stipulate_ that
    ELFSꟴ ⊆ 𝒫(ℚ) holds
    all and only the edgeless.ℚ.foresplits
    and we _derive_ from that stipulation
    the least upper bound property for ELFSꟴ

    If you (RF) base your analysis on
    it being hinky to "construct" the real numbers
    from the real numbers,
    then, Hurrah! we have a point of agreement.
    _But that's not what we do_

    Describe an edgeless.ℚ.foresplit F
    F is a subset of ℚ
    F and ℚ\F are not.empty
    each of F < each of ℚ\F
    The real numbers are not required here.
    The real numbers are not mentioned here.

    Stipulate that,
    if F is an edgeless.ℚ.foresplit,
    then F is in ELFSꟴ, and,
    if F is in ELFSꟴ,
    then F is an edgeless.ℚ.foresplit

    We derive that
    F ⊆ F′ ∧ F′ ⊆ F″ ⟹ F ⊆ F″
    and
    F ⊆ F′ ∧ F ⊇ F′ ⟹ F = F′
    Easy. They're true for all sets.

    We derive that
    F ⊆ F′ ∨ F ⊇ F′
    without mentioning ℝ

    F ⊆ F′ ∨ F ⊈ F′

    (i)
    F ⊆ F′
    ⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯
    F ⊆ F′ ∨ F ⊇ F′

    (ii)
    F ⊈ F′
    p ∈ F ∧ p ∉ F′

    p ∉ F′ ⇔ p ∈ ℚ\F′ ⟹
    ∀p′ ∈ ℚ: p ≤ p′ ⇒ p′ ∈ ℚ\F′
    ∀p′ ∈ ℚ: p′ ∈ F′ ⇒ p′ < p

    p ∈ F ⟹
    ∀p′ ∈ ℚ: p′ < p ⇒ p′ ∈ F

    ∀p′ ∈ ℚ: p′ ∈ F′ ⇒ p′ ∈ F
    F ⊇ F'
    ⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯
    F ⊆ F′ ∨ F ⊇ F′

    Now, when we define '≤' as '⊆'
    we know that '≤' has the properties required.
    By derivation, not by stipulation.

    That's only part of the derivation.
    The rest of it is the same, in that
    we do not mention ℝ, apart from commentary.

    The whole point is
    to derive that something and its relations exist
    having the properties of a complete ordered field,
    without stipulating that ℝ and relations exist.

    Avoiding hinkiness.

    or else it wouldn't be suitable at all,
    you will so assert Least Upper Bound
    to make gaplessness,
    then
    it was just an artifice and a convenience,
    not a contrivance.

    We stipulate that
    the union ⋃S of
    bounded non.empty set S of edgeless.ℚ.foresplits
    exists.
    We derive that
    ⋃S is the least upper bound of S.
    Non.hinkily.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to FromTheRafters on Sat Jan 27 18:43:41 2024
    On 1/27/2024 12:01 PM, FromTheRafters wrote:
    Richard Damon formulated the question :
    On 1/27/24 5:50 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 27/01/2024 à 01:50, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/26/24 1:06 PM, WM wrote:

    If they are existing,
    then we can start at both ends.

    Only if they HAVE both ends.

    They have, and we can if all points exist.

    Sp, what it that highest natural number?

             6
            5  7
         3 4    8
        2        9
     { 1           .
                    .
                     .}

    Six?

    https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=O6rHeD5x2tI
    How many licks does it take to get to
    the Tootsie Roll center of a Tootsie Pop?
    (Three.)

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Sat Jan 27 18:32:13 2024
    On 1/27/2024 5:47 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 26/01/2024 à 20:12, Jim Burns a écrit :

    Arithmetic says
    no ⅟k is first.

    Obviously that would violate NUF(x)
    in connection with
    ∀n ∈ ℕ:
    1/n - 1/(n+1) > 0.

    ∀n ∈ ℕ₁:
    ∀k ∈ ℕ₁:
    ⅟n - ⅟(n+k) > 0.
    Arithmetic.

    ∀n ∈ ℕ₁:
    ∀k ∈ ℕ₁:
    |{⅟j ∈ ⅟ℕ₁: ⅟n ≥ ⅟j ≥ ⅟(n+k)}| ≤
    |{⅟j ∈ ⅟ℕ₁: ⅟n ≥ ⅟j > 0}|

    ∀n ∈ ℕ₁:
    ∀k ∈ ℕ₁:
    k ≤ |{⅟j ∈ ⅟ℕ₁: ⅟n ≥ ⅟j > 0}|

    ∀n ∈ ℕ₁:
    |{⅟j ∈ ⅟ℕ₁: ⅟n ≥ ⅟j > 0}| ∉ ℕ₁

    ∀n ∈ ℕ₁: NUF(⅟n) ∉ ℕ₁
    Arithmetic.

    Therefore
    Peano works only on visible numbers.

    For each non.empty split F,H of ⟨0,…,k⟩
    i‖i⁺¹ exists last‖first in F‖H
    F = ⟨0,…,i⟩
    H = ⟨i⁺¹,…,k⟩

    Consider predicate P(j) on
    ends of ⟨0,…,j⟩

    Define super.predicate Pᙿᑉ(j) such that
    Pᙿᑉ(j) :⇔ ∀j′=<j: P(j′)

    | Assume
    | exists ⟨0,…,k⟩: P(0) ∧ ¬P(k)
    |
    | Pᙿᑉ(j) determines
    | a non.empty split Fₖ,Hₖ of ⟨0,…,k⟩
    | Fₖ = {j:Pᙿᑉ(j)}
    | Hₖ = {j:¬Pᙿᑉ(j)}
    |
    | iₖ‖iₖ⁺¹ exists last‖first in Fₖ‖Hₖ
    | Fₖ = {j:Pᙿᑉ(j)} = ⟨0,…,iₖ⟩
    | Hₖ = {j:¬Pᙿᑉ(j)} = ⟨iₖ⁺¹,…,k⟩
    |
    | Pᙿᑉ(iₖ)
    | P(iₖ)
    |
    | ¬Pᙿᑉ(iₖ⁺1)
    | ∀i′<iₖ⁺¹: P(i′)
    | ¬P(iₖ⁺¹)
    |
    | exists ⟨0,…,iₖ,iₖ⁺¹⟩: P(iₖ) ∧ ¬P(iₖ⁺¹)

    Therefore,
    if exists ⟨0,…,k⟩: P(0) ∧ ¬P(k)
    then exists ⟨0,…,iₖ,iₖ⁺¹⟩: P(iₖ) ∧ ¬P(iₖ⁺¹)

    That is Peano induction.
    It is a theorem about ends of ⟨0,…,k⟩
    A more familiar way to write the same claim is
    P(0) ∧ ∀i∈ℕ: P(i)⇒P(i⁺¹) ⟹ ∀k∈ℕ: P(k)

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Sat Jan 27 19:56:18 2024
    On 1/27/2024 12:39 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On Friday, January 26, 2024
    at 12:41:08 PM UTC-8, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On Friday, January 26, 2024
    at 10:31:06 AM UTC-8, Jim Burns wrote:

    [...]
    [...]

    Not.first.false, ....

    Material implication is kind of like that.

    Yes. Yes, yes, yes. Yes.
    In a material implication,
    its conclusion is not.first.false.

    That can be useful because _we can see_ that
    its conclusion is not.first.false,
    whatever else we know or don't know.

    In a finite sequence of claims in which
    any claim is false,
    one of the claims is first.false.

    In other words,
    in a finite sequence of claims in which
    each claim is not.first.false,
    each claims is not.false.

    We have the opportunity to find
    a finite sequence of claims in which
    _we can see_ that each claim is not.first.false.

    If we find such a sequence, it will have
    claims we know for "external" reasons
    -- maybe some other theorem, elsewhere -- and
    claims we know for "internal" reasons
    -- such as a conclusion Q of material implication
    which we see is preceded by P and P⇒Q

    Consider:
    we know this fact about objects we aren't seeing
    because of claims we are seeing, in phosphor dots
    or chalk dust or clay scratches.

    Sounds crazy, am I right?
    But this is limited to finite sequences of claims
    in which _each claim_ is not.first.false.
    That is a high bar to clear.

    It is a bar _not cleared_ by
    a sequence with only _some_ not.first.false claims
    -- such as in the case of ex falso quodlibet.

    Unfortunately when ~P,

    When ~P, in a finite sequence, there is a first.false.
    The condition for knowing these claims by seeing them
    is being in a finite sequence _without_ first.false.
    The condition is not met.

    Unfortunately when ~P,
    then they've sort of missed
    the contrapositive "not.first.false",
    that they sort of demand being evaluated in
    an un-sorted manner, "not.any.false",
    otherwise,
    the rules engine spits out "insert money".

    I am sorry that these people have lost money,
    but their logic is broken.

    I recommend that
    they stop using broken logic,
    not that they stop using logic.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Sun Jan 28 11:50:23 2024
    Le 27/01/2024 à 16:25, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/27/24 5:50 AM, WM wrote:

    So, what it that highest natural number?

    It is dark, therefore unknown as an individual.

    You just claimed it exists.

    And if you do name it, what is that number + 1?

    Why isn't it also a Natural Number.

    Peano holds only for visible numbers.

    As I have been saying, you logic just doesn't work with unbounded sets.

    But it is required for mathematics. In particular a function counting
    points can only increase at these points. Every contrary "logic" is
    rubbish.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Sun Jan 28 07:50:33 2024
    On 1/28/24 6:50 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 27/01/2024 à 16:25, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/27/24 5:50 AM, WM wrote:

    So, what it that highest natural number?

    It is dark, therefore unknown as an individual.

    It can't exist, by the definition of Natural Numbers.

    *ALL* Natural Numbers have a successor. DEFINITION,

    You are just proving you don't understand what you are talking about.


    You just claimed it exists.

    And if you do name it, what is that number + 1?

    Why isn't it also a Natural Number.

    Peano holds only for visible numbers.

    Peano defines what are called the Natural Numbers.

    I guess you are admitting your "dark" numbers are not what is called the natural numbers.


    As I have been saying, you logic just doesn't work with unbounded sets.

    But it is required for mathematics. In particular a function counting
    points can only increase at these points. Every contrary "logic" is
    rubbish.

    But a function counting points can only be defined if there is a first
    point to start the count.

    A variant of NUF(x) counting unit fractions above x, exists, as that end
    has a start.

    You can't try to count from a direction that has no end.


    Regards, WM



    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Sun Jan 28 13:07:46 2024
    On 1/27/2024 10:05 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On Saturday, January 27, 2024
    at 4:56:24 PM UTC-8, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 1/27/2024 12:39 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:

    Unfortunately when ~P,
    then they've sort of missed
    the contrapositive "not.first.false",
    that they sort of demand being evaluated in
    an un-sorted manner, "not.any.false",
    otherwise,
    the rules engine spits out "insert money".

    I am sorry that these people have lost money,
    but their logic is broken.
    I recommend that
    they stop using broken logic,
    not that they stop using logic.

    If by "broken" you mean
    "arbitrarily capricious and not thoroughly integral",
    yeah, EFQ+MI is readily broken.

    EFQ+MI: ex falso quodlibet and material implication

    With P being
    "the bottom didn't fall out of the gold market
    today"
    and Q being
    "gold is a good investment",
    you might figure that
    material implication would arrive at,
    in the wider context of
    a usual scrimper and saver and value investor,
    that each day
    they invest their money in gold.

    Material implication isn't broken there.
    Material implication isn't used there.

    P is there and Q is there.
    P⇒Q isn't there.

    I'm looking at your example of brokenness,
    and it seems to me that,
    although it can't be a failure of material implication,
    not being material implication,
    it is a failure of _physical induction_
    by which I mean _not_ the property with that name
    of natural numbers or ordinals.
    | ... Au↑₋₄ Au↑₋₃ Au↑₋₂ Au↑₋₁ Au↑₀
    | Therefore Au↑₊₁

    Or, rather, the "failure" of physical induction.
    Yes, it might be Au↓₊₁ not Au↑₊₁
    But physical induction only claims:
    this is the way to bet.

    Sometimes, it's a very confident bet.
    "Bet that the sun will rise tomorrow"
    But it's a bet, and bets can be lost.
    Losing a bet does _not_ mean that,
    given what one knew _at betting time_
    one should have bet the other way.

    Justifying physical induction has a literature. https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Inductive_reasoning#External_links

    My own swing at the piñata is that
    physical induction is supported by
    Baye's theorem which is supported by
    the Dutch book theorems which are supported by
    finite claim.sequences of only not.first.false
    with material implication among the not.first.false.

    Different initial assessments of
    the probability of a hypothesis converge
    as evidence increases.

    "That's how to bet" is not
    "That's what will happen".
    Caveat inductor.
    But that _is_ how to bet.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Sun Jan 28 17:23:32 2024
    On 1/28/2024 1:46 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On Sunday, January 28, 2024
    at 10:07:53 AM UTC-8, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 1/27/2024 10:05 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On Saturday, January 27, 2024
    at 4:56:24 PM UTC-8, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 1/27/2024 12:39 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On Friday, January 26, 2024
    at 12:41:08 PM UTC-8, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On Friday, January 26, 2024
    at 10:31:06 AM UTC-8, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 1/25/2024 9:15 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On Thursday, January 25, 2024
    at 3:33:50 PM UTC-8, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 1/24/2024 7:52 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On Wednesday, January 24, 2024
    at 1:42:17 PM UTC-8, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 1/24/2024 3:17 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:

    If you can't split a line into points,
    and can't draw points into a line,
    what makes you think that
    axiomatizing the gaplessness of
    the complete ordered field
    is a good idea?
    Or is it just wishful thinking,
    of the contradictory sort?

    If
    the set ℚ of rationals,
    its power set 𝒫(ℚ), and
    the power.set.subset of edgeless.foresplits
    {F ⊆ ℚ| Fᣔ<ᘁFᣔ<ᣔℚ\F }\{∅,ℚ} ⊆ 𝒫(ℚ)
    isn't wishful thinking,
    then
    axiomatizing the gaplessness of
    the complete ordered field
    isn't wishful thinking.

    F ᣔ<ᘁ F ⟺
    ∀p ∈ F: ∃p′ ∈ F: p < p′ ⟺
    ¬∃p ∈ F: ∀p′ ∈ F: p′ =< p

    F ᣔ<ᣔ ℚ\F ⟺
    ∀p ∈ F: ∀q ∈ ℚ\F: p < q

    Unfortunately when ~P,
    then they've sort of missed
    the contrapositive "not.first.false",
    that they sort of demand being evaluated in
    an un-sorted manner, "not.any.false",
    otherwise,
    the rules engine spits out "insert money".

    I am sorry that these people have lost money,
    but their logic is broken.
    I recommend that
    they stop using broken logic,
    not that they stop using logic.

    If by "broken" you mean
    "arbitrarily capricious and not thoroughly integral",
    yeah, EFQ+MI is readily broken.

    With P being
    "the bottom didn't fall out of the gold market
    today"
    and Q being
    "gold is a good investment",
    you might figure that
    material implication would arrive at,
    in the wider context of
    a usual scrimper and saver and value investor,
    that each day
    they invest their money in gold.

    | ... Au↑₋₄ Au↑₋₃ Au↑₋₂ Au↑₋₁ Au↑₀
    | Therefore Au↑₊₁

    isn't material implication.

    Or, rather, the "failure" of physical induction.
    Yes, it might be Au↓₊₁ not Au↑₊₁
    But physical induction only claims:
    this is the way to bet.

    Sometimes, it's a very confident bet.
    "Bet that the sun will rise tomorrow"
    But it's a bet, and bets can be lost.
    Losing a bet does _not_ mean that,
    given what one knew _at betting time_
    one should have bet the other way.

    Justifying physical induction has a literature.
    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Inductive_reasoning#External_links

    My own swing at the piñata is that
    physical induction is supported by
    Baye's theorem which is supported by
    the Dutch book theorems which are supported by
    finite claim.sequences of only not.first.false
    with material implication among the not.first.false.

    Different initial assessments of
    the probability of a hypothesis converge
    as evidence increases.

    "That's how to bet" is not
    "That's what will happen".
    Caveat inductor.
    But that _is_ how to bet.

    Bayes priors
    Jeffreys priors
    Bayes uncertainty
    Jeffreys uncertainty,
    Knightian uncertainty
    Central Limit Theorem
    Gaussian distribution,
    log-normal distribution
    "Uniformization Limit Theorem"
    "Laws of Large Numbers",
    the weak and strong
    the global and total
    criteria of convergence
    the martingale
    gambler's ruin
    the naturals at uniform random
    not-a-real-function distributions
    limits of Dutch Book.
    "error record"
    sometimes "long tail"
    "material implication"
    "classical quasi-modal logic"
    "relevance logic"
    "classical quasi-modal logic"
    statistics and probability,
    Student's, t-,
    Fisher,
    and Chi-squared,
    up to ANOVA/ANCOVA
    MANOVA/MANCOVA,
    _continuous_ distributions
    _discrete_ distributions
    _discrete, infinite, uniform distributions_
    unrelated variables,
    fabrication of non-sense.


    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Mon Jan 29 14:39:11 2024
    On 1/28/2024 10:12 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On Sunday, January 28, 2024
    at 2:23:42 PM UTC-8, Jim Burns wrote:

    [...]

    Probability theory is one of the most active fields,
    in, "nonstandard", analysis.

    In it, are some of the most pressing needs,
    for what mathematics _owes_, of the extra-ordinary,
    the super-classical, the infinitary-reasoning,
    the "non-standard".

    That isn't what I am talking about.

    Some of what we here talk about sounds peculiar
    because it's legitimately peculiar.
    Some of what we here talk about sounds peculiar
    because it's wrong.

    I have been looking for less.peculiar ways of
    framing peculiar and correct results that
    some of us think are peculiar and wrong.
    That might not be easily distinguishable from
    showing that some wrong claims here are wrong.

    There is a vast realm beyond my little project.
    That realm.beyond isn't what I am talking about.

    Why we've chosen what.a.proof.is to be
    that which we call a proof.

    Why we've chosen what.a.natural.number.is to be
    that which we call a natural number.

    Why we've chosen what.a.real.line.is to be
    that which we call a real line.

    That is what I am talking about.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Tue Jan 30 08:36:52 2024
    Le 28/01/2024 à 13:50, Richard Damon a écrit :

    You can't try to count from a direction that has no end.

    If the points are there, they can be counted. If they have distances, then there is a first one.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Tue Jan 30 07:50:50 2024
    On 1/30/24 3:36 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 28/01/2024 à 13:50, Richard Damon a écrit :

    You can't try to count from a direction that has no end.

    If the points are there, they can be counted. If they have distances,
    then there is a first one.

    Regards, WM


    How do you count something if you can't get to the "first" of them?

    Your logic is just flawed.

    There does not need to be a first one, as the distances shrink faster
    than the positions, leaving room for more and more before them.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Tue Jan 30 13:06:22 2024
    On 1/30/2024 3:36 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 28/01/2024 à 13:50, Richard Damon a écrit :

    You can't try to count from
    a direction that has no end.

    If the points are there, they can be counted.
    If they have distances, then there is a first one.

    If there is a first one, there is a before.first one.

    If exists point x in (0,1]
    then exists midpoint x/2 at
    | the intersection of segment 0:x and segment P:P′
    | such that points P and P′ are the intersection of
    | circles C₀ and Cₓ radii |0:x| centers 0 and x

    If exists first unit.fraction x
    then
    exists unit n ∈ ℕ such that n⋅x = 1
    exists unit 2n ∈ ℕ such that (2n)⋅(x/2) = 1
    and exists before.first unit.fraction x/2

    First unit.fraction without before.first not.exists

    First unit.fraction with before.first
    contradicts "first", and not.exists, too.

    With or without before.first,
    a first unit.fraction not.exists.

    ----
    Define "final" such that,
    for each final ordinal k
    inserting one other can't fit
    ¬(⟨1,…,k⟩ ⇇ ⟨1,…,k,k⁺¹⟩)

    For each final ordinal k
    k.many unit.fractions are in (0,x]
    ⟨⅟k⁺ᵐˣ,…,⅟1⁺ᵐˣ⟩ ⊆ (0,X]
    such that mₓ < ⅟x =< mₓ⁺¹
    with at least one other ⅟k⁺ᵐˣ/2 ∈ (0,⅟k⁺ᵐˣ)
    which can't all fit in ⟨1,…,k⟩
    ¬(⟨1,…,k⟩ ⇇ ⟨⅟k⁺ᵐˣ/2,⅟k⁺ᵐˣ,…,⅟1⁺ᵐˣ⟩)

    k⁺¹.many with
    all the other unit-fractions in (0,x]
    won't fit in ⟨1,…,k⟩
    ¬(⟨1,…,k⟩ ⇇ ⅟ℕₓ)

    For each final ordinal k
    |k| isn't |⅟ℕₓ|

    |⅟ℕₓ| isn't any final ordinal.
    ¬¬(⅟ℕₓ ⇇ ⅟ℕₓ∪{Bob})
    Inserting one more fits in ⅟ℕₓ
    ⅟ℕₓ ⇇ ⅟ℕₓ∪{Bob}

    After all final ordinals are not.final ordinals.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Wed Jan 31 08:01:52 2024
    Le 30/01/2024 à 13:50, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/30/24 3:36 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 28/01/2024 à 13:50, Richard Damon a écrit :

    You can't try to count from a direction that has no end.

    If the points are there, they can be counted. If they have distances,
    then there is a first one.

    How do you count something if you can't get to the "first" of them?

    Since they are dark, no.one can ctually count them. But we can prove that
    there is a first one.

    There does not need to be a first one, as the distances shrink faster
    than the positions, leaving room for more and more before them.

    ℵ₀ unit fractions together with the "uncountably" many points between
    them must lie at the left edge of the interval (0, 1]. They do not fit
    into one point. Hence they can be divided into parts with fewer unit
    fractions.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Instead of actual infinity we bette on Wed Jan 31 07:57:11 2024
    Le 30/01/2024 à 19:06, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 1/30/2024 3:36 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 28/01/2024 à 13:50, Richard Damon a écrit :

    You can't try to count from
    a direction that has no end.

    If the points are there, they can be counted.
    If they have distances, then there is a first one.

    If there is a first one, there is a before.first one.

    If there is a visible first one, then there is a visible before the first
    one.
    But there is no visible first one.

    If exists point x in (0,1]
    then exists midpoint x/2 at

    That is the dynamic or potential infinity of visible points.
    Actual infinity is static. Only a first unit fraction can agree with mathematics:
    NUF(0) = 0, NUF (x>0) > 0 and ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) = d_n > 0.
    Instead of actual infinity we better should write: No complete overall
    view is possible.

    First unit.fraction without before.first not.exists

    The interval [0, 1] contains infinitely many points including a first and
    a last obe.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Wed Jan 31 07:42:43 2024
    On 1/31/24 3:01 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 30/01/2024 à 13:50, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/30/24 3:36 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 28/01/2024 à 13:50, Richard Damon a écrit :

    You can't try to count from a direction that has no end.

    If the points are there, they can be counted. If they have distances,
    then there is a first one.

    How do you count something if you can't get to the "first" of them?

    Since they are dark, no.one can ctually count them. But we can prove
    that there is a first one.

    So, you agree that NUF(x) can't count them.


    There does not need to be a first one, as the distances shrink faster
    than the positions, leaving room for more and more before them.

    ℵ₀ unit fractions together with the "uncountably" many points between them must lie at the left edge of the interval (0, 1]. They do not fit
    into one point. Hence they can be divided into parts with fewer unit fractions.
    Regards, WM


    But there is no "edge" to pile them all at.

    You just don't seem to understand that.

    And yes, you can get uncountably many points (real numbers) into as
    small of a space you want.

    There is a fundamental diference betwen the single fixed point of a
    single number or end of a closed interval, and the the termination of an
    open interval whcih does't have a single point as its "end".

    Your logic just can't handle open intervals, or infinite unbounded sets.
    (those whose bound isn't in the set, like the unit fractions),

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Wed Jan 31 13:48:07 2024
    On 1/31/2024 2:57 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 30/01/2024 à 19:06, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 1/30/2024 3:36 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 28/01/2024 à 13:50, Richard Damon a écrit :

    You can't try to count from
    a direction that has no end.

    If the points are there, they can be counted.
    If they have distances, then there is a first one.

    If there is a first one, there is a before.first one.

    If there is a visible first one,
    then there is a visible before the first one.

    We start with claims true about
    10⁶ᐧ⁰²²¹⁴⁰⁷⁶ᴱ²³ unit.fractions.

    We continue with claims not.first.false about
    those same 10⁶ᐧ⁰²²¹⁴⁰⁷⁶ᴱ²³ unit.fractions.

    Not 10⁶ᐧ⁰²²¹⁴⁰⁷⁶ᴱ²³ _claims_ though,
    barely a handful of claims.

    One of the claims is that
    this unit.fraction is not.first in the lime.
    We see the handful of claims is each
    not.first.false in the order claimed.
    We know that claim is true about each of
    10⁶ᐧ⁰²²¹⁴⁰⁷⁶ᴱ²³ unit fractions.

    We can't see 10⁶ᐧ⁰²²¹⁴⁰⁷⁶ᴱ²³ unit fractions,
    but we know they're each not.first.

    But there is no visible first one.

    Visiblewm or darkwm, we know each is not.first.

    If exists point x in (0,1]
    then exists midpoint x/2 at

    That is the dynamic or potential infinity of
    visible points.
    Actual infinity is static.

    After _all_ final ordinals,
    not merely 10⁶ᐧ⁰²²¹⁴⁰⁷⁶ᴱ²³ of them
    there are no other final ordinals. "All".

    A final ordinal can play musical chairs. https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Musical_chairs
    All are seated.
    All stand up, and a chair is removed.
    Music plays, all parade around the chairs.
    Musics stops, all sit down.
    No, all _try_ to sit down.
    One player is left standing, and is out of the game.
    Do it again. And again.

    An ordinal after all final ordinals
    can't play music chairs correctly.
    All stand up, and a chair is removed.
    Music stops, _all sit down_ Really. All.
    No one is eliminated.

    Only a first unit fraction can agree with [WM]

    Fixed it. You're welcome.

    NUF(0) = 0,
    NUF (x>0) > 0 and
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) = d_n > 0.

    ∀n ∈ ℕ: ∀k ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+k) > 0.

    Instead of actual infinity we better should write:
    No complete overall view is possible.

    We start with claims true about
    10⁶ᐧ⁰²²¹⁴⁰⁷⁶ᴱ²³ unit.fractions.

    We continue with claims not.first.false about
    those same 10⁶ᐧ⁰²²¹⁴⁰⁷⁶ᴱ²³ unit.fractions.

    Not 10⁶ᐧ⁰²²¹⁴⁰⁷⁶ᴱ²³ _claims_ though,
    barely a handful of claims.

    A view of a handful of claims is possible.
    That's how we know what we know about
    those same 10⁶ᐧ⁰²²¹⁴⁰⁷⁶ᴱ²³ unit.fractions,
    a view of which is not possible.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Thu Feb 1 09:39:00 2024
    Le 31/01/2024 à 19:48, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 1/31/2024 2:57 AM, WM wrote:

    Only a first unit fraction can agree with [WM]

    Fixed it. You're welcome.

    You are unable to interpret the maths correctly.

    NUF(0) = 0,
    NUF (x>0) > 0

    ∃ 1/n (0, 1]: ~∃ 1/m < 1/n.

    Never mind. There are many dyslogical matheologians like you.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Thu Feb 1 09:46:41 2024
    Le 31/01/2024 à 13:42, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/31/24 3:01 AM, WM wrote:

    How do you count something if you can't get to the "first" of them?

    Since they are dark, no-one can actually count them. But we can prove
    that there is a first one.

    So, you agree that NUF(x) can't count them.

    NUF counts them by definition. The result cannot be known because it is
    dark.


    There does not need to be a first one, as the distances shrink faster
    than the positions, leaving room for more and more before them.

    ℵ₀ unit fractions together with the "uncountably" many points between
    them must lie at the left edge of the interval (0, 1]. They do not fit
    into one point. Hence they can be divided into parts with fewer unit
    fractions.

    And yes, you can get uncountably many points (real numbers) into as
    small of a space you want.

    But not into one point!

    There is a fundamental diference betwen the single fixed point of a
    single number or end of a closed interval, and the the termination of an
    open interval whcih does't have a single point as its "end".

    In actual infinity it has a single point at its end, in potential infiniy
    it has a gap at its (not existing) end.
    But that is irrelevant for the simple conclusion: In actual infinity
    NUF(0) = 0 and NUF (x>0) > 0 ==> ∃ 1/n (0, 1]: ~∃ 1/m < 1/n.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Thu Feb 1 07:36:48 2024
    On 2/1/24 4:46 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 31/01/2024 à 13:42, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 1/31/24 3:01 AM, WM wrote:

    How do you count something if you can't get to the "first" of them?

    Since they are dark, no-one can actually count them. But we can prove
    that there is a first one.

    So, you agree that NUF(x) can't count them.

    NUF counts them by definition. The result cannot be known because it is
    dark.


    But it CAN'T in a direction that doesn't have a first.

    Even if your idea was right and that there was a first that was dark,
    you couldn't count them, as counting is an individual action, so you
    can't count "dark numbers".

    THus, your definition is just incorrrect.



    There does not need to be a first one, as the distances shrink
    faster than the positions, leaving room for more and more before them.

    ℵ₀ unit fractions together with the "uncountably" many points between >>> them must lie at the left edge of the interval (0, 1]. They do not
    fit into one point. Hence they can be divided into parts with fewer
    unit fractions.

    And yes, you can get uncountably many points (real numbers) into as
    small of a space you want.

    But not into one point!

    So?

    There is still no Smallest Unit Fraction.

    Your logic just can't handle the potential infinities of "Dense" systems.


    There is a fundamental diference betwen the single fixed point of a
    single number or end of a closed interval, and the the termination of
    an open interval whcih does't have a single point as its "end".

    In actual infinity it has a single point at its end, in potential
    infiniy it has a gap at its (not existing) end.
    But that is irrelevant for the simple conclusion: In actual infinity
    NUF(0) = 0 and NUF (x>0) > 0 ==> ∃ 1/n (0, 1]: ~∃ 1/m < 1/n.

    It seems your idea of "Potential Infinity" is just ill defined.

    Since you refuse to state your axioms, you are just admitting that you
    logic is BASEDLESS and thus worthless.

    Your LOGIC has gone "Dark" and it can't be used.


    Regards, WM




    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Thu Feb 1 15:52:28 2024
    On 2/1/2024 4:39 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 31/01/2024 à 19:48, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 1/31/2024 2:57 AM, WM wrote:

    Only a first unit fraction can agree with [WM]

    Fixed it. You're welcome.

    NUF(0) = 0,
    NUF (x>0) > 0

    ∃ 1/n (0, 1]: ~∃ 1/m < 1/n.

    | Assume [WM] is math.
    | Assume ∃⅟n ∈ (0,1]: ¬∃ ⅟m < ⅟n
    |
    | ∃n ∈ ℕ: n⋅⅟n = 1
    | ¬∃m ∈ ℕ: m⋅⅟m = 1 ∧ ⅟m < ⅟n
    |
    | However,
    | ∃m ∈ ℕ: m = n+1 ∧ n < m ∧
    | n⋅⅟n⋅⅟m < m⋅⅟n⋅⅟m ∧
    | ⅟m < ⅟n
    | Contradiction.

    Therefore,
    no unit.fraction x is
    below all unit.fractions.
    ¬∃⅟n ∈ (0,1]: ¬∃⅟m < ⅟n

    ----
    More generally,
    no positive.point x is
    below all unit.fractions.
    ¬∃x ∈ (0,1]: ¬∃ ⅟m < x

    | Assume otherwise.
    | Assume δ ∈ (0,1]: ¬∃⅟m < δ
    |
    | 0 < δ ∈ {x| ¬∃⅟m < x}
    | {x| ¬∃⅟m < x} is non.empty and bounded.
    | β is the least upper bound of {x| ¬∃⅟m < x}
    |
    | 0 < δ ≤ β
    | 0 < β/2 < β < 2β
    |
    | β < 2β ∉ {x| ¬∃⅟m < x}
    | ∃⅟m < 2β: m ∈ ℕ
    | ⅟m₂ᵦ < 2β ∧ m₂ᵦ ∈ ℕ
    | Thus,
    | ⅟(4m₂ᵦ) < β/2 ∧ 4m₂ᵦ ∈ ℕ
    |
    | However
    | β > β/2 ∈ {x| ¬∃ ⅟m < x}
    | ¬∃ ⅟m < β/2
    | ¬(⅟(4m₂ᵦ) < β/2)
    | Contradiction.

    Therefore,
    no positive point x is
    below all unit.fractions.
    ¬∃x ∈ (0,1]: ¬∃ ⅟m < x

    ----
    No positive point x is above a maximum of
    final.ordinal k.many unit fractions.
    ¬∃x ∈ (0,1]: ¬∃k ∈ ℕᶠⁿᵒʳᵈ: ¬∃ᵏ⁺¹ ⅟m < x

    ∀x ∈ (0,1]:
    ∃mₓ ∈ ℕᶠⁿᵒʳᵈ: mₓ ≤ ⅟x < mₓ+1
    ∀k ∈ ℕᶠⁿᵒʳᵈ:
    ⟨⅟k⁺ᵐˣ,…,⅟1⁺ᵐˣ⟩ ᣔ< x
    |⅟k⁺ᵐˣ,…,⅟1⁺ᵐˣ| = |k|
    ¬(⟨⅟k⁺ᵐˣ,…,⅟1⁺ᵐˣ⟩ ⇇ ⅟ℕₓ)
    |⅟k⁺ᵐˣ,…,⅟1⁺ᵐˣ| = |k| ≠ |⅟ℕₓ|
    thus
    |⅟ℕₓ| ∉ ℕᶠⁿᵒʳᵈ:
    ¬¬(⅟ℕₓ ⇇ ⅟ℕₓu{Bob})
    ⅟ℕₓ ⇇ ⅟ℕₓu{Bob}

    ∀x ∈ (0,1]: ¬(NUF(x) < ℵ₀)
    ℵ₀ = |ℕᶠⁿᵒʳᵈ|

    ----
    Only a first unit fraction can agree with [WM]

    Fixed it. You're welcome.

    You are unable to interpret [WM] correctly.

    Fixed it again.

    There is more to being a doctor than
    a willingness to say one is a doctor.
    There is more to being math than
    a willingness to say it is math.

    Never mind.
    There are many dyslogical matheologians like you.

    What is your explanation for
    the rest of the world being out of step with you?

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Fri Feb 2 12:24:52 2024
    Le 01/02/2024 à 13:36, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/1/24 4:46 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 31/01/2024 à 13:42, Richard Damon a écrit :

    Even if your idea was right and that there was a first that was dark,
    you couldn't count them, as counting is an individual action, so you
    can't count "dark numbers".

    I don't count but if all unit fractions exist, then the fuction exists
    too.


    Your logic just can't handle the potential infinities of "Dense" systems.

    The unit fractions are not dense - nowhere. My logic is maths:

    An infinite set does not contain a *visible* last element. But if infinity
    is complete, then there are all unit fractions 1/n in the interval (0, 1].
    They all have distances by simplest mathematics:
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) > 0. (*)
    The function Number of Unit Fractions between 0 and x, NUF(x), is counting them.
    NUF(0) = 0, NUF(x > 0) > 0. (**)
    NUF(x>0) cannot start with infinity. (Infinitely many unit fractions with "uncountably" many points between them do not fit into one point.)

    Since you refuse to state your axioms,

    This is it: ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) > 0.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Fri Feb 2 12:20:25 2024
    Le 01/02/2024 à 21:52, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 2/1/2024 4:39 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 31/01/2024 à 19:48, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 1/31/2024 2:57 AM, WM wrote:

    Only a first unit fraction can agree with [WM]

    Fixed it. You're welcome.

    NUF(0) = 0,
    NUF (x>0) > 0

    ∃ 1/n (0, 1]: ~∃ 1/m < 1/n.

    | Assume ∃⅟n ∈ (0,1]: ¬∃ ⅟m < ⅟n
    |
    | ∃n ∈ ℕ: n⋅⅟n = 1
    | ¬∃m ∈ ℕ: m⋅⅟m = 1 ∧ ⅟m < ⅟n
    |
    | However,
    | ∃m ∈ ℕ: m = n+1

    Not for dark numbers.
    An infinite set does not contain a *visible* last element. But if infinity
    is complete, then there are all unit fractions 1/n in the interval (0, 1].
    They all have distances by simplest mathematics:
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) > 0. (*)
    The function Number of Unit Fractions between 0 and x, NUF(x), is counting them.
    NUF(0) = 0, NUF(x > 0) > 0. (**)
    NUF(x>0) cannot start with infinity. (Infinitely many unit fractions with "uncountably" many points between them do not fit into one point.)
    Please try to forget all you have learned about infinity. Simply adhere to mathematics.

    Therefore,
    no unit.fraction x is
    below all unit.fractions.

    Contradicted above. Only in the visible natural numbers every n is
    followed by n+1.
    Actual infinity means that an end is invisible. But by the unit fractions
    we recognize that they end before zero because zero is visible.

    This is the only solution I can imagine. You can only parrot your "proofs" which are in contradiction with maths (*).

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Fri Feb 2 09:33:34 2024
    On 2/2/24 7:24 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 01/02/2024 à 13:36, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/1/24 4:46 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 31/01/2024 à 13:42, Richard Damon a écrit :

    Even if your idea was right and that there was a first that was dark,
    you couldn't count them, as counting is an individual action, so you
    can't count "dark numbers".

    I don't count but if all unit fractions exist, then the fuction exists too.

    But if you can't count them, then there is no requirement that it have
    the value 1 at any of them.

    It can just start at infinity.



    Your logic just can't handle the potential infinities of "Dense" systems.

    The unit fractions are not dense - nowhere. My logic is maths:

    An infinite set does not contain a *visible* last element. But if
    infinity is complete, then there are all unit fractions 1/n in the
    interval (0, 1]. They all have distances by simplest mathematics:
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) > 0. (*)
    The function Number of Unit Fractions between 0 and x, NUF(x), is
    counting them.
    NUF(0) = 0, NUF(x > 0) > 0. (**)
    NUF(x>0) cannot start with infinity. (Infinitely many unit fractions
    with "uncountably" many points between them do not fit into one point.)

    You have already admitted that you logic is incompatible with Natural
    Numbers, so you logic is just broken here too.

    Your logic says that in any set with distinct numbers, there is a lowest
    and higher elements that are members of that set.

    The Construction Definition of Natural Numbers is that for every Natural Number, there is another Natural Number past it.

    These both can not be true at the same time, so you can't have Natural
    Numbers in your system, and thus also not Rationals or Reals, or
    anything derived from them. (or you are admitting your system is just
    based on inconsistent logic and thus exploded)

    You can't try to weasle out by only talking about the unit fractions, as
    simple math and definitions shows that the existence of a smallest Unit Fraction means also a claim of a Highest Natural Number.


    Since you refuse to state your axioms,

    This is it: ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) > 0.


    Which doesn't prove what you need.

    In fact, it proves the opposite

    It shows that at ANY point, 1/n, the distance between this point and the
    next one will be less than that distance we are from the origin, and
    thus there is always room for more.

    Regards, WM




    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Fri Feb 2 13:14:21 2024
    On 2/2/2024 7:20 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 01/02/2024 à 21:52, Jim Burns a écrit :

    [...]

    An infinite set does not contain
    a *visible* last element.
    But if infinity is complete,
    then there are all unit fractions 1/n in
    the interval (0, 1].

    Define
    a final ordinal k to be the last of that cardinality.
    k with one other inserted not.fits k
    final k ⟺
    ¬(⟨1,…,k⟩ ⇇ ⟨1,…,k⟩∪{Bob})

    ℕᶠⁱⁿᵃˡ is the set of final ordinals
    k ∈ ℕᶠⁱⁿᵃˡ ⟺
    ¬(⟨1,…,k⟩ ⇇ ⟨1,…,k⟩∪{Bob})

    For each set S such that
    S with one other inserted not.fits S
    exists final ordinal k which S fits
    ¬(S ⇇ S∪{Bob}) ⟹ ∃k ∈ ℕᶠⁱⁿᵃˡ: ⟨1,…,k⟩ ⇇ S

    The successor of final ordinal k is
    final ordinal k⁺¹
    ¬(⟨1,…,k⟩ ⇇ ⟨1,…,k⟩∪{Bob}) ⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯
    ¬(⟨1,…,k,k⁺¹⟩ ⇇ ⟨1,…,k,k⁺¹⟩∪{Bob})
    [1]

    Each final ordinal and its successor
    fits in ℕᶠⁱⁿᵃˡ
    ¬(⟨1,…,k⟩ ⇇ ⟨1,…,k⟩∪{Bob}) ⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯
    ℕᶠⁱⁿᵃˡ ⇇ ⟨1,…,k⟩
    ℕᶠⁱⁿᵃˡ ⇇ ⟨1,…,k,k⁺¹⟩

    ℕᶠⁱⁿᵃˡ not.fits each final ordinal.
    ¬(⟨1,…,k⟩ ⇇ ⟨1,…,k⟩∪{Bob}) ⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯
    ¬(⟨1,…,k⟩ ⇇ ℕᶠⁱⁿᵃˡ)
    [2]

    ¬∃k ∈ ℕᶠⁱⁿᵃˡ: ⟨1,…,k⟩ ⇇ ℕᶠⁱⁿᵃˡ ℕᶠⁱⁿᵃˡ is not a set such that
    ℕᶠⁱⁿᵃˡ with one other inserted not.fits ℕᶠⁱⁿᵃˡ ¬¬(ℕᶠⁱⁿᵃˡ ⇇ ℕᶠⁱⁿᵃˡ∪{Bob})

    Instead,
    ℕᶠⁱⁿᵃˡ with one other inserted fits ℕᶠⁱⁿᵃˡ ℕᶠⁱⁿᵃˡ ⇇ ℕᶠⁱⁿᵃˡ∪{Bob}

    An infinite set does not contain
    a *visible* last element.
    But if infinity is complete,
    then there are all unit fractions 1/n in
    the interval (0, 1].

    Each final ordinal fits an infinite set S

    Because each final ordinal fits S
    S not.fits each final ordinal,
    and
    S is not a set such that
    S with one other inserted not.fits S

    Because each final ordinal fits S
    S _is_ a set such that
    S with one other inserted _fits_ S
    and
    S is your incompleteᵂᴹ

    Each final ordinal fits S
    and,
    for any set T
    each final ordinal fits S∪T
    S∪T with one other inserted fits S∪T
    and
    S∪T is your incompleteᵂᴹ

    Your completeᵂᴹ infinity not.exists.

    ----
    [1]
    The successor of final ordinal k is
    final ordinal k⁺¹
    ¬(⟨1,…,k⟩ ⇇ ⟨1,…,k⟩∪{Bob}) ⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯
    ¬(⟨1,…,k,k⁺¹⟩ ⇇ ⟨1,…,k,k⁺¹⟩∪{Bob})

    | Assume otherwise.
    | Assume
    | ¬(⟨1,…,k⟩ ⇇ ⟨1,…,k⟩∪{Bob})
    | ⟨1,…,k,k⁺¹⟩ ⇇ ⟨1,…,k,k⁺¹⟩∪{Bob}
    |
    | g: ⟨1,…,k,k⁺¹⟩∪{Bob} ⇉ ⟨1,…,k,k⁺¹⟩
    | Define
    | if g(j) ≠ k⁺¹
    | then f(j) = g(j)
    | else f(j) = g(k⁺¹)
    | f: ⟨1,…,k⟩∪{Bob} ⇉ ⟨1,…,k⟩
    |
    | However,
    | ¬(⟨1,…,k⟩ ⇇ ⟨1,…,k⟩∪{Bob})
    | Contradiction.

    ----
    [2]
    ℕᶠⁿᵒʳᵈ not.fits each final ordinal.
    ¬(⟨1,…,k⟩ ⇇ ⟨1,…,k⟩∪{Bob}) ⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯⎯
    ¬(⟨1,…,k⟩ ⇇ ℕᶠⁿᵒʳᵈ)

    | Assume otherwise.
    | Assume ⟨1,…,k⟩ ⇇ ℕᶠⁿᵒʳᵈ
    | ¬(⟨1,…,k⟩ ⇇ ⟨1,…,k⟩∪{Bob})
    |
    | However,
    | ℕᶠⁿᵒʳᵈ ⇇ ⟨1,…,k,k⁺¹⟩
    |
    | ⟨1,…,k,k⁺¹⟩ ⇇ ⟨1,…,k⟩∪{Bob}
    | ℕᶠⁿᵒʳᵈ ⇇ ⟨1,…,k,k⁺¹⟩
    | ⟨1,…,k⟩ ⇇ ℕᶠⁿᵒʳᵈ
    |
    | ⟨1,…,k⟩ ⇇ ⟨1,…,k⟩∪{Bob}
    | However,
    | ¬(⟨1,…,k⟩ ⇇ ⟨1,…,k⟩∪{Bob})
    | Contradiction.

    ----
    NUF(0) = 0,
    NUF (x>0) > 0

    ∃ 1/n (0, 1]: ~∃ 1/m < 1/n.

    | Assume ∃⅟n ∈ (0,1]: ¬∃ ⅟m < ⅟n
    |
    | ∃n ∈ ℕ: n⋅⅟n = 1
    | ¬∃m ∈ ℕ: m⋅⅟m = 1 ∧ ⅟m < ⅟n
    |
    | However,
    | ∃m ∈ ℕ: m = n+1

    Not for dark numbers.

    More generally,
    no positive.point x is
    below all unit.fractions.
    ¬∃x ∈ (0,1]: ¬∃ ⅟m < x

    | Assume otherwise.
    | Assume δ ∈ (0,1]: ¬∃⅟m < δ
    |
    | 0 < δ ∈ {x| ¬∃⅟m < x}
    | {x| ¬∃⅟m < x} is non.empty and bounded.
    | β is the least upper bound of {x| ¬∃⅟m < x}
    |
    | 0 < δ ≤ β
    | 0 < β/2 < β < 2β
    |
    | β < 2β ∉ {x| ¬∃⅟m < x}
    | ∃⅟m < 2β: m ∈ ℕ
    | ⅟m₂ᵦ < 2β ∧ m₂ᵦ ∈ ℕ
    | Thus,
    | ⅟(4m₂ᵦ) < β/2 ∧ 4m₂ᵦ ∈ ℕ
    |
    | However
    | β > β/2 ∈ {x| ¬∃ ⅟m < x}
    | ¬∃ ⅟m < β/2
    | ¬(⅟(4m₂ᵦ) < β/2)
    | Contradiction.

    Therefore,
    no positive point x is
    below all unit.fractions.
    ¬∃x ∈ (0,1]: ¬∃ ⅟m < x

    ----
    They all have distances by simplest mathematics:
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) > 0. (*)

    They all have all final ordinals:
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: ∀k ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+k) > 0.

    They all aren't final ordinals.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Fritz Feldhase on Sat Feb 3 11:03:29 2024
    Fritz Feldhase schrieb am Freitag, 2. Februar 2024 um 14:04:55 UTC+1:
    On Friday, February 2, 2024 at 1:20:35 PM UTC+1, WM wrote:

    forget all you have learned about infinity.
    Seems to work for you.

    The problem is: YOU are no Bolzano, Cantor, Dedekind or Frege.

    Did they see this problem?

    NUF(0) = 0,
    NUF (x>0) > 0
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) > 0
    ∃ 1/n (0, 1]: ~∃ 1/m < 1/n.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Sat Feb 3 11:00:23 2024
    Le 02/02/2024 à 19:14, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 2/2/2024 7:20 AM, WM wrote:

    | However
    | β > β/2
    | Contradiction.

    Not for all β. Otherwise there is another contradiction involving unit fractions.

    They all have distances by simplest mathematics:
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) > 0. (*)

    They all have all final ordinals:
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: ∀k ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+k) > 0.

    They all aren't final ordinals.

    Your elaborate wrintings have not yet explained this:

    NUF(0) = 0,
    NUF (x>0) > 0
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) > 0
    ∃ 1/n (0, 1]: ~∃ 1/m < 1/n.

    Try it.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Sat Feb 3 11:09:06 2024
    Le 02/02/2024 à 15:33, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/2/24 7:24 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 01/02/2024 à 13:36, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/1/24 4:46 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 31/01/2024 à 13:42, Richard Damon a écrit :

    Even if your idea was right and that there was a first that was dark,
    you couldn't count them, as counting is an individual action, so you
    can't count "dark numbers".

    I don't count but if all unit fractions exist, then the fuction exists too.

    But if you can't count them, then there is no requirement that it have
    the value 1 at any of them.

    It can just start at infinity.

    No. Then ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) > 0 would be violated.

    Your logic just can't handle the potential infinities of "Dense" systems. >>
    The unit fractions are not dense - nowhere. My logic is maths:

    An infinite set does not contain a *visible* last element. But if
    infinity is complete, then there are all unit fractions 1/n in the
    interval (0, 1]. They all have distances by simplest mathematics:
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) > 0. (*)
    The function Number of Unit Fractions between 0 and x, NUF(x), is
    counting them.
    NUF(0) = 0, NUF(x > 0) > 0. (**)
    NUF(x>0) cannot start with infinity. (Infinitely many unit fractions
    with "uncountably" many points between them do not fit into one point.)

    You have already admitted that you logic is incompatible with Natural Numbers,

    No, it is fundamental for all of mathematics.

    Your logic says that in any set with distinct numbers, there is a lowest
    and higher elements that are members of that set.

    The Construction Definition of Natural Numbers is that for every Natural Number, there is another Natural Number past it.

    That is true for visible numbers only.

    These both can not be true at the same time,

    Therefore it is true for visible numbers only.

    Since you refuse to state your axioms,

    This is it: ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) > 0.


    Which doesn't prove what you need.

    It disproves more than one unit fraction at one point. It is just proving
    that your above proposal is wrong.

    In fact, it proves the opposite

    It shows that at ANY point, 1/n, the distance between this point and the
    next one will be less than that distance we are from the origin, and
    thus there is always room for more.

    That would require that your proposal is right. But it is wrong.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Sat Feb 3 06:51:42 2024
    On 2/3/24 6:09 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 02/02/2024 à 15:33, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/2/24 7:24 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 01/02/2024 à 13:36, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/1/24 4:46 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 31/01/2024 à 13:42, Richard Damon a écrit :

    Even if your idea was right and that there was a first that was
    dark, you couldn't count them, as counting is an individual action,
    so you can't count "dark numbers".

    I don't count but if all unit fractions exist, then the fuction
    exists too.

    But if you can't count them, then there is no requirement that it have
    the value 1 at any of them.

    It can just start at infinity.

    No. Then ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) > 0 would be violated.

    Your logic just can't handle the potential infinities of "Dense"
    systems.

    The unit fractions are not dense - nowhere. My logic is maths:

    An infinite set does not contain a *visible* last element. But if
    infinity is complete, then there are all unit fractions 1/n in the
    interval (0, 1]. They all have distances by simplest mathematics:
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) > 0. (*)
    The function Number of Unit Fractions between 0 and x, NUF(x), is
    counting them.
    NUF(0) = 0, NUF(x > 0) > 0. (**)
    NUF(x>0) cannot start with infinity. (Infinitely many unit fractions
    with "uncountably" many points between them do not fit into one point.)

    You have already admitted that you logic is incompatible with Natural
    Numbers,

    No, it is fundamental for all of mathematics.

    Nope.

    NOTHING in basic mathematics says that any set of numbers (including
    unbounded sets) must have a highest and lowest element.

    IN fact, your statement ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) > 0 also proves there can not be a smallest visible 1/m, as we can, by simple math transform it to:

    ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n > 1/(n+1).

    And since the DEFINITION of Natural Numbers says that for all Natural
    Numbers, if n exists, so does n+1 (which would also be true for your
    "Visible numbers" if not, what visible number doesn't have a successor,
    since it is visible, it is individually namable).

    Thus, for any 1/n claimed to be the smallest visible, that statement it
    proven false, so there is no smallest (visible) unit fraction.

    Your NUF(x) is built on shifting sands.


    Your logic says that in any set with distinct numbers, there is a
    lowest and higher elements that are members of that set.

    The Construction Definition of Natural Numbers is that for every
    Natural Number, there is another Natural Number past it.

    That is true for visible numbers only.

    Natural Numbers, BY THEIR DEFINITION are what you call "Visible" numbers.

    Where do you get otherwise?


    These both can not be true at the same time,

    Therefore it is true for visible numbers only.

    No, it says your logic is BROKEN.

    Your "Darkness" is just you closing your eyes to the Truth.


    Since you refuse to state your axioms,

    This is it: ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) > 0.


    Which doesn't prove what you need.

    It disproves more than one unit fraction at one point. It is just
    proving that your above proposal is wrong.

    And I never said more that one unit fraction at one point. I just point
    out that there isn't a "first" point to an open interval with an
    unbounded set.


    In fact, it proves the opposite

    It shows that at ANY point, 1/n, the distance between this point and
    the next one will be less than that distance we are from the origin,
    and thus there is always room for more.

    That would require that your proposal is right. But it is wrong.

    No, it shows that you are just wrong because you are intentionally
    ignoring the Truth. You seem to like the "darkness" too much, that you
    refuse to come into the light.


    Regards, WM


    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Sat Feb 3 14:11:52 2024
    On 2/3/2024 6:00 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 02/02/2024 à 19:14, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 2/2/2024 7:20 AM, WM wrote:

    They all have distances by simplest mathematics:
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) > 0. (*)

    They all have all final ordinals:
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: ∀k ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+k) > 0.
    They all aren't final ordinals.

    Your elaborate wrintings have not yet
    explained this:

    NUF(0) = 0,
    NUF (x>0) > 0
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) > 0
    ∃ 1/n (0, 1]: ~∃ 1/m < 1/n.

    The explanation is that you made a mistake.

    ∀n ∈ ℕ: ⅟n - ⅟(n+1) > 0

    ∀n ∈ ℕ: ⅟(n+1) < ⅟n

    ∀n ∈ ℕ: ∃m ∈ ℕ: ⅟m < ⅟n

    ¬∃n ∈ ℕ: ¬∃m ∈ ℕ: ⅟m < ⅟n


    You (WM) don't like to elaborate on
    your mistakes, only to repeat them,
    so I'll settle for a working hypothesis
    on _why_ you deny arithmetic.

    There are four ways to interchange quantifiers,
    ∀x∀y:P ∃x∃y:P ∃x∀y:P ∀x∃y:P
    All but one way is valid (not.first.false)
    ∀x∀y:P⊢∀y∀x:P ∃x∃y:P⊢∃y∃x:P ∃x∀y:P⊢∀y∃x:P
    You (WM) use the one invalid way as though it's valid.
    ∀x∃y:P⊬∃y∀x:P

    The reason we use only the three valid interchanges
    is in order to be able to say
    about each of our claims
    | We know that
    | the later claim can only be false if
    | the earlier claim is false.

    That breaks down if we use the interchange which
    can be false without the earlier claim being false.

    In order to show that ∀x∃y:P⊬∃y∀x:P
    that is, we _can't_ justify a claim that way,
    it is enough to give a counter.example,
    any one example of P such that
    ∀x∃y:P ∧ ¬∃y∀x:P

    You have been given counter.examples again and again.
    And yet, you continue to use ☠ ∀x∃y:P⊢∃y∀x:P ☠

    My hypothesis for your behavior is Ex Falso Quodlibet.
    Counter.examples give contradictions give
    whatever your (WM's) intuition tells you,
    by Ex Falso Quodlibet.
    It also gives a denial of your intuition,
    but you just call that part matheology and move on.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Sat Feb 3 15:10:39 2024
    On 2/3/2024 12:29 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On 01/24/2024 12:17 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On Wednesday, January 24, 2024
    at 11:56:30 AM UTC-8, Jim Burns wrote:

    [...]

    If you can't split a line into points,
    and can't draw points into a line,
    what makes you think that axiomatizing
    the gaplessness of the complete ordered field
    is a good idea?
    Or is it just wishful thinking,
    of the contradictory sort?

    For a bounded non.empty set S of
    edgeless.foresplits of ℚ
    its union ⋃S
    is an edgeless.foresplit of ℚ and
    contains (⊇) each edgeless foresplit in S and
    is contained by (⊆) each edgeless.foresplit which
    contains (⊇) each edgeless.foresplit in S

    In short, ⋃S is the least upper bound of S
    The existence of least upper bound ⋃S follows
    the existence of set union ⋃S

    In every other way, too, the edgeless.foresplits of ℚ
    is the complete ordered field.

    Because the edgeless.foresplits of ℚ exist,
    the gaplessness of the complete ordered field
    is not of the contradictory sort.

    The Least Upper Bound property of
    the standard complete ordered field,
    is a non-logical/proper axiom.

    The least upper bound property is
    a theorem of the edgeless.foresplits of ℚ

    It sort of works out better that line-reals and
    signal-reals have field-reals in the middle.

    Lots better.

    Elaborate.

    See also Jordan measure and Dirichlet problem,
    line-reals and signal-reals.

    "Reke thine own rede." -- Virgil

    I hae recked ma own rede, for a' that.

    Let's see, where were we, ....

    You were just about to start elaborating.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Sat Feb 3 16:10:34 2024
    On 2/3/2024 6:00 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 02/02/2024 à 19:14, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 2/2/2024 7:20 AM, WM wrote:

    | However
    | β > β/2
    | Contradiction.

    | However
    | β > β/2 ∈ {x| ¬∃ ⅟m < x}
    | ¬∃ ⅟m < β/2
    | ¬(⅟(4m₂ᵦ) < β/2)
    | Contradiction.

    Not for all β.

    If ∃δ: ¬∃⅟m < δ > 0
    then
    β := lub{x| ¬∃⅟m < x} exists
    and
    0 < δ ≤ β
    0 < β/2 < β < 2β

    β/2 is lower than the least upper bound β
    β/2 isn't an upper bound
    Some point γ exists: β/2 < γ ∧ ¬∃⅟m < γ
    Also, because
    ∃⅟m < β/2 < γ
    if true, would contradict
    ¬∃⅟m < γ,
    ¬∃⅟m < β/2

    2β is higher than the least upper bound β
    2β isn't in {x| ¬∃⅟m < x}
    ∃⅟m < 2β

    ∃δ: ¬∃⅟m < δ > 0
    ---------------------
    ¬∃⅟m < β/2
    ∃⅟m < 2β

    However,
    for each unit.fraction ⅟m < 2β
    exists unit.fraction ⅟(4⋅m) < β/2
    Contradiction.

    Therefore,
    ¬∃δ: ¬∃⅟m < δ > 0

    Otherwise
    there is another contradiction involving
    unit fractions.

    Elaborate.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Sun Feb 4 08:35:51 2024
    Le 03/02/2024 à 12:51, Richard Damon a écrit :

    And I never said more that one unit fraction at one point. I just point
    out that there isn't a "first" point to an open interval with an
    unbounded set.

    Either there is a first one or a first many after 0.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Sun Feb 4 08:47:14 2024
    Le 03/02/2024 à 20:11, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 2/3/2024 6:00 AM, WM wrote:

    Your elaborate wrintings have not yet
    explained this:

    NUF(0) = 0,
    NUF (x>0) > 0
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) > 0
    ∃ 1/n (0, 1]: ~∃ 1/m < 1/n.

    The explanation is that you made a mistake.

    ∀n ∈ ℕ: ⅟n - ⅟(n+1) > 0

    ∀n ∈ ℕ: ⅟(n+1) < ⅟n

    ∀n ∈ ℕ: ∃m ∈ ℕ: ⅟m < ⅟n

    ¬∃n ∈ ℕ: ¬∃m ∈ ℕ: ⅟m < ⅟n

    That does not explain how NUF can increase from 0 to more without passing
    1.

    There are four ways to interchange quantifiers,

    Geometric points are there or are not there, independent of teh question
    or quantifier interchange.

    The reason we use only the three valid interchanges

    There are no interchanges. Either NUF increases in one point to 1 or to
    more. The latter is excluded by
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: ⅟n - ⅟(n+1) > 0. No quantifier interchange is used.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Sun Feb 4 08:49:53 2024
    Le 03/02/2024 à 22:10, Jim Burns a écrit :

    Otherwise
    there is another contradiction involving
    unit fractions.

    Elaborate.

    NUF would start with more than 1 at some point. That is excluded by ∀n
    ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) > 0.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Fritz Feldhase on Sun Feb 4 09:53:25 2024
    Fritz Feldhase schrieb am Samstag, 3. Februar 2024 um 21:20:16 UTC+1:
    On Saturday, February 3, 2024 at 12:00:31 PM UTC+1, WM wrote:

    Your elaborate wrintings have not yet explained this:

    NUF(0) = 0,
    NUF(x) = aleph_0 for all x ∈ IR, x > 0.
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) > 0
    ∃ 1/n ∈ (0, 1]: ~∃ 1/m < 1/n.

    Richtig ist nämlich: ¬∃n ∈ ℕ: ¬∃m ∈ ℕ: ⅟m < ⅟n

    bzw. ∀n ∈ ℕ: ∃m ∈ ℕ: ⅟m < ⅟n. (*)

    Der Beweis für (*) ist einfach.

    Der Beweis geht von Peano aus und ist bekannt. Er beantwortet aber nicht
    die gestellte Frage. Wie kann NUF von 0 auf mehr steigen, ohne ∀n ∈
    ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) > 0 zu verletzen und 1 zu passieren?

    Gruß WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Sun Feb 4 07:48:09 2024
    On 2/4/24 3:35 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 03/02/2024 à 12:51, Richard Damon a écrit :

    And I never said more that one unit fraction at one point. I just
    point out that there isn't a "first" point to an open interval with an
    unbounded set.

    Either there is a first one or a first many after 0.

    Regards, WM

    Why?

    WHy do you think there must be an "end" in that direction?


    What is the last number added in the sequence:

    1 + 1/2 + 1/4 + 1/8 + 1/16 + ... + 1/(2^n) + ...


    There doesn't NEED to be an end to a sequence, that is the power of
    infinity.

    "Infinitity" may not be a "Number" but it is a concept in Finite
    Mathematics that explains a lot.

    Not understanding it breaks your logic.

    You have so ingreained into your mind how you WANT things to work, that
    you just refuse to look at things that make you wrong.

    That doesn't make them not exist, just shows your utter ignorance of
    what you are talking about.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Sun Feb 4 14:22:33 2024
    On 2/4/2024 12:59 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On 02/03/2024 12:10 PM, Jim Burns wrote:

    [...]

    About the union of a set of edgeless.foresplits
    ...of ℚ...
    being in the set of edgeless.foresplits,
    ...of ℚ...

    Being in the set is a theorem.

    then that would entail that
    the least, of the upper bounds, is for first:
    making that so in a theory with
    only rational numbers,

    The edgeless.foresplits of ℚ are in a theory with
    _sets_ of rational numbers.

    This answers at least one of your objections,
    since there are more sets of rationals than rationals.

    to illustrate that the rationals
    do contain their completion this way.

    Their power set 𝒫(ℚ) contains the completion of ℚ

    𝒫(ℚ) ⊇ {F ⊆ ℚ| F ᣔ<ᘁ F ᣔ<ᣔ ℚ\F}\{∅,ℚ}
    which is the set of nontrivial edgeless.foresplits of ℚ
    which is the complete ordered field,
    unique up to isomorphism.

    Of course, one might aver you would say
    [...]
    so I must be talking about
    edgeless.foresplits in R already,
    the complete ordered field".

    No, I wouldn't say that.
    Nontrivial edgeless.foresplits of ℚ model ℝ

    My claim is not the least bit controversial.
    It's a construction of ℝ that goes back
    at least to Dedekind, I think.

    The "edgeless.foresplit" is still only
    a "partition".

    For each subset F ⊆ ℚ
    each element p ∈ ℚ is in
    exactly one of F and ℚ\F

    That makes each {F,ℚ\F} a partition of ℚ

    No,
    I would not say that {F ⊆ ℚ} models ℝ
    {F ⊆ ℚ| F ᣔ<ᘁ F ᣔ<ᣔ ℚ\F}\{∅,ℚ} models ℝ

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Sun Feb 4 14:23:13 2024
    On 2/4/2024 3:47 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 03/02/2024 à 20:11, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 2/3/2024 6:00 AM, WM wrote:

    Your elaborate wrintings have not yet
    explained this:
    NUF(0) = 0,
    NUF (x>0) > 0
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) > 0
    ∃ 1/n (0, 1]: ~∃ 1/m < 1/n.

    The explanation is that you made a mistake.
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: ⅟n - ⅟(n+1) > 0
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: ⅟(n+1) < ⅟n
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: ∃m ∈ ℕ: ⅟m < ⅟n
    ¬∃n ∈ ℕ: ¬∃m ∈ ℕ: ⅟m < ⅟n

    That does not explain how
    NUF can increase from 0 to more
    without passing 1.

    Because each unit fraction is preceded,
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: ∃m ∈ ℕ: ⅟m < ⅟n
    no unit fraction is not.preceded.
    ¬∃n ∈ ℕ: ¬∃m ∈ ℕ: ⅟m < ⅟n

    The assumption that
    there is a not.preceded (first) unit.fraction
    is a mistake.

    The answer to the question
    | How can we, as finite beings, _count_
    | unit.fractions from 0 to ⅟137?
    is
    | We, as finite beings, _can't_ count
    | unit.fractions from 0 to ⅟137.
    | To claim that we, as finite beings, can
    | is a mistake.

    What we, as finite beings, _can_ do --
    what we, as finite beings, _do_ -- is
    say a thing true about each
    unit.fraction between 0 and ⅟136
    and
    say another thing not.first.false about each
    unit.fraction between 0 and ⅟136.

    One of the things we say not.first.false.ly
    about each unit.fraction between 0 and ⅟136
    is that this unit.fraction (whichever) is preceded.

    To clarify, there are two orders in use:
    the order of unit fractions, and
    the order of claims about unit fractions.
    There is a first claim.
    There isn't a first unit.fraction.

    There are four ways to interchange quantifiers,

    Geometric points are there or are not there,
    independent of teh question or quantifier interchange.

    For some quantifier interchanges,
    we know by _looking at claims_
    that the interchanged claim is not.first.false.

    An interchanged claim which
    we can see to be a not.first.false claim
    we will know by
    justifying the preceding un.interchanged claim
    to be a justified claim.

    However,
    an interchanged claim which
    we _can't_ see to be a not.first.false claim
    we _won't_ know by
    justifying the preceding un.interchanged claim
    to be a justified claim.

    The reason we use only the three valid interchanges

    There are no interchanges.
    Either NUF increases in one point to 1
    or to more.
    The latter is excluded by
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: ⅟n - ⅟(n+1) > 0.

    Elaborate.

    No quantifier interchange is used.

    Okay.
    Elaborate without using a quantifier exchange.
    But elaborate.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Sun Feb 4 17:46:37 2024
    On 2/4/2024 2:44 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On 02/04/2024 11:22 AM, Jim Burns wrote:

    [...]

    Consider only partitions of rationals,

    I would prefer to consider only
    non.trivial edgeless.foresplits of the rationals,
    {F ⊆ ℚ| F ᣔ<ᘁ F ᣔ<ᣔ ℚ\F}\{∅,ℚ}
    which is what I am claiming is a model of the reals.

    The first important difference I see
    is that
    non.trivial edgeless.foresplits of the rationals
    are totally.ordered by '⊆' and
    partitions.more.generally of the rationals
    {F,H}: F∩H = ∅ ∧ F∪H = ℚ
    aren't.

    If you intend to prove that
    _partitions_ of ℚ don't model ℝ
    then I wish you all the best in your endeavor,
    but that's not my claim.

    Consider only partitions of rationals,
    because of
    the density of the rationals in the reals, and,
    the fact that the rationals are
    not gapless/complete/having-LUB,
    establishing for a given element that
    a given partition has a lesser and a greater side,

    That is not established for partitions.
    However, that is established for
    non.trivial edgeless.foresplits of the rationals
    and their complement.

    each lesser lesser than each greater and vice-versa,
    these partitions must be as by

    "must be as by" == ?

    these partitions must be as by
    the complete ordered field or R itself already.

    I'm not sure how to regard "already" in this context.

    It is true that
    non.trivial edgeless.foresplits of the rationals
    "already" model ℝ
    in that they are not time.bound.
    They have always, do now, and will always model ℝ
    Thus, they "already" model ℝ

    It is false that
    ℝ existing is a prerequisite to
    non.trivial edgeless.foresplits of the rationals
    existing.

    ℚ yes
    𝒫(ℚ)yes
    {F ⊆ ℚ| F ᣔ<ᘁ F ᣔ<ᣔ ℚ\F}\{∅,ℚ} yes
    ℝ no

    I understand that you wouldn't say that,
    because,
    the rationals are looking HUGE, but,
    it seems ignorant,
    then once informed, it seems hypocritical.

    | I beseech you, in the bowels of Christ,
    | think it possible that you may be mistaken.
    |
    -- Oliver Cromwell.

    However huge the rationals are,
    the sets of rationals are provably huger.

    It is _sets of rationals_ and not rationals
    which are the "points" in
    what is provably a model of ℝ

    A model might not hold
    what you think it should hold.
    However, if it satisfies the axioms,
    it is a model.

    So, how to arrive at this
    when the rationals are everywhere dense, in the reals,
    but nowhere gapless, in the reals,
    so clearly don't have least-upper-bound property,

    It is selected sets of rationals, not rationals,
    which have the least.upper.bound.property.
    A non.trivial edgeless.foresplit of the rationals
    is a set of rationals, not a rational.

    I'll agree that
    sets of rationals _have_ a least upper bound,
    then immediately demonstrate that's because
    the complete ordered field has least upper bound,

    That isn't the least upper.bound property.

    {1,2,3,4,5,6,7,8,9} has
    the least.upper.bound property because
    each of its bounded, non.empty subsets
    has a least.upper.bound
    in {1,2,3,4,5,6,7,8,9}

    ℝ is a much more interesting example,
    but {1,2,3,4,5,6,7,8,9} is also an example.

    ℚ doesn't have the least.upper.bound property.
    {F ⊆ ℚ| F ᣔ<ᘁ F ᣔ<ᣔ ℚ\F}\{∅,ℚ} has it.

    So, let's talk about this relation:  '^<^'.

    It is an abbreviation of "foresplit"
    F ᣔ<ᣔ ℚ\F :⇔
    ∀x ∈ F: ∀y ∈ ℚ\F: x < y

    Also too, an abbreviation of "edgeless" is:
    F ᣔ<ᘁ F :⇔
    ∀x ∈ F: ∃x′ ∈ ℚ\F: x < x′

    For what it's worth,
    ᣔ is superscript AND
    ᘁ is superscript OR

    Also, you mentioned the usual, ..., understanding of that
    "the complete ordered field is unique up to isomorphism",
    then I wonder if you recalled when I wrote field operations
    as a limiting case for the interval [-1, 1], or,
    "field operations equipping the unit interval with
    being a field", and as with
    regards to how it's a bit singularly different.

    The complete ordered field satisfies
    the complete.ordered.field axioms.
    Something.a.bit.different which doesn't isn't.

    We know that
    the complete ordered field is
    unique up to isomorphism
    because,
    given two models, let us say
    the non.trivial edgeless.foresplits of ℚ
    and the partitions of Cauchy sequences of ℚ
    an isomorphism between them exists.

    _Any_ model of ℝ satisfies those axioms,
    and it is from the axioms that
    the isomorphism is proven to exist.
    Thus, unique up to isomorphism.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Mon Feb 5 08:59:00 2024
    Le 04/02/2024 à 13:48, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/4/24 3:35 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 03/02/2024 à 12:51, Richard Damon a écrit :

    And I never said more that one unit fraction at one point. I just
    point out that there isn't a "first" point to an open interval with an
    unbounded set.

    Either there is a first one or a first many after 0.

    Why?

    Because the unit fractions are really existing points, no ghosts of
    matheology.

    WHy do you think there must be an "end" in that direction?


    What is the last number added in the sequence:

    1 + 1/2 + 1/4 + 1/8 + 1/16 + ... + 1/(2^n) + ...

    It is dark. By the way an entry of ℵ unit fractions at an undefinable
    point proves the existence of ℵ dark unit fractions.

    You have so ingreained into your mind how you WANT things to work, that
    you just refuse to look at things that make you wrong.

    Try to define the ℵ unit fractions which do not enter at a definable
    point.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Mon Feb 5 09:16:08 2024
    Le 04/02/2024 à 20:23, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 2/4/2024 3:47 AM, WM wrote:

    no unit fraction is not.preceded.
    ¬∃n ∈ ℕ: ¬∃m ∈ ℕ: ⅟m < ⅟n

    Every chosen unit fraction is preceded by ℵ remaining smaller unit
    fractions.
    ℵ of them cannot be chosen. They are dark.
    Or can you choose a unit fraction without ℵ smaller ones remaining?

    There are no interchanges.
    Either NUF increases in one point to 1
    or to more.
    The latter is excluded by
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: ⅟n - ⅟(n+1) > 0.

    Elaborate.

    No quantifier interchange is used.

    Okay.
    Elaborate without using a quantifier exchange.
    But elaborate.

    Logic!

    Either NUF increases in one point to 1 or to more.
    The latter is excluded by
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: ⅟n - ⅟(n+1) > 0.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Mon Feb 5 07:51:21 2024
    On 2/5/24 3:59 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 04/02/2024 à 13:48, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/4/24 3:35 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 03/02/2024 à 12:51, Richard Damon a écrit :

    And I never said more that one unit fraction at one point. I just
    point out that there isn't a "first" point to an open interval with
    an unbounded set.

    Either there is a first one or a first many after 0.

    Why?

    Because the unit fractions are really existing points, no ghosts of matheology.

    But unit fractions ARE a product of mathematics.

    Maybe your problem is you don't beleive in actual math.


    WHy do you think there must be an "end" in that direction?


    What is the last number added in the sequence:

    1 + 1/2 + 1/4 + 1/8 + 1/16 + ... + 1/(2^n) + ...

    It is dark. By the way an entry of ℵ unit fractions at an undefinable
    point proves the existence of ℵ dark unit fractions.

    You have so ingreained into your mind how you WANT things to work,
    that you just refuse to look at things that make you wrong.

    Try to define the ℵ unit fractions which do not enter at a definable point.

    Regards, WM


    So, it seems that anything you don't understand just becomes "dark"

    It seems that things like the largest visible natural number become
    "dark", and thus darkness isn't an attribute of just the numbers we
    can't see, but numbers we can, thus all is dark (to you).

    All your "darkness" seems to be is you closing your eyes to things you
    don't like. You are just doing your version of sticking your fingers in
    your ear and going blah-blah-blah-blah I can't hear you.

    You proe your stupidity.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Mon Feb 5 14:31:56 2024
    On 2/4/2024 8:53 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On 02/04/2024 02:46 PM, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 2/4/2024 2:44 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:

    So, let's talk about this relation:  '^<^'.

    It is an abbreviation of "foresplit"
    F ᣔ<ᣔ ℚ\F  :⇔
    ∀x ∈ F: ∀y ∈ ℚ\F:  x < y

    Also too, an abbreviation of "edgeless" is:
    F ᣔ<ᘁ F  :⇔
    ∀x ∈ F: ∃x′ ∈ ℚ\F:  x < x′

    Oops. Better:
    ∀x ∈ F: ∃x′ ∈ F: x < x′

    For what it's worth,
    ᣔ is superscript AND
    ᘁ is superscript OR

    By F ᣔ<ᘁ F I intend to write
    "F doesn't hold a maximum"
    ∀x ∈ F: ∃x′ ∈ F: x < x′

    But F ᣔ<ᘁ F is unclear.
    ᣔ before ᘁ ? ᘁ before ᣔ ?

    I declare ᣔ before ᘁ
    Write F ᘁ>ᣔ F for
    ∃x′ ∈ F: ∀x ∈ F: x < x′
    (which is false)

    That <=, l.t.e. arithmetically and, you know,
    <= set-wise, subset, have that
    the sub-set relation only exists because
    l.t.e., already.

    If it's "less than, a given rational",
    or "less than, a given irrational",
    or "less than, a given real",
    those are various I'd imagine you'd agree.

    For my best guess at what you're saying,
    no, I'd disagree.

    An edgeless.foresplit F
    F ᣔ<ᘁ F ᣔ<ᣔ ℚ\F
    doesn't need some x between F,ℚ\F
    ∃?x: F ᣔ< x ≤ᣔ ℚ\F

    An edgeless.foresplit F ᣔ<ᘁ F ᣔ<ᣔ ℚ\F
    might have such an x but
    F only needs each of F to be less than
    each of its complement ℚ\F
    F ᣔ<ᣔ ℚ\F


    Consider an algorithm that calculates ℼ
    In 10 steps, it gives 3.1
    In 100 steps, it gives 3.14
    In 1000 steps, it gives 3.141
    In 10000 steps, it gives 3.1415
    In 100000 steps, it gives 3.14159
    ...

    The algorithm can't finitely calculate
    _all_ the digits of ℼ
    but it can for each digit.

    Notation:
    {<3.1} is the edgeless.foresplit with 3.1 between
    {<3.1} ᣔ< 3.1 ≤ᣔ ℚ\{<3.1}
    3.09,3.099,3.0999,... ∈ {<3.1}
    3.1 ∉ {<3.1}

    Take the initial digit.strings to represent
    edgeless.foresplits.
    In 10 steps, it gives {<3.1}
    In 100 steps, it gives {<3.14}
    In 1000 steps, it gives {<3.141}
    In 10000 steps, it gives {<3.1415}
    In 100000 steps, it gives {<3.14159}
    ...

    We, as finite beings, cannot calculate them all.

    However,
    by a fairly timid standard of what exists,
    that which can be calculated,
    each edgeless.foresplit in the sequence exists.

    It's a Cauchy sequence.

    Is it a convergent sequence?
    Does its limit exist?

    Yes, its limit exists.
    The limit is the union of
    all the edgeless.foresplits in the sequence.

    The limit _exists_
    but that's because the set union exists
    not like {<3.1}, {<3.14}, {<3.141}, ... which
    exist because they are finitely calculable.

    It is enough for a limit to _exist_
    finitely.calculable or not,
    in order to make this axiomatization of gaplessness
    of the non.contradictory variety.

    For edgeless.foresplits, that means
    it is enough for set unions to exist
    in order to make this axiomatization of gaplessness
    of the non.contradictory variety.

    But we must say goodbye to points.between.
    {<ℼ} :=
    ⋃{{<3.1}, {<3.14}, {<3.141}, ...}
    _exists_
    {<ℼ} has no edge in ℚ
    ℚ\{<ℼ} ha no edge in ℚ
    and that's all right because
    it isn't the point.between which represents ℼ
    it is {<ℼ} ⊆ ℚ

    for then it's quite
    simple to demonstrate with the illative, that, these
    would be so many distinct rationals,
    as there are, distinct partitions.

    s/partition/edgeless.foresplit/

    No, there aren't so many distinct rationals
    as there are distinct edgeless.foresplits.

    For each bounded non.empty set of edgeless.foresplits,
    there is its union, which is an edgeless.foresplit.

    However,
    there is a sequence in which
    each rational occurs with a finite index,
    and
    there _isn't_ a sequence in which
    each edgeless.foresplit occurs with a finite index.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Tue Feb 6 00:43:58 2024
    On 2/5/2024 8:05 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On 02/05/2024 11:31 AM, Jim Burns wrote:

    [...]


    My post is too much to repeat completely.
    If I knew which parts were relevant to
    your post, I would repeat those.
    But I don't.
    See upthread.

    Hey now -
    no "infinite descending epsilon chains", ....

    To the best of my knowledge, I have
    no infinite descending epsilon chains.
    Elaborate.

    One reason why the definition is
    "equivalence classes of sequences that are Cauchy",
    is that the cuts of rationals in
    various supersets, vary, and,
    the implications of their existence, vary.

    Equivalence classes of Cauchy sequences of rationals
    is not a definition of the complete ordered field.

    Equivalence classes of Cauchy sequences of rationals
    is a model of the complete ordered field.


    If
    something is a model of the complete ordered field,
    such as the non.trivial edgeless.foresplits of Q,
    and
    something _isn't_ a model of the complete ordered field,
    such as "various supersets",
    then
    something is a model of the complete ordered field,
    such as the non.trivial edgeless.foresplits of Q,
    and
    the complete.ordered.field axiomatization of
    gaplessness is not of the contradictory kind.

    So when you said
    "beyond the infinite in the sequence",

    Please refresh my memory.
    Where did I say that?

    I remember saying something that might
    be mistaken for that, but isn't that.

    The proof of uncountability of the reals
    calls for
    an endless sequence of real numbers in which
    each real number is finitely.indexed[1]

    That real.number.sequence determines
    an endless nested sequence of
    finitely.indexed[2] _intervals_ with
    endpoints with strictly increasing indexes[1]

    A real.number in the number.sequence can only be
    in all the intervals in the interval.sequence
    if it is after all infinitely-many endpoints.

    Maybe that sounds to you like
    "beyond the infinite in the sequence".

    My point there is that
    _there is no_
    "beyond the infinite in the sequence"
    Such an indexed point not.exists.

    It is a contradiction, which can be used
    to prove real numbers uncountable.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Tue Feb 6 15:18:31 2024
    On 2/5/2024 4:16 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 04/02/2024 à 20:23, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 2/4/2024 3:47 AM, WM wrote:

    no unit fraction is not.preceded.

    ¬∃n ∈ ℕ: ¬∃m ∈ ℕ: ⅟m < ⅟n

    Every chosen unit fraction is preceded by
    ℵ remaining smaller unit fractions.

    For each unit.fraction ⅟i′
    each final.ordinal k is not.a.bound of
    how many smaller unit.fractions ⅟k′
    there are.

    ∀i′: Final(i′) ⇒
    ∀k: Final(k) ⇒
    ∃ᵏ⁺¹ ⅟k′: 0 < ⅟k′ < ⅟i′ ∧

    ℵ of them cannot be chosen.

    For each unit.fraction ⅟i′
    each final.ordinal k is not.a.bound of
    how many _choosable_ smaller unit.fractions ⅟k′
    there are.

    ∀i′: Final(i′) ⇒
    ∀k: Final(k) ⇒
    ∃j: Final(j) ∧
    ∃ᵏ⁺¹ ⅟k′: 0 < ⅟k′ < ⅟i′ ∧
    ¬∃j⁺¹ ⅟j′: ⅟k′ < ⅟j′ < ⅟1

    A unit.fraction is _choosable_ if
    a final.ordinal.bound j exists of
    how many larger unit.fractions ⅟j′ there are.

    They are dark.

    ℵ₀ of them aren't dark.

    Or can you choose
    a unit fraction without
    ℵ smaller ones remaining?

    A unit.fraction ⅟i′ without
    ℵ₀ smaller unit fractions ⅟k′
    not.exists
    ¬∃i′: Final(i′) ∧
    ∃k: Final(k) ∧
    ¬∃ᵏ⁺¹ ⅟k′: 0 < ⅟k′ < ⅟i′

    because,
    for each unit.fraction ⅟i′
    each final.ordinal k is not.a.bound of
    how many smaller unit.fractions ⅟k′
    there are.
    ∀i′: Final(i′) ⇒
    ∀k: Final(k) ⇒
    ∃ᵏ⁺¹ ⅟k′: 0 < ⅟k′ < ⅟i′

    There are no interchanges.
    Either NUF increases in one point to 1
    or to more.
    The latter is excluded by
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: ⅟n - ⅟(n+1) > 0.

    Elaborate.

    No quantifier interchange is used.

    Okay.
    Elaborate without using a quantifier exchange.
    But elaborate.

    Logic!
    Either NUF increases in one point to 1 or to more.
    The latter is excluded by
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: ⅟n - ⅟(n+1) > 0.

    Elaborate why the latter is excluded by
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: ⅟n - ⅟(n+1) > 0.

    | _elaborate_ (verb)
    | 1.(transitive) Тo develop in detail or complexity.
    |
    https://en.wiktionary.org/wiki/elaborate

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Tue Feb 6 17:40:23 2024
    On 2/6/2024 4:53 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On 02/05/2024 09:43 PM, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 2/5/2024 8:05 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:

    So when you said
    "beyond the infinite in the sequence",

    Please refresh my memory.
    Where did I say that?

    It was this bit:

    However,
    by a fairly timid standard of what exists,
    that which can be calculated,
    each edgeless.foresplit in the sequence exists.

    It's a Cauchy sequence.

    Is it a convergent sequence?
    Does its limit exist?

    Yes, its limit exists.
    The limit is the union of
    all the edgeless.foresplits in the sequence.

    The limit _exists_
    but that's because the set union exists
    not like {<3.1}, {<3.14}, {<3.141}, ... which
    exist because they are finitely calculable.

    That the limit exists, if it exists,
    in the reals,

    The limit is the union of sets of rationals.
    The sequences is a sequence of sets of rationals.

    If the union exists, the limit exists.
    Thence, least.upper.bound.property.

    is _not_ negating that
    the rationals do _not_ have
    least-upper-bound property.

    I do not intend to negate that
    the rationals do not have
    the least.upper.bound.property.

    The non.trivial edgeless.foresplits of rationals
    aren't rationals.
    They are sets of rationals.

    So when you said
    "beyond the infinite in the sequence",

    So, I guess you're paraphrasing me?
    Your use of quote marks for a paraphrase
    is confusing.

    And still,
    I don't see what I wrote that could be
    paraphrased in that way.

    You do seem a bit fresher today,
    I can sort of understand why you'd look at
    the least-upper-bound appearing in the set
    you imagine the sequences are from,

    It's a theorem.
    I can give you as much detail of the proof
    as you'd like. More than you'd like, I'll bet.

    But it seems as though
    we're still talking past one another.
    I say "non.trivial edgeless.foresplits of Q"
    You say it's not conscientious (honest?) of
    me to say that about _the rationals_
    Have I misunderstood you?

    I haven't said that about the rationals.
    The non.trivial edgeless.foresplits of Q
    aren't Q

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Wed Feb 7 07:35:31 2024
    Le 06/02/2024 à 21:18, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 2/5/2024 4:16 AM, WM wrote:

    Logic!
    Either NUF increases in one point to 1 or to more.
    The latter is excluded by
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: ⅟n - ⅟(n+1) > 0.

    Elaborate why the latter is excluded by
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: ⅟n - ⅟(n+1) > 0.

    It is not. It would be excluded by
    ∀ n ∈ ℕ ∃ n+1 ∈ ℕ.

    Therefore we have the alternative choice: either
    every ordered set of points 1/n on positive the real line, having gaps of uncountably many points between each other, has a first point
    or
    for every point 1/n there exists a point 1/(n+1).
    Both together is impossible. I prefer the first.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Wed Feb 7 07:24:33 2024
    Le 05/02/2024 à 13:51, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/5/24 3:59 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 04/02/2024 à 13:48, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/4/24 3:35 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 03/02/2024 à 12:51, Richard Damon a écrit :

    And I never said more that one unit fraction at one point. I just
    point out that there isn't a "first" point to an open interval with
    an unbounded set.

    Either there is a first one or a first many after 0.

    Why?

    Because the unit fractions are really existing points, no ghosts of
    matheology.

    But unit fractions ARE a product of mathematics.

    They are even points at the real line in linear order. Hence a first
    exists.

    Try to define the ℵ unit fractions which do not enter at a definable point.

    So, it seems that anything you don't understand just becomes "dark"

    Try to define them.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Wed Feb 7 07:29:05 2024
    On 2/7/24 2:24 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 05/02/2024 à 13:51, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/5/24 3:59 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 04/02/2024 à 13:48, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/4/24 3:35 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 03/02/2024 à 12:51, Richard Damon a écrit :

    And I never said more that one unit fraction at one point. I just
    point out that there isn't a "first" point to an open interval
    with an unbounded set.

    Either there is a first one or a first many after 0.

    Why?

    Because the unit fractions are really existing points, no ghosts of
    matheology.

    But unit fractions ARE a product of mathematics.

    They are even points at the real line in linear order. Hence a first
    exists.

    Nope. Since there is no first positive rel point either, there still
    isn't a FIRST unit fraction.

    You are just PROVING that you logic system is based on inconsistent
    axioms (or whatever you want to call your base principle)

    For there to be a "first unit fraction" there needs to be a Highest
    Natural Number, but that can be BY THE DEFINIITION of the construction
    of Natural Numbers


    Try to define the ℵ unit fractions which do not enter at a definable
    point.

    So, it seems that anything you don't understand just becomes "dark"

    Try to define them.

    They are just the Natural Numbers, as defined by the metheologics you
    refuse to accept.

    That's just YOUR ignorance.

    YOU can believe the earth is flat, since otherwise people on the
    "bottom" side would just fall off, but that is just bad logic.

    Thinking there must be a smallest unit fraction, or largest Natural
    Number, when there isn't is just the same type of error.


    Regards, WM



    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Wed Feb 7 12:59:49 2024
    On 2/6/2024 11:15 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On 02/06/2024 02:40 PM, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 2/6/2024 4:53 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:

    You do seem a bit fresher today,
    I can sort of understand why you'd look at
    the least-upper-bound appearing in the set
    you imagine the sequences are from,

    It's a theorem.
    I can give you as much detail of the proof
    as you'd like. More than you'd like, I'll bet.

    But it seems as though
    we're still talking past one another.
    I say "non.trivial edgeless.foresplits of Q"
    You say it's not conscientious (honest?) of
    me to say that about _the rationals_
    Have I misunderstood you?

    I haven't said that about the rationals.
    The non.trivial edgeless.foresplits of Q
    aren't Q'

    Are they not, any one, a partition of Q?

    Exactly.
    A partition of ℚ isn't an element of ℚ

    ----
    Let's change tack.

    We start by assuming there exists
    ℝ the complete ordered field.
    Then we work our way around to
    no longer needing to assume that.

    For each point x ∈ ℝ
    there is a partition {Fᴿₓ {x} Hᴿₓ}
    Fᴿₓ = {y∈ℝ|y<x}
    Hᴿₓ = {y∈ℝ|y<x}

    There is a bijection between points and partitions.
    An order.isomorphism, in fact.
    x ⟷ {Fᴿₓ {x} Hᴿₓ}
    Moreover,
    x ⟷ Fᴿₓ
    x ⟷ {x}
    x ⟷ Hᴿₓ

    Fᴿₓ is a non.trivial edgeless.foresplit of ℝ
    Because of the isomorphism, we could choose to
    discuss non.trivial edgeless.foresplits
    instead of points. The results will be the same.

    The set {Fᴿ} of non.trivial edgeless.foresplits of ℝ
    is defined on ℝ
    but {Fᴿ} isn't the model of ℝ

    There is also the set {Fꟴ} of
    non.trivial edgeless.foresplits of ℚ
    {Fꟴ} is the model of ℝ

    {Fꟴ} can be a model of ℝ because
    there is an isomorphism between {Fꟴ} and {Fᴿ}

    For each Fᴿ ∈ {Fᴿ}
    exists Fꟴ = Fᴿ∩ℚ ∈ {Fꟴ}

    For each Fꟴ ∈ {Fꟴ}
    exists Fᴿ = {x∈ℝ| ∃p∈Fꟴ: x<p} ∈ {Fᴿ}

    That's what we want because,
    for each two points x,y in ℝ
    there is a rational p in ℚ between them.

    Fᴿ is edgeless.
    for each x ∈ Fᴿ
    exists y ∈ Fᴿ: x < y and
    exists p ∈ Fᴿ∩ℚ: x < p < y

    There are no points in Fᴿ
    which are not in {x∈ℝ| ∃p∈Fꟴ: x<p} ∈ {Fᴿ}

    Fꟴ ⟼ {x∈ℝ| ∃p∈Fꟴ: x<p}
    is the inverse of
    Fᴿ ⟼ Fᴿ∩ℚ

    {Fᴿ} ⟷ {Fꟴ}

    Also,
    ℝ ⟷ {Fᴿ}

    ℝ ⟷ {Fᴿ} ⟷ {Fꟴ}

    {Fꟴ} has all the properties which
    we require ℝ to have
    because, up to isomorphism,
    {Fꟴ} is ℝ

    However,
    we don't need to assume {Fꟴ} exists
    the way I did up.post.
    {Fꟴ} is a set of sets of rationals.

    If
    we assume or prove that
    ℚ and 𝒫(ℚ) and {S ⊆ ℚ| F(S)} exist
    F == "is an edgeless.foresplit"
    then
    {Fꟴ} exists and
    the complete.ordered.field axioms for ℝ
    are not of the contradictory kind.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Wed Feb 7 13:59:25 2024
    On 2/7/2024 2:35 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 06/02/2024 à 21:18, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 2/5/2024 4:16 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 04/02/2024 à 20:23, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 2/4/2024 3:47 AM, WM wrote:

    Either NUF increases in one point to 1
    or to more.
    The latter is excluded by
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: ⅟n - ⅟(n+1) > 0.
    No quantifier interchange is used.

    Logic!
    Either NUF increases in one point to 1 or to more.
    The latter is excluded by
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: ⅟n - ⅟(n+1) > 0.

    Elaborate why the latter is excluded by
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: ⅟n - ⅟(n+1) > 0.

    It is not.
    It would be excluded by
    ∀ n ∈ ℕ ∃ n+1 ∈ ℕ.

    Therefore we have the alternative choice:
    either
    every ordered set of points 1/n on
    positive the real line,
    having gaps of uncountably many points
    between each other,
    has a first point
    or
    for every point 1/n
    there exists a point 1/(n+1).
    Both together is impossible.
    I prefer the first.

    It is the second alternative,
    | for each ⅟n exists ⅟n⁺¹ < ⅟n
    which supports the claim that
    no unit.fraction is smallest of them,
    which in turn is supported by
    ∀ n ∈ ℕ ∃ n+1 ∈ ℕ and
    n⋅⅟n⋅⅟n⁺¹ < n⁺¹⋅⅟n⋅⅟n⁺¹

    Your argument appears to begin and end
    at "I prefer the first".

    Do you agree with my assessment?
    Or will you elaborate on
    why there is more to your argument than appears?

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Wed Feb 7 14:46:42 2024
    On 2/7/2024 8:03 AM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On 02/06/2024 08:15 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On 02/06/2024 02:40 PM, Jim Burns wrote:

    [...]


    So, put pencil to paper and draw a line and you've
    well-ordered the reals, indicated by lifting the pencil.

    What.a.well.order.is is that
    each set holds a first element
    if it's not empty.

    The line has a total standard order.
    That standard order isn't a well-order.
    For example, (0,1] doesn't hold a first.

    The standard order of the rationals
    isn't a well.order.
    However, there are other orders of them
    which are well.orders.
    Cantor's celebrated sequence is an example of
    a well.order of the rationals.

    The axiom of choice is equivalent to
    the axiom of "each set has a well.order".
    That's not the same as
    "each order is a well.order".

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Wed Feb 7 17:28:54 2024
    On 2/7/2024 3:23 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On 02/07/2024 09:59 AM, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 2/6/2024 11:15 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On 02/06/2024 02:40 PM, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 2/6/2024 4:53 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:

    You do seem a bit fresher today,
    I can sort of understand why you'd look at
    the least-upper-bound appearing in the set
    you imagine the sequences are from,

    It's a theorem.
    I can give you as much detail of the proof
    as you'd like. More than you'd like, I'll bet.

    But it seems as though
    we're still talking past one another.
    I say "non.trivial edgeless.foresplits of Q"
    You say it's not conscientious (honest?) of
    me to say that about _the rationals_
    Have I misunderstood you?

    I haven't said that about the rationals.
    The non.trivial edgeless.foresplits of Q
    aren't Q'

    Are they not, any one, a partition of Q?

    Exactly.
    A partition of ℚ isn't an element of ℚ

    the ordered field Q does not have
    the least-upper-bound property, which is
    about the most usual axiom in the non-logical part of
    descriptive set theory that is among usual models of
    reals the complete ordered field.

    ℚ doesn't model ℝ

    The non.trivial edgeless.foresplits {Fꟴ} of ℚ
    which isn't ℚ
    models ℝ

    non.trivial \{∅,ℚ}
    edgeless F ᣔ<ᘁ F
    foresplit F ᣔ<ᣔ ℚ\F
    of ℚ F ⊆ ℚ

    {Fꟴ} = {F ⊆ ℚ| F ᣔ<ᘁ F ᣔ<ᣔ ℚ\F}\{∅,ℚ}

    {Fꟴ} isn't ℚ


    Ordered by ⊆
    {Fꟴ} has the least.upper.bound property.

    Let S be a bounded non.empty subset of {Fꟴ}

    ⋃S ⊆ ℚ
    ∀F ∈ S ⊆ ℚ
    ⋃S ⊆ ℚ

    ⋃S isn't ∅
    ∃F ∈ {Fꟴ}: F ∈ S
    F ≠ ∅
    ⋃S ≠ ∅

    ⋃S isn't ℚ
    A bound β ∈ {Fꟴ} of S exists
    β ≠ ℚ
    ∃p ∈ ℚ: p ∉ β
    ∀F ∈ S: F ⊆ β
    p ∉ F ⊆ β
    p ∉ ⋃S
    ⋃S ≠ ℚ

    ⋃S is edgeless.
    ∀p ∈ US:
    ∃F ∋ p: F ∈ S ⊆ {Fꟴ}
    ∃q ∈ F: p < q
    p < q ∈ ⋃S
    ∀p ∈ ⋃S: ∃q ∈ ⋃S: p < q
    ⋃S ᣔ<ᘁ ⋃S

    ⋃S is a foresplit.
    ∀p ∈ ⋃S: ∀q ∈ ℚ\⋃S:
    ∃F ∈ S ⊆ {Fꟴ}
    p ∈ F & q ∈ ℚ\F
    p < q
    ⋃S ᣔ<ᣔ ℚ\⋃S

    For bounded non.empty S ⊆ {Fꟴ}
    ⋃S ∈ {Fꟴ}

    ∀B:(∀F∈S:F ⊆ B) ⟹ (∀F∈S:F ⊆ ⋃S ⊆ B)

    {Fꟴ} holds ⋃S the least.upper.bound of
    bounded non.empty S ⊆ {Fꟴ}

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Thu Feb 8 10:59:15 2024
    Le 07/02/2024 à 13:29, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/7/24 2:24 AM, WM wrote:

    They are even points at the real line in linear order. Hence a first
    exists.

    Nope. Since there is no first positive rel point either, there still
    isn't a FIRST unit fraction.

    That is wrong in case of actual infinity. Without a first point there are
    no points.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Thu Feb 8 11:39:38 2024
    Le 07/02/2024 à 19:59, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 2/7/2024 2:35 AM, WM wrote:

    Therefore we have the alternative choice:
    either
    every ordered set of points 1/n on
    positive the real line,
    having gaps of uncountably many points
    between each other,
    has a first point
    or
    for every point 1/n
    there exists a point 1/(n+1).
    Both together is impossible.
    I prefer the first.

    It is the second alternative,
    | for each ⅟n exists ⅟n⁺¹ < ⅟n
    which supports the claim that
    no unit.fraction is smallest of them,
    which in turn is supported by
    ∀ n ∈ ℕ ∃ n+1 ∈ ℕ and
    n⋅⅟n⋅⅟n⁺¹ < n⁺¹⋅⅟n⋅⅟n⁺¹

    Your argument appears to begin and end
    at "I prefer the first".

    NUF(x) cannot increase by more than 1 per point because all unit fractions
    are points which have giant distances, namely uncountably many points.

    This is disproving your choice. However, also your choice implies
    infinitely many unit fractions which cannot be identified by any eps.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Thu Feb 8 07:35:53 2024
    On 2/8/24 5:59 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 07/02/2024 à 13:29, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/7/24 2:24 AM, WM wrote:

    They are even points at the real line in linear order. Hence a first
    exists.

    Nope. Since there is no first positive rel point either, there still
    isn't a FIRST unit fraction.

    That is wrong in case of actual infinity. Without a first point there
    are no points.

    Regards, WM


    Nope, we KNOW there are points, as we can name them.

    Your logic just doesn't works for this case, an infinite unbounded set.

    What is the first point on a circle? or do those not exist?

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Thu Feb 8 12:52:33 2024
    Le 08/02/2024 à 13:35, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/8/24 5:59 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 07/02/2024 à 13:29, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/7/24 2:24 AM, WM wrote:

    They are even points at the real line in linear order. Hence a first
    exists.

    Nope. Since there is no first positive rel point either, there still
    isn't a FIRST unit fraction.

    That is wrong in case of actual infinity. Without a first point there
    are no points.

    Nope, we KNOW there are points, as we can name them.

    You cannot, remember the missing eps for almost all of them.

    Your logic just doesn't works for this case, an infinite unbounded set.

    What is the first point on a circle? or do those not exist?

    Here we have no circle but a linear problem containing points with large distances.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Fritz Feldhase on Thu Feb 8 12:54:05 2024
    Fritz Feldhase schrieb am Mittwoch, 7. Februar 2024 um 16:21:07 UTC+1:
    On Wednesday, February 7, 2024 at 8:24:41 AM UTC+1, WM wrote:

    [The unit fractions] are points at the real line in linear order. Hence a
    first exists.

    The integers are points at the real line in linear order. Hence a first exists?

    Yes, that is proved by the unit fractions.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Fritz Feldhase on Thu Feb 8 13:01:12 2024
    Fritz Feldhase schrieb am Mittwoch, 7. Februar 2024 um 16:43:22 UTC+1:
    On Wednesday, February 7, 2024 at 8:35:37 AM UTC+1, WM wrote:

    | The latter is excluded by
    | ∀n ∈ ℕ: ⅟n - ⅟(n+1) > 0.
    und nun (nach einer Rückfrage):
    | It would be excluded by
    | ∀ n ∈ ℕ ∃ n+1 ∈ ℕ.
    It "would be" excluded?

    The first "latter" concerns ∀n ∈ ℕ: ⅟n - ⅟(n+1) > 0 excludes an increase of NUF by more than 1.
    The second "latter" concerns ∀n ∈ ℕ: ⅟n - ⅟(n+1) > 0 does not
    prove that for every n there is n+1.

    Hinweis: Es gilt im Kontext der klassischen Mathematik in der Tat:

    | ∀n ∈ ℕ: ∃m ∈ ℕ: m = n+1.

    But in the same context every unit fraction is followed by a gap excluding
    the increase of NUF by more than 1 in a point.

    we have the alternative choice:
    either
    every ordered set of points 1/n on the positive real line, having gaps of uncountably many points between each other, has a first point
    or
    for every point 1/n there exists a point 1/(n+1).
    Both together is impossible. I prefer the first.

    Great, Mückenheim. MATHEMATICS prefers the second (see Peano-Axioms).

    That is only because no mathematician hitherto has considered the second.

    Regards, WM


    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Thu Feb 8 13:53:26 2024
    On 2/8/2024 6:39 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 07/02/2024 à 19:59, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 2/7/2024 2:35 AM, WM wrote:

    Therefore we have the alternative choice:
    either
    every ordered set of points 1/n on
    positive the real line,
    having gaps of uncountably many points
    between each other,
    has a first point
    or
    for every point 1/n
    there exists a point 1/(n+1).
    Both together is impossible.
    I prefer the first.

    It is the second alternative,
    | for each ⅟n exists ⅟n⁺¹ < ⅟n
    which supports the claim that
    no unit.fraction is smallest of them,
    which in turn is supported by
    ∀ n ∈ ℕ ∃ n+1 ∈ ℕ and
    n⋅⅟n⋅⅟n⁺¹ < n⁺¹⋅⅟n⋅⅟n⁺¹

    Your argument appears to begin and end
    at "I prefer the first".

    NUF(x) cannot increase by
    more than 1 per point
    because
    all unit fractions are
    points which have giant distances, namely
    uncountably many points.

    This is disproving your choice.

    However, also your choice implies
    infinitely many unit fractions which
    cannot be identified by any eps.

    Each unit.fraction ⅟i′ is preceded by more than
    any final.ordinal.k.many unit.fractions ⅟k′
    such that each ⅟k′ is NOT followed by more than
    _any_ final.ordinal.j.many unit.fractions ⅟j′

    ∀⅟i′ ∈ ⅟ℕ:
    ∀k: Final(k) ⇒ ∃ᵏ⁺¹ ⅟k′ ∈ ⅟ℕ:
    (0 < ⅟k′ < ⅟i′ ∧
    ¬∀j: Final(j) ⇒ ∃ʲ⁺¹ ⅟j′ ∈ ⅟ℕ:
    (⅟k′ < ⅟j′ < ⅟1))

    Each unit.fraction ⅟i′ is
    infinitely.preceded by unit.fractions ⅟k′
    each ⅟k′ finitely.followed by unit.fractions ⅟j′

    A _final ordinal_ k cannot fit Bob in too.
    Final(k) ⟺
    {α|α<k} ⃒⇇ {Bob}∪{α|α<k} ⟺
    ¬∃f: {α|α<k}∪{Bob} ⇉ {α|α<k}:
    β≠γ ⇒ f(β)≠f(γ)

    After all ordinals which Bob cannot fit in,
    Bob can fit in.
    Final ᣔ<ᣔ ¬Final

    For each unit.fraction ⅟j′
    Bob can fit in ahead of ⅟j′ and
    Bob cannot fit in behind ⅟j′

    ∀⅟j′ ∈ ⅟ℕ:
    {⅟k′|⅟k′<⅟j′}∪{Bob} ⇉ {⅟k′|⅟k′<⅟j′} ∧ {⅟i′|⅟j′<⅟i′} ⃒⇇ {Bob}∪{⅟i′|⅟j′<⅟i′}

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Thu Feb 8 22:40:59 2024
    On 2/8/24 7:52 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 08/02/2024 à 13:35, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/8/24 5:59 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 07/02/2024 à 13:29, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/7/24 2:24 AM, WM wrote:

    They are even points at the real line in linear order. Hence a
    first exists.

    Nope. Since there is no first positive rel point either, there still
    isn't a FIRST unit fraction.

    That is wrong in case of actual infinity. Without a first point there
    are no points.

    Nope, we KNOW there are points, as we can name them.

    You cannot, remember the missing eps for almost all of them.

    What's missig about them?

    For every one of them, I can find an eps that is smaller, and for every
    eps I can find a unit fraction that is smaller.

    They keep getting smaller all the way down with no end.


    Your logic just doesn't works for this case, an infinite unbounded set.

    What is the first point on a circle? or do those not exist?

    Here we have no circle but a linear problem containing points with large distances.

    No, we have a linear problem with boundlessly small distances, so there
    is no smallest.


    Regards, WM



    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Fri Feb 9 09:44:45 2024
    Le 08/02/2024 à 19:53, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 2/8/2024 6:39 AM, WM wrote:

    Either NUF increases in one point to 1
    or to more.
    The latter is excluded by
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: ⅟n - ⅟(n+1) > 0.

    Elaborate on why

    Not before you have understood the above argument.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Fri Feb 9 09:40:25 2024
    Le 08/02/2024 à 19:53, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 2/8/2024 6:39 AM, WM wrote:

    NUF(x) cannot increase by
    more than 1 per point
    because
    all unit fractions are
    points which have giant distances, namely
    uncountably many points.

    Can you understand this?

    This is disproving your choice.

    However, also your choice implies
    infinitely many unit fractions which
    cannot be identified by any eps.

    Each unit.fraction ⅟i′ is preceded

    Stop to waffle. I know your argument.
    Can you understand the above?

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Fri Feb 9 09:59:06 2024
    Le 09/02/2024 à 04:40, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/8/24 7:52 AM, WM wrote:


    Nope, we KNOW there are points, as we can name them.

    You cannot, remember the missing eps for almost all of them.

    What's missig about them?

    You cannot define ℵ smallest existing unit fractions.

    For every one of them, I can find an eps that is smaller, and for every
    eps I can find a unit fraction that is smaller.

    Bigmout. Liar.

    No, we have a linear problem with boundlessly small distances, so there
    is no smallest.

    Impossible for NUF(x). NUF(0) = 0 and NUF(x>0) > 0 cannot exist without
    NUF(x) = 1 because between all points 1/n there are uncountably many
    points x with NUF(x) constant.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Fri Feb 9 07:19:05 2024
    On 2/9/24 4:59 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 09/02/2024 à 04:40, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/8/24 7:52 AM, WM wrote:


    Nope, we KNOW there are points, as we can name them.

    You cannot, remember the missing eps for almost all of them.

    What's missig about them?

    You cannot define ℵ smallest existing unit fractions.

    Well, there is no number ℵ (that would be a name for a set of values)

    And I can define the infinite set of the smallest unit fractions:

    1/n, 1/(n+1), 1/(n+2), 1/(n+3), ... 1/(n+k), ...


    For every one of them, I can find an eps that is smaller, and for
    every eps I can find a unit fraction that is smaller.

    Bigmout. Liar.

    Good self-discription.

    Give me a number it can't be done with.


    No, we have a linear problem with boundlessly small distances, so
    there is no smallest.

    Impossible for NUF(x). NUF(0) = 0 and NUF(x>0) > 0 cannot exist without NUF(x) = 1 because between all points 1/n there are uncountably many
    points x with NUF(x) constant.

    Bcause your definition of NUF(x) is broken.

    Note, you said BETWEEN points, and that only applies to points between
    unit fractions, not below all of them.

    Since there isn't a point below all the unit fractions and above 0,
    there is no constant point for NUF(x) to be 1.

    Your space has a discontinuity in definition, where NUF(x) jumps from
    its defined value of 0, to its poorly defined value of infinity. (since
    you claim to be working in the finite space, it can't have the value of
    ℵ, since that isn't a finite value)


    Regards, WM




    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Fri Feb 9 11:06:44 2024
    On 2/9/2024 4:44 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 08/02/2024 à 19:53, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 2/8/2024 6:39 AM, WM wrote:

    Either NUF increases in one point to 1
    or to more.
    The latter is excluded by
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: ⅟n - ⅟(n+1) > 0.

    Elaborate on why

    Not before you have understood
    the above argument.

    Until you elaborate,
    you do not have an argument.

    https://sneltraining.nl/then-a-miracle-occurs/
    |
    | "then a miracle occurs"
    |
    | I think you should be more explicit
    | here in step two"

    You have _at best_
    in what's far too _generous_ a framing
    a demand that _someone else_ make your argument
    _for you_

    I _understand_ that the argument you owe
    can't be made.
    Your argument _not.exists_ Wolfgang Mückenheim of
    Hochschule für angewandte Wissenschaften Augsburg,

    Either NUF increases in one point to 1
    or to more.
    The latter is excluded by
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: ⅟n - ⅟(n+1) > 0.

    At each unit.fraction ⅟n
    yes,
    there is one other[1]
    unit.fraction.to.the.left
    from left.of.⅟n to right.of.⅟n

    However,
    0 is not a unit.fraction, and
    0 is where NUF(x) jumps from 0 to ℵ₀
    | ∀n ∈ ℕ: ⅟n - ⅟(n+1) > 0.
    doesn't even begin to talk about
    the ℵ₀.jump.

    The difference between ⅟n and 0 is that
    around ⅟n is a small open interval,
    (left.of.⅟n,⅟n,right.of.⅟n)
    such that, in that small open interval,
    no unit.fractions are left.of.⅟n
    no unit.fractions are right.of.⅟n

    Thus,
    for each _unit.fraction_ ⅟n
    there is one other[1]
    unit.fraction.to.the.left
    from left.of.⅟n to right.of.⅟n

    In contrast,
    around _non.unit.fraction_ 0,
    no small open interval like that exists.

    For each right.of.0 (0,β)
    there is a unit.fraction ⅟1⁺ᵐᵝ in (0,β)
    mᵦ ≤ ⅟β < 1⁺ᵐᵝ

    For each final ordinal k
    there are more than k in (0,β),
    ⅟1⁺ᵐᵝ ⅟2⁺ᵐᵝ ... ⅟k⁺ᵐᵝ ⅟(k+1)⁺ᵐᵝ

    [1]
    At each unit.fraction ⅟n
    yes,
    there is one other
    unit.fraction.to.the.left
    from left.of.⅟n to right.of.⅟n

    I say "other" instead of "more"
    because,
    for unit.fractions.to.the.left,
    including one other _isn't_
    including one more.

    For a final.ordinal,
    including one other _is_
    including one more.

    However,
    unit.fractions.to.the.left
    _aren't_ any final ordinal k
    ⅟1⁺ᵐᵝ ⅟2⁺ᵐᵝ ... ⅟k⁺ᵐᵝ ⅟(k+1)⁺ᵐᵝ
    and
    one other isn't one more.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Sat Feb 10 17:35:19 2024
    Le 09/02/2024 à 13:19, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/9/24 4:59 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 09/02/2024 à 04:40, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/8/24 7:52 AM, WM wrote:


    Nope, we KNOW there are points, as we can name them.

    You cannot, remember the missing eps for almost all of them.

    What's missig about them?

    You cannot define ℵ smallest existing unit fractions.

    Well, there is no number ℵ (that would be a name for a set of values)

    I use it for infinitely many.

    And I can define the infinite set of the smallest unit fractions:

    1/n, 1/(n+1), 1/(n+2), 1/(n+3), ... 1/(n+k), ...

    ℵ are missing.

    Impossible for NUF(x). NUF(0) = 0 and NUF(x>0) > 0 cannot exist without
    NUF(x) = 1 because between all points 1/n there are uncountably many
    points x with NUF(x) constant.

    Your space has a discontinuity in definition, where NUF(x) jumps from
    its defined value of 0, to its poorly defined value of infinity. (since
    you claim to be working in the finite space, it can't have the value of
    ℵ, since that isn't a finite value)

    It can't jump from 0 to more than 1.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Fritz Feldhase on Sat Feb 10 19:08:52 2024
    Fritz Feldhase schrieb am Freitag, 9. Februar 2024 um 19:54:29 UTC+1:

    His "argument" is somehow like "the finite distances (>0) between any 2 'successive' unit fractions do not allow for infinitely many unit fractions in (0,
    x] [for all x > 0]", or so.

    Nonsense. Correct is: The finite distances force NUF(x) to pause after
    every increase by 1.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Sat Feb 10 18:18:50 2024
    Le 09/02/2024 à 17:06, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 2/9/2024 4:44 AM, WM wrote:

    Either NUF increases in one point to 1
    or to more.
    The latter is excluded by
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: ⅟n - ⅟(n+1) > 0.

    At each unit.fraction ⅟n
    yes,

    Only they are counted.

    However,
    0 is not a unit.fraction,

    Therefore NUF(0) = 0

    and
    0 is where NUF(x) jumps from 0 to ℵ₀

    Impossible because NUF jumps only at unit fractions, by definition.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Sat Feb 10 14:39:22 2024
    On 2/10/2024 12:35 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 09/02/2024 à 13:19, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/9/24 4:59 AM, WM wrote:

    You cannot define
    ℵ smallest existing unit fractions.

    Well, there is no number ℵ
    (that would be a name for a set of values)

    I use it for infinitely many.

    Unicode U+221E INFINITY ∞

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Sat Feb 10 14:31:59 2024
    On 2/10/2024 1:18 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 09/02/2024 à 17:06, Jim Burns a écrit :

    and
    0 is where NUF(x) jumps from 0 to ℵ₀

    Impossible because
    NUF jumps only at unit fractions,
    by definition.

    Probably what you (WM) mean by
    | ∀n ∈ ℕ: ⅟n - ⅟(n+1) > 0
    is
    | For each unit.fraction ⅟k
    | exists small.enough β > 0 such that
    | there is only one other unit.fraction < ⅟k+β
    | than there is ⅟k-β

    Yes, but
    for point 0 (not a unit.fraction)
    for each β > 0 (none are too small)
    unit.fractions < 0-β are 0.many
    and
    unit.fractions < 0-β are more than any final k

    0 < mᵦ ≤ ⅟β < mᵦ+1 = 1⁺ᵐᵝ
    β > ⅟1⁺ᵐᵝ > ... > ⅟k⁺ᵐᵝ > ⅟(k+1)⁺ᵐᵝ > 0

    Not( exists small.enough β > 0 such that
    there is only one other unit.fraction < 0+β
    than there is 0-β )

    Moreover,
    not( exists small.enough β > 0 such that
    there are only _two_ other unit.fraction < 0+β
    than there is 0-β )

    Not( exists small.enough β > 0 such that
    there are only k.many other unit.fraction < 0+β
    than there is 0-β )
    for any final ordinal k

    The jump NUF(x) makes at 0 is more than 1, more than 2,
    more than any final ordinal k.

    The jump NUF(x) makes at 0 isn't a final ordinal.

    and
    0 is where NUF(x) jumps from 0 to ℵ₀

    Impossible because
    NUF jumps only at unit fractions,
    by definition.

    Your definition is incorrect.

    What is correct is that
    NUF(x) jumps _near_ unit fractions.

    0 is _near_ unit fractions.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Sat Feb 10 15:02:40 2024
    On 2/10/2024 12:35 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 09/02/2024 à 13:19, Richard Damon a écrit :

    And I can define
    the infinite set of the smallest unit fractions:
    1/n, 1/(n+1), 1/(n+2), 1/(n+3), ... 1/(n+k), ...

    ℵ are missing.

    A set from which any unit fraction ≤ ⅟n is missing
    isn't the set of unit.fractions ≤ ⅟n

    It can't jump from 0 to more than 1.

    0 < mᵦ ≤ ⅟β < mᵦ+1 = 1⁺ᵐᵝ
    β > ⅟1⁺ᵐᵝ > ... > ⅟k⁺ᵐᵝ > ⅟(k+1)⁺ᵐᵝ > 0

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Sat Feb 10 15:34:09 2024
    On 2/10/24 12:35 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 09/02/2024 à 13:19, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/9/24 4:59 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 09/02/2024 à 04:40, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/8/24 7:52 AM, WM wrote:


    Nope, we KNOW there are points, as we can name them.

    You cannot, remember the missing eps for almost all of them.

    What's missig about them?

    You cannot define ℵ smallest existing unit fractions.

    Well, there is no number ℵ (that would be a name for a set of values)

    I use it for infinitely many.

    So, not a "number", since you reject "Mathelogical" definitions.

    "Natural Mathematics" doesn't have "infinite" as a "Value" only a
    concept that you can approach (because we are finite, and thus can't
    "see" infinity).

    Normally indicated with the symbol ∞


    And I can define the infinite set of the smallest unit fractions:

    1/n, 1/(n+1), 1/(n+2), 1/(n+3), ... 1/(n+k), ...

    ℵ are missing.

    Which ones?

    since n+k gets unboundedly large, 1/(n+k) gets unboundedly small, so no
    unit fraction gets missed.


    Impossible for NUF(x). NUF(0) = 0 and NUF(x>0) > 0 cannot exist
    without NUF(x) = 1 because between all points 1/n there are
    uncountably many points x with NUF(x) constant.

    Your space has a discontinuity in definition, where NUF(x) jumps from
    its defined value of 0, to its poorly defined value of infinity.
    (since you claim to be working in the finite space, it can't have the
    value of ℵ, since that isn't a finite value)

    It can't jump from 0 to more than 1.

    Why not?

    The other question, can it actually exist, since ℵ is not a "number" in
    the finite number systems (Natural Numbers, Rationals or Reals).

    To have the value of ℵ as an actual number, you need to accept some "mathelogical" framework that defines it, as "infinity" isn't a natural mathematical value.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Sat Feb 10 17:50:49 2024
    On 2/10/2024 2:31 PM, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 2/10/2024 1:18 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 09/02/2024 à 17:06, Jim Burns a écrit :

    and
    0 is where NUF(x) jumps from 0 to ℵ₀

    Impossible because
    NUF jumps only at unit fractions,
    by definition.

    [typos]

    Probably what you (WM) mean by
    | ∀n ∈ ℕ: ⅟n - ⅟(n+1) > 0
    is
    | For each unit.fraction ⅟k
    | exists small.enough β > 0 such that
    | there is only one other unit.fraction < ⅟k+β
    | than there are < ⅟k-β

    Yes, but
    for point 0 (not a unit.fraction)
    for each β > 0 (none are too small)
    unit.fractions < 0+β which aren't < 0-β
    aren't only k.many, for any final.ordinal k

    0 < mᵦ ≤ ⅟β < mᵦ+1 = 1⁺ᵐᵝ
    β > ⅟1⁺ᵐᵝ > ... > ⅟k⁺ᵐᵝ > ⅟(k+1)⁺ᵐᵝ > 0

    Not( exists small.enough β > 0 such that
    there is only one other
    unit.fraction < 0+β which isn't ≤ 0-β )

    Moreover,
    not( exists small.enough β > 0 such that
    there are only _two_ other
    unit.fractions < 0+β which aren't ≤ 0-β )

    Not( exists small.enough β > 0 such that
    there are only k.many other
    unit.fractions < 0+β which aren't ≤ 0-β )
    for any final ordinal k

    The jump NUF(x) makes at 0 is more than 1,
    more than 2, more than any final ordinal k.

    Each final.ordinal is not the jump NUF(x) makes at 0
    The jump is ℵ₀ which is not.a.final.ordinal.

    and
    0 is where NUF(x) jumps from 0 to ℵ₀

    Impossible because
    NUF jumps only at unit fractions,
    by definition.

    Your definition is incorrect.

    What is correct is that
    NUF(x) jumps _near_ unit fractions.

    The point 0 is _near_ unit fractions.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Sun Feb 11 08:57:56 2024
    Le 10/02/2024 à 20:39, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 2/10/2024 12:35 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 09/02/2024 à 13:19, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/9/24 4:59 AM, WM wrote:

    You cannot define
    ℵ smallest existing unit fractions.

    Well, there is no number ℵ
    (that would be a name for a set of values)

    I use it for infinitely many.

    Unicode U+221E INFINITY ∞

    That is used for potential infinity.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Sun Feb 11 08:56:48 2024
    Le 10/02/2024 à 20:31, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 2/10/2024 1:18 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 09/02/2024 à 17:06, Jim Burns a écrit :

    and
    0 is where NUF(x) jumps from 0 to ℵ₀

    Impossible because
    NUF jumps only at unit fractions,
    by definition.

    Yes, but
    for point 0 (not a unit.fraction)
    for each β > 0 (none are too small)
    unit.fractions < 0-β are 0.many
    and
    unit.fractions < 0-β are more than any final k

    After every unit fraction the function NUF(x) is constant over a distance containing many points. Therefore every increase can cover only one unit fraction. There is no exception.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Sun Feb 11 09:00:18 2024
    Le 10/02/2024 à 21:34, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/10/24 12:35 PM, WM wrote:


    It can't jump from 0 to more than 1.

    Why not?

    Because after every unit fraction there are points where NUF(x) remains constant.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Sun Feb 11 09:31:09 2024
    Le 10/02/2024 à 20:31, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 2/10/2024 1:18 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 09/02/2024 à 17:06, Jim Burns a écrit :

    and
    0 is where NUF(x) jumps from 0 to ℵ₀

    Nice and relieving to see that you have no mathematical argument.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Sun Feb 11 09:38:32 2024
    Le 10/02/2024 à 21:34, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/10/24 1:18 PM, WM wrote:

    You only have an "Natural Language" definition of NUF(x). You haven't
    shown that it can actually exist.

    Mathematics is not restricted to matheology.

    Your definition creates a contradiction, that NUF(x) will have the value
    1 at the smallest unit fraction, but there isn't a smallest unit
    fraction, so you don't have a workable definition.

    There is no visible first unit fraction. But if there are many unit
    fractions in linear order, then a first one is indispensable by simple
    logic.

    That is sort of like asking, what is the truth value for the following statement:

    This statement is false.

    Assuming you have NUF(x), breaks your mathematics.

    Claiming that there are all unit fractions visible although in every case almost all are invisible exhibits an incredible courage to accept self-contradictions.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Sun Feb 11 09:46:49 2024
    Le 10/02/2024 à 23:50, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 2/10/2024 2:31 PM, Jim Burns wrote:

    NUF jumps only at unit fractions,
    by definition.

    Your definition is incorrect.

    What is correct is that
    NUF(x) jumps _near_ unit fractions.

    Why should it do so?

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Sun Feb 11 07:47:48 2024
    On 2/11/24 3:57 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 10/02/2024 à 20:39, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 2/10/2024 12:35 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 09/02/2024 à 13:19, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/9/24 4:59 AM, WM wrote:

    You cannot define
    ℵ smallest existing unit fractions.

    Well, there is no number ℵ
    (that would be a name for a set of values)

    I use it for infinitely many.

    Unicode U+221E INFINITY  ∞

    That is used for potential infinity.

    Regards, WM

    No, that is ACTUAL infinity.

    I guess you don't understand the math you are talking about.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Sun Feb 11 16:40:03 2024
    On 2/11/2024 4:46 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 10/02/2024 à 23:50, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 2/10/2024 2:31 PM, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 2/10/2024 1:18 PM, WM wrote:

    NUF jumps only at unit fractions,
    by definition.

    Your definition is incorrect.
    What is correct is that
    NUF(x) jumps _near_ unit fractions.

    Why should it do so?

    You will recall that, for differentiable f(x)
    its derivative _at_ x is defined using
    points _near_ x.
    Here, we aren't discussing a derivative, but
    there are similarities.


    For each point t
    The set ⅟ℕ∩(-∞,x) doesn't change _at_ x
    ⅟ℕ∩(-∞,x) is one set, unchanging.
    From what would it be different?

    Not.entirely.relevantly,
    I am reminded of my favorite riddle.
    A...certain length of time ago,
    I would ask it, given any excuse:

    Q. What is the difference between a duck?
    A. One has feathers.

    What's the difference between ⅟ℕ∩(-∞,x)?
    One has feathers?

    We can do better:
    What's the difference between
    ⅟ℕ∩(-∞,x₋) near.and.before x and
    ⅟ℕ∩(-∞,x₊) ear.and.after x?


    for each ⅟n
    intervals (⅟n-β,⅟n), (⅟n,⅟n+β) exist
    such that
    ⅟n is between (⅟n-β,⅟n), (⅟n,⅟n+β) and
    (⅟n-β,⅟n), (⅟n,⅟n+β) hold no unit fractions.

    For any point x₊ ∈ (⅟n,⅟n+β)
    the set ⅟ℕ∩(-∞,x₊) holds
    the single unit.fraction ⅟n which isn't also in
    any of the sets ⅟ℕ∩(-∞,x₋) with x₋ ∈ (⅟n-β,⅟n)

    That is a jump in unit.fraction.ness _at_ ⅟n
    from a point near.and.before ⅟n
    to a point near.and.after ⅟n

    How near is "near"?

    Consider the unit.fraction point ⅟n

    0.many unit.fractions from ⅟n downto ⅟n-β
    0.many unit.fractions from ⅟n downto ⅟n-β/10
    0.many unit.fractions from ⅟n downto ⅟n-β/10¹⁰⁰
    0.many unit.fractions from ⅟n downto ⅟n-β/10¹ᐧᴱ¹⁰⁰

    0.many unit.fractions from ⅟n upto ⅟n+β
    0.many unit.fractions from ⅟n upto ⅟n+β/10
    0.many unit.fractions from ⅟n upto ⅟n+β/10¹⁰⁰
    0.many unit.fractions from ⅟n upto ⅟n+β/10¹ᐧᴱ¹⁰⁰

    However near is meant by "near",
    much nearer is also true.

    Squeeze all that detail out of the discussion
    and we are left with
    ⅟ℕ∩(-∞,x) jumps at ⅟n


    Consider the not.a.unit.fraction point 0

    Yes,
    0.many unit.fractions from 0 downto 0-β
    0.many unit.fractions from 0 downto 0-β/10
    0.many unit.fractions from 0 downto 0-β/10¹⁰⁰
    0.many unit.fractions from 0 downto 0-β/10¹ᐧᴱ¹⁰⁰

    However,
    for each final ordinal n such that
    ⟨1,…,n⟩ ⃒⇇ ⟨1,…,n,n+1⟩:

    more than n.many from 0 upto 0+β
    0 < m ≤ ⅟β < m⁺¹ = 1⁺ᵐ
    β > ⅟1⁺ᵐ > ... > ⅟n⁺ᵐ > ⅟(n+1)⁺ᵐ > 0

    more than n.many from 0 upto 0+β\10
    0 < k ≤ 10/β < k⁺¹ = 1⁺ᵏ
    β/10 > ⅟1⁺ᵏ > ... > ⅟n⁺ᵏ > ⅟(n+1)⁺ᵏ > 0

    more than n.many from 0 upto 0+β\10¹⁰⁰
    0 < j ≤ 10¹⁰⁰/β < j⁺¹ = 1⁺ʲ
    β/10¹⁰⁰ > ⅟1⁺ʲ > ... > ⅟n⁺ʲ > ⅟(n+1)⁺ʲ > 0

    more than n.many from 0 upto 0+β/10¹ᐧᴱ¹⁰⁰
    0 < i ≤ 10/β < i⁺¹ = 1⁺ⁱ
    β/10¹ᐧᴱ¹⁰⁰ > ⅟1⁺ⁱ > ... > ⅟n⁺ⁱ > ⅟(n+1)⁺ⁱ > 0

    ⅟1⁺ᵐ, ..., ⅟n⁺ᵐ, ⅟(n+1)⁺ᵐ
    aren't
    ⅟1⁺ᵏ, ..., ⅟n⁺ᵏ, ⅟(n+1)⁺ᵏ
    which aren't
    ⅟1⁺ʲ, ... , ⅟n⁺ʲ, ⅟(n+1)⁺ʲ
    which aren't
    ⅟1⁺ⁱ, ..., ⅟n⁺ⁱ, ⅟(n+1)⁺ⁱ

    They're all positive,
    they're all different points,
    they're all not.darkᵂᴹ

    And
    For each β > 0 (and β/10¹ᐧᴱ¹⁰⁰ too)
    for each final.ordinal n ∈ ℕ
    NUF(β) > n ∈ ℕ

    NUF(x) jumps _near_ unit fractions.

    Why should it do so?

    If there is a jump _at_ a point,
    it's because of a comparison of
    leftward.unit.fractions between
    its one side and its other side
    _near_ the point.

    The jump at 0 is more.than.1
    because,
    anywhere on its other side,
    there is more than 1 unit fraction
    between the other.side.point and 0

    Also, more than 2, more than 3, more than 4,
    more than any final ordinal n
    ⟨1,…,n⟩ ⃒⇇ ⟨1,…,n,n+1⟩

    The jump at/near 0 isn't any of those.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Sun Feb 11 17:59:43 2024
    On 2/11/2024 9:17 AM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On 02/10/2024 02:50 PM, Jim Burns wrote:

    [...]

    and topologies of various sorts,
    including at least one where
    open and closed _are_ binary,

    A topological space X which doesn't have
    at least two clopen (closed.and.open) sets,
    X and ∅
    isn't a topological space.


    A topological space ⟨X,𝒪⟩ is
    a set X and a collection 𝒪 ⊆ 𝒫(X) of its subsets,
    designated the set of _open_ sets of the space.
    𝒪 is the topology of ⟨X,𝒪⟩

    The topological axioms for ⟨X,𝒪⟩ are:
    1. The union of an arbitrary open.set.set 𝒜 ⊆ 𝒪
    is the open.set ⋃𝒜 ∈ 𝒪.
    2. The intersection of two open.sets B,C ∈ 𝒪
    is the open set B∩C ∈ 𝒪.
    3. ∅ and X are open sets.

    1. 𝒜 ⊆ 𝒪 ⇒ ⋃𝒜 ∈ 𝒪
    2. B,C ∈ 𝒪 ⇒ B∩C ∈ 𝒪
    3. ∅ ∈ 𝒪 ∧ X ∈ 𝒪

    The complement of an open set is a closed set,
    and vice versa.

    The complement of open ∅ ∈ 𝒪 is open X.
    ∅ is clopen.
    The complement of open X ∈ O is open 0
    X is clopen.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Mon Feb 12 15:02:08 2024
    Le 11/02/2024 à 13:47, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/11/24 3:57 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 10/02/2024 à 20:39, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 2/10/2024 12:35 PM, WM wrote:
    Le 09/02/2024 à 13:19, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/9/24 4:59 AM, WM wrote:

    You cannot define
    ℵ smallest existing unit fractions.

    Well, there is no number ℵ
    (that would be a name for a set of values)

    I use it for infinitely many.

    Unicode U+221E INFINITY  ∞

    That is used for potential infinity.

    No, that is ACTUAL infinity.

    I guess you don't understand the math you are talking about.

    Das Zeichen oo, ... ersetze ich von nun an durch ω, weil das Zeichen oo
    schon vielfach zur Bezeichnung von unbestimmten [d. h. potentiellen] Unendlichkeiten verwandt wird. [Cantor]

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Mon Feb 12 15:03:14 2024
    Le 11/02/2024 à 13:47, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/11/24 4:00 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 10/02/2024 à 21:34, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/10/24 12:35 PM, WM wrote:


    It can't jump from 0 to more than 1.

    Why not?

    Because after every unit fraction there are points where NUF(x) remains
    constant.

    But if there isn't a first,

    then there is none at all.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Mon Feb 12 15:08:19 2024
    Le 11/02/2024 à 13:47, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/11/24 4:38 AM, WM wrote:

    Assuming you have NUF(x), breaks your mathematics.

    Claiming that there are all unit fractions visible although in every
    case almost all are invisible exhibits an incredible courage to accept
    self-contradictions.

    Where was any "invisible".

    You can't show that ANY are "invisible".

    You said: And why do you need to travese it "step by step"? That
    restriction is the restriction of finiteness, and doesn't allow for the infinite.

    That is proving the invisible that cannot be traversed step by step.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Mon Feb 12 15:11:25 2024
    Le 11/02/2024 à 22:40, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 2/11/2024 4:46 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 10/02/2024 à 23:50, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 2/10/2024 2:31 PM, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 2/10/2024 1:18 PM, WM wrote:

    NUF jumps only at unit fractions,
    by definition.

    Your definition is incorrect.
    What is correct is that
    NUF(x) jumps _near_ unit fractions.

    Why should it do so?

    You will recall that, for differentiable f(x)
    its derivative _at_ x is defined using
    points _near_ x.
    Here, we aren't discussing a derivative, but
    there are similarities.

    No. Here we have steps in only one point each.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Mon Feb 12 14:38:28 2024
    On 2/12/2024 10:11 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 11/02/2024 à 22:40, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 2/11/2024 4:46 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 10/02/2024 à 23:50, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 2/10/2024 2:31 PM, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 2/10/2024 1:18 PM, WM wrote:

    NUF jumps only at unit fractions,
    by definition.

    Your definition is incorrect.
    What is correct is that
    NUF(x) jumps _near_ unit fractions.

    Why should it do so?

    You will recall that, for differentiable f(x)
    its derivative _at_ x is defined using
    points _near_ x.
    Here, we aren't discussing a derivative, but
    there are similarities.

    No.
    Here we have steps in only one point each.

    Here we have the explanation you (WM) asked for.

    For each _unit.fraction_ ⅟n
    left.of.⅟n is unit.fraction.less (⅟n⁺¹,⅟n)
    ⅟n is a unit.fraction.
    right.of.⅟n is unit.fraction.less (⅟n,⅟n⁻¹)

    The sets ⅟ℕ∩(-∞,x) for each x changes by
    a single element ⅟n
    from ⅟ℕ∩(-∞,x₋) at near.point x₋ ∈ (⅟n⁺¹,⅟n)
    to ⅟ℕ∩(-∞,x₊) at near.point x₊ ∈ (⅟n,⅟n⁻¹)

    Near.points x₋ x₊

    For _not.unit.fraction_ 0
    left.of.0 is a unit.fraction.less (-∞,0)
    0 is a not.unit.fraction.

    However,
    right of 0, each (0,x₊) is not unit.fraction.less

    For each final.ordinal n, there are more.than.n
    unit.fractions.in.(0,x₊)
    x₊ > ⅟1⁺ᵐ > ... > ⅟n⁺ᵐ > ⅟(n+1)⁺ᵐ > 0
    for 0 < m ≤ ⅟x₊ < m⁺¹ = 1⁺ᵐ

    Those more.than.n unit.fractions in (0,x₊) are
    positive,
    separately.positioned, and
    NOT common.to.all.(0,x₊)
    For example,
    x′₊ > ⅟1⁺ᵐ⁺ⁿ⁺¹ > ... > ⅟n⁺ᵐ⁺ⁿ⁺¹ > ⅟(n+1)⁺ᵐ⁺ⁿ⁺¹ > 0
    for x′₊ = ⅟m⁺ⁿ⁺¹ = ⅟(n+1)⁺ᵐ = ⅟0⁺ᵐ⁺ⁿ⁺¹

    ⟨⅟1⁺ᵐ,…,⅟(n+1)⁺ᵐ⟩ are in (0,x₊)
    and also not.in (0,x′₊)
    and not common
    but
    ⟨⅟1⁺ᵐ⁺ⁿ⁺¹,…,⅟(n+1)⁺ᵐ⁺ⁿ⁺¹⟩ are in (0,x′₊)

    For each (0,x₊)
    more.than.final.ordinal.n
    positive, separately.positioned, not.common
    unit.fractions are in (0,x₊)

    A jump across 0 to any x₊
    augments ⅟ℕ∩(-∞,x) by ℵ₀ (more.than.any.final)
    positive, separately.positioned, not.common
    unit.fractions in (0,x₊)

    Hence,
    ∀x ∈ (0,1]: NUF(x) = ℵ₀

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Mon Feb 12 18:07:23 2024
    On 2/12/2024 4:18 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On 02/12/2024 11:38 AM, Jim Burns wrote:

    [...]

    [...] and these kinds of things,
    about the special and vacuous and trivial
    topologies, yet what still fulfill the
    requirements and desiderata of continuous domains.

    I'm pretty sure that, by "continuous",
    you (RF) mean here "connected".

    "Connected" is a topological concept:
    reducible to talk about open sets.

    I am thinking of an Old One's advice:
    explanations should be as simple as possible,
    but no simpler.

    I think that expressing "connected" _topologically_
    accomplishes that.

    (i) A connected space X is not a disconnected space.

    (ii) A disconnected space can be partitioned into
    two non.empty open sets B,C ∈ 𝒪\{∅}
    B∪C = X ∧ B∩C = ∅

    0. 𝒪 ⊆ 𝒫(X)
    1. 𝒜 ⊆ 𝒪 ⇒ ⋃𝒜 ∈ 𝒪
    2. B,C ∈ 𝒪 ⇒ B∩C ∈ 𝒪
    3. ∅ ∈ 𝒪 ∧ X ∈ 𝒪

    The Dedekind completion of disconnected ℚ
    gives us connected ℝ,
    which provides a function which jumps
    somewhere at which it jumps.

    I refer to the standard topology 𝒪ᴿ of ℝ which
    is determined by an open basis ℬᴿ of
    open intervals in ℝ as determined by
    the standard metric |y-x| of ℝ
    ℬᴿ = {(x,y): x,y ∈ ℝ}
    𝒪ᴿ = {⋃𝒜: 𝒜 ⊆ ℬᴿ}

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Mon Feb 12 21:21:35 2024
    On 2/12/24 10:03 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 11/02/2024 à 13:47, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/11/24 4:00 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 10/02/2024 à 21:34, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/10/24 12:35 PM, WM wrote:


    It can't jump from 0 to more than 1.

    Why not?

    Because after every unit fraction there are points where NUF(x)
    remains constant.

    But if there isn't a first,

    then there is none at all.

    Regards, WM


    So, you just admitted you logic can't make the Natural Numbers.


    Your logic is BUSTED.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Tue Feb 13 10:36:08 2024
    Le 12/02/2024 à 20:38, Jim Burns a écrit :

    Hence,
    ∀x ∈ (0,1]: NUF(x) = ℵ₀

    Two unit fractions, whatever their index may be, take infinitely many
    points. Hence not even two, let alone more, can lie before every x > 0.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Tue Feb 13 10:41:30 2024
    Le 13/02/2024 à 03:21, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/12/24 10:03 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 11/02/2024 à 13:47, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/11/24 4:00 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 10/02/2024 à 21:34, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/10/24 12:35 PM, WM wrote:


    It can't jump from 0 to more than 1.

    Why not?

    Because after every unit fraction there are points where NUF(x)
    remains constant.

    But if there isn't a first,

    then there is none at all.

    So, you just admitted you logic can't make the Natural Numbers.

    It can and does. It cures intelligent readers from wrong assumptions which stupid readers cannot give up.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Tue Feb 13 07:21:57 2024
    On 2/13/24 5:41 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 13/02/2024 à 03:21, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/12/24 10:03 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 11/02/2024 à 13:47, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/11/24 4:00 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 10/02/2024 à 21:34, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/10/24 12:35 PM, WM wrote:


    It can't jump from 0 to more than 1.

    Why not?

    Because after every unit fraction there are points where NUF(x)
    remains constant.

    But if there isn't a first,

    then there is none at all.

    So, you just admitted you logic can't make the Natural Numbers.

    It can and does. It cures intelligent readers from wrong assumptions
    which stupid readers cannot give up.

    Regards, WM


    But you just admitted that if there wasn't a lowest Unit Fraction, and
    thus a Highest Natural Number, then there weren't any in your system.

    We KNOW there can't be either of those, as BY DEFINITION, every Natural
    Number has a successor, (and thus every Unit Fraction as another smaller
    than it). This is a DEFINITION, and can't be changed and still be
    working with that set.

    You can't escape the results of your own logic.

    YOU are the one make "Wrong Assumptions".

    Your logic system is just totally inconsistent and worthless when
    applied to this field.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Tue Feb 13 13:12:55 2024
    On 2/13/2024 5:36 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 12/02/2024 à 20:38, Jim Burns a écrit :

    Hence,
    ∀x ∈ (0,1]: NUF(x) = ℵ₀

    Two unit fractions,
    whatever their index may be,
    take infinitely many points.

    Let's say:
    ⅟137 and ⅟138
    take infinitely many points.
    Elaborate.
    What does that mean?

    Hence
    not even two,
    let alone more,
    can lie before every x > 0.

    1.
    not.exists two unit.fractions such that,
    for each x > 0,
    the two < x
    ¬∃{⅟n,⅟n′} ⊆ ⅟ℕ₁:
    ∀x ∈ ℝ⁺:
    x > ⅟n′ > ⅟n > 0

    | Assume otherwise.
    | Assume ∀x ∈ ℝ⁺: x > ⅟n′ > ⅟n > 0
    |
    | However,
    | counter.example: x = ⅟n⁺¹
    | ¬(x = ⅟n⁺¹ > ⅟n′ > ⅟n > 0)
    | ¬∀x ∈ ℝ⁺: x > ⅟n′ > ⅟n > 0
    | Contradiction.

    2.
    for each x > 0,
    exists two unit.fractions such that,
    the two < x
    ∀x ∈ ℝ⁺:
    ∃{⅟n,⅟n′} ⊆ ⅟ℕ₁:
    x > ⅟n′ > ⅟n > 0

    for each x ∈ ℝ⁺
    for example,
    0 ≤ mₓ ≤ ⅟x < mₓ⁺¹ < mₓ⁺²
    ⅟n′ = ⅟mₓ⁺¹, ⅟n = ⅟mₓ⁺²
    x > ⅟n' > ⅟n > 0


    Because of #2
    ∀x ∈ R+: NUF(x) > 1

    Moreover,
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: ∀x ∈ R+: NUF(x) > n


    | ¬∃{⅟n,⅟n′} ⊆ ⅟ℕ₁:
    | ∀x ∈ ℝ⁺:
    | x > ⅟n′ > ⅟n > 0
    does not imply
    | ¬∀x ∈ ℝ⁺:
    | ∃{⅟n,⅟n′} ⊆ ⅟ℕ₁:
    | x > ⅟n′ > ⅟n > 0

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Tue Feb 13 16:15:16 2024
    On 2/13/2024 2:05 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On 02/12/2024 07:32 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On 02/11/2024 02:59 PM, Jim Burns wrote:

    [...]
    [...]

    What I have in mind here is that
    the continuous domain has sorts of topologies, that
    make it so, that every open set is also
    a continuous domain, and, to make it so, that
    only two open sets that are "contiguous", are in
    this sort of topology.

    It is worth remembering that
    a topological space ⟨X,𝒪⟩ is
    a set X and a set 𝒪 of sets in X
    meeting certain conditions.
    0. 𝒪 ⊆ 𝒫(X)
    1. 𝒜 ⊆ 𝒪 ⇒ ⋃𝒜 ∈ 𝒪
    2. B,C ∈ 𝒪 ⇒ B∩C ∈ 𝒪
    3. ∅ ∈ 𝒪 ∧ X ∈ 𝒪

    That's it.
    That leaves a lot of room to choose
    different topologies 𝒪,𝒪′ which
    meet conditions 0,1,2,3.

    For different topologies 𝒪≠𝒪′, ⟨X,𝒪⟩≠⟨X,𝒪′⟩ ⟨X,𝒪⟩ and ⟨X,𝒪′⟩ are different spaces.

    Domain ⟨X,𝒪⟩ being connected/continuous
    places another condition on 𝒪:
    no two non.empty open sets (sets in 𝒪) partition X
    For _connected_ topological space ⟨X,𝒪⟩
    4. B ∈ 𝒪\{∅,X} ⇒ X\B ∉ 𝒪

    I don't know offhand but I wouldn't be shocked if
    there are also multiple _connnected_ topologies
    for some sets X

    What I have in mind here is that
    the continuous domain has sorts of topologies, that
    make it so, that every open set is also
    a continuous domain, and, to make it so, that
    only two open sets that are "contiguous", are in
    this sort of topology.

    I vaguely recall from a topology course that
    my instructor blended "contiguous" and "continuous"
    into "contiuous" for some theorems.

    There might be a notion of "contiguous" that's
    useful here. If there is, I'd like to know it.

    Please define "contiguous" for the context
    in which you are using it here.

    Googling "contiguous" or "contiuous"
    could in principle resolve my quandary,
    but there are too many other uses.
    I tried it and got no joy.
    (For "contiuous", too many typos of continuous")

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Tue Feb 13 18:47:13 2024
    On 2/13/2024 4:38 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On 02/13/2024 01:15 PM, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 2/13/2024 2:05 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:

    What I have in mind here is that
    the continuous domain has sorts of topologies, that
    make it so, that every open set is also
    a continuous domain, and, to make it so, that
    only two open sets that are "contiguous", are in
    this sort of topology.

    I vaguely recall from a topology course that
    my instructor blended "contiguous" and "continuous"
    into "contiuous" for some theorems.

    There might be a notion of "contiguous" that's
    useful here. If there is, I'd like to know it.

    Please define "contiguous" for the context
    in which you are using it here.

    Googling "contiguous" or "contiuous"
    could in principle resolve my quandary,
    but there are too many other uses.
    I tried it and got no joy.
    (For "contiuous", too many typos of continuous")

    Contiguous basically means "in all neighborhoods
    together".

    So, for 𝒪 = {∅,X}
    all points in X are contiguous to each other?
    Do I have that right?

    This seems related to Hausdorff space.
    | for any two distinct points, there exist
    | neighbourhoods of each that are disjoint from each other.
    |
    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Hausdorff_space

    With your interest in defining ℝ,
    that seems right up your (RF's) alley.
    | Of the many separation axioms that can be imposed on
    | a topological space, the "Hausdorff condition" (T2) is
    | the most frequently used and discussed.
    | It implies the uniqueness of limits of
    | sequences, nets, and filters
    |
    ibid.

    ----
    Side note:
    You know what's a connected topology?
    𝒪 = {∅,X} is a connected topology.

    Condition #4 is vacuously satisfied.
    4. B ∈ 𝒪\{∅,X} ⇒ X\B ∉ 𝒪

    But 𝒪 = {∅,X} isn't Hausdorff.

    It makes me go "Hmmm."

    Not sure about "contiuous", "conti?uous".

    I would not be surprised if "contiuous"
    was an invention of my instructor,
    and not particularly widely used.

    Mathematics:  both sides to anything.

    ...unless only one side exists.

    Mathematicians do agree on some things.
    But those seem to only be things upon which
    there is no rational alternative to agreeing.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Wed Feb 14 09:26:42 2024
    Le 13/02/2024 à 13:21, Richard Damon a écrit :

    But you just admitted that if there wasn't a lowest Unit Fraction, and
    thus a Highest Natural Number, then there weren't any in your system.

    We KNOW there can't be either of those, as BY DEFINITION, every Natural Number has a successor,

    This definition concerns visible numbers only.

    This is a DEFINITION, and can't be changed

    it is important for mathematics. Mathematics uses only visible numbers.

    Look, this statement:
    ∃^ℵo y ∈ {1/n : n ∈ ℕ}, ∀ x ∈ (0, 1]: 0 < y < x .
    It is wrong!
    It can only be wrong only if there are x > 0 existing between this subset
    of ℵo unit fractions interrupting it. Or why should it be wrong?
    But if an uninterrupted sequences of ℵo unit fractions is excluded by interrupting x, then not all of these interrupters can have ℵo unit
    fractions at their left-hand side. Then there are x with fewer smaller
    unit fractions.

    They are dark.

    Regards, WM

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Wed Feb 14 09:29:52 2024
    Le 13/02/2024 à 13:21, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/13/24 5:36 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 12/02/2024 à 20:38, Jim Burns a écrit :

    Hence,
    ∀x ∈ (0,1]: NUF(x) = ℵ₀

    Two unit fractions, whatever their index may be, take infinitely many
    points. Hence not even two, let alone more, can lie before every x > 0.

    But can before ANY x > 0.

    The pair cannot be before the x between them. And since between every pair
    of all the infinitely many, there are x, there cannot be pairs before
    every x.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Wed Feb 14 09:22:33 2024
    Le 13/02/2024 à 19:12, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 2/13/2024 5:36 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 12/02/2024 à 20:38, Jim Burns a écrit :

    Hence,
    ∀x ∈ (0,1]: NUF(x) = ℵ₀

    Two unit fractions,
    whatever their index may be,
    take infinitely many points.

    Let's say:
    ⅟137 and ⅟138
    take infinitely many points.
    Elaborate.
    What does that mean?

    That means: They do not fit below every x > 0.

    Hence
    not even two,
    let alone more,
    can lie before every x > 0.

    1.
    not.exists two unit.fractions such that,

    For all 1/n and 1/(n+1) the same holds: They do not fit below every x > 0.


    | ¬∃{⅟n,⅟n′} ⊆ ⅟ℕ₁:
    | ∀x ∈ ℝ⁺:
    | x > ⅟n′ > ⅟n > 0

    Why not? Of course your statement is wrong. But there must be some facts
    which make it wrong. Same with this statement:
    ∃^ℵo y ∈ {1/n : n ∈ ℕ}, ∀ x ∈ (0, 1]: 0 < y < x .
    It is wrong!
    It can only be wrong only if there are x > 0 existing between this subset
    of ℵo unit fractionsinterrupting it. Or why should it be wrong?
    But if an uninterrupted sequences of ℵo unit fractions is excluded by interrupting x, then not all of these interrupters have ℵo unit
    fractions at their left-hand side. Then there are x with fewer smaller
    unit fractions.

    They are dark.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Fritz Feldhase on Wed Feb 14 09:48:42 2024
    Fritz Feldhase schrieb am Dienstag, 13. Februar 2024 um 17:28:30 UTC+1:

    Es wird aber NICHT behauptet "There are infinitely many unit fractions that are
    smaller than every x > 0." (2)

    Why is this a wrong claim? It can only be wrong, if there is no
    uninterrupted infinite sequence of unit fractions smaller than every x.
    Which x interrupt it? such that no uninterrupted infinite sequence of unit fractions remains smaller than every x? This can only be caused by x
    within this sequence which have fewer smaller unit fraction. Without them statement (2) would be true.

    Wie Du richtig beobachtet hast, gibt es NICHT EINMAL 2 unit fractions, die kleiner sind als alle x > 0.

    This can only be avoided by x within every pair. This is a property of all pairs. Therefore even infinitely many pairs fail to exclude an x with only
    one smaller unit fraction.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Wed Feb 14 07:36:58 2024
    On 2/14/24 4:29 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 13/02/2024 à 13:21, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/13/24 5:36 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 12/02/2024 à 20:38, Jim Burns a écrit :

    Hence,
    ∀x ∈ (0,1]: NUF(x) = ℵ₀

    Two unit fractions, whatever their index may be, take infinitely many
    points. Hence not even two, let alone more, can lie before every x > 0.

    But can before ANY x > 0.

    The pair cannot be before the x between them. And since between every
    pair of all the infinitely many, there are x, there cannot be pairs
    before every x.

    Regards, WM


    Of course there can.

    Yoyu are just caught in your finite logic.

    Every time you think of an x greater thatn 0, there exist an INFINITE
    number of unit fractions below it, so there are at least 2. (Since 2 is
    less than infinity).

    Your mind is just so slow it is stuck two steps behind where you are.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Wed Feb 14 07:34:04 2024
    On 2/14/24 4:26 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 13/02/2024 à 13:21, Richard Damon a écrit :

    But you just admitted that if there wasn't a lowest Unit Fraction, and
    thus a Highest Natural Number, then there weren't any in your system.

    We KNOW there can't be either of those, as BY DEFINITION, every
    Natural Number has a successor,

    This definition concerns visible numbers only.

    So every visible number has a visible number after it, thus there is no
    higher visible number, and ALL Natural Numbers are visible, and none are
    dark.

    I guess you can go home now.


    This is a DEFINITION, and can't be changed

    it is important for mathematics. Mathematics uses only visible numbers.

    WHy do you say that?



    Look, this statement:
    ∃^ℵo y ∈ {1/n : n ∈ ℕ}, ∀ x ∈ (0, 1]: 0 < y < x .
    It is wrong!

    Why do you think it should be right?

    THAT is your problem.

    It can only be wrong only if there are x > 0 existing between this subset
    of ℵo unit fractions interrupting it. Or why should it be wrong?

    Because of the properties of infinite sets.

    But if an uninterrupted sequences of ℵo unit fractions is excluded by interrupting x, then not all of these interrupters can have ℵo unit fractions at their left-hand side. Then there are x with fewer smaller
    unit fractions.

    They are dark.

    Regards, WM

    Regards, WM


    You are just using finite logic on infinte sets.

    Very similar to trying to divide by 0.

    THe logic blows up.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Wed Feb 14 13:38:06 2024
    On 2/14/2024 4:22 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 13/02/2024 à 19:12, Jim Burns a écrit :

    [...]

    But if
    an uninterrupted sequences of
    ℵo unit fractions

    uninterrupted sequence ==
    not.exists final.ordinal.j
    ¬∃⟨1,…,j⟩ ⃒⇇ ⟨1,…,j,j+1⟩:
    such that
    not.exists more.than.j unit.fractions
    ¬∃⟨⅟1,…,⅟j,⅟(j+1)⟩

    is excluded by interrupting x,

    interrupting x ==
    x > 0 such that
    exists final ordinal j
    x: ∃⟨1,…,j⟩ ⃒⇇ ⟨1,…,j,j+1⟩:
    such that
    not.exists more.than.j unit.fractions
    ¬∃⟨⅟1,…,⅟j,⅟(j+1)⟩:
    each before x
    ⟨⅟1,…,⅟j,⅟(j+1)⟩ ᣔ> x > 0

    then
    not all of these interrupters have
    ℵo unit fractions at their left-hand side.

    Elaborate on
    why you think that
    an uninterrupted sequence _doesn't_
    continue uninterrupted on
    the other side of an interruption.

    Elaborate on
    why you think it's _false_ that
    for each interrupting x > 0
    ∀x:∃⟨1,…,j⟩ ⃒⇇ ⟨1,…,j,j+1⟩: ¬∃⟨⅟1,…,⅟j,⅟(j+1)⟩:
    ⟨⅟1,…,⅟j,⅟(j+1)⟩ ᣔ> x > 0

    the sequence is uninterrupted after x
    ¬∃⟨1,…,k⟩ ⃒⇇ ⟨1,…,k,k+1⟩: ¬∃⟨⅟1⁺ᵐˣ,…,⅟k⁺ᵐˣ,⅟(k+1)⁺ᵐˣ⟩:
    x >ᣔ ⟨⅟1⁺ᵐˣ,…,⅟k⁺ᵐˣ,⅟(k+1)⁺ᵐˣ⟩ ᣔ> 0
    for
    0 ≤ mₓ ≤ ⅟x < mₓ+1 = 1⁺ᵐˣ

    (i)
    Do you (WM) deny that mₓ exists,
    contrary to the Archimedean property?

    (ii)
    Do you (WM) deny that final.ordinal.addition
    is provably closed in the final.ordinals?

    If (i) or (ii),
    you aren't using words
    how we're using words,
    you aren't denying
    what we're claiming.

    To anyone else,
    a parakeet isn't a counter.example to
    | No horses have feathers
    even if what _you_ mean by "horse"
    includes parakeets.
    That's not the way words work.

    Then there are x with
    fewer smaller unit fractions.

    They are dark.

    Ex falso quodlibet.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Wed Feb 14 18:30:41 2024
    On 2/14/2024 4:22 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 13/02/2024 à 19:12, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 2/13/2024 5:36 AM, WM wrote:

    Hence
    not even two,
    let alone more,
    can lie before every x > 0.

    1.
    not.exists two unit.fractions such that,
    for each x > 0,
    the two < x
    ¬∃{⅟n,⅟n′} ⊆ ⅟ℕ₁:
    ∀x ∈ ℝ⁺:
    x > ⅟n′ > ⅟n > 0

    #1 re.states your claim just above.
    #1 is provable.

    For all 1/n and 1/(n+1) the same holds:
    They do not fit below every x > 0.

    ..which is to say,
    ∀{⅟n,⅟n⁺¹} ⊆ ⅟ℕ₁:
    ¬∀x ∈ ℝ⁺:
    x > ⅟n > ⅟n⁺¹ > 0

    Essentially the same as #1
    Still provable. Still yours.

    | ¬∃{⅟n,⅟n′} ⊆ ⅟ℕ₁:
    | ∀x ∈ ℝ⁺:
    | x > ⅟n′ > ⅟n > 0

    Why not?

    Why not what?
    The statement just.above is
    -- provable (see proof, above)
    -- and your claim.

    Of course your statement is wrong.

    My statement is
    ¬∃{⅟n,⅟n′} ⊆ ⅟ℕ₁:
    ∀x ∈ ℝ⁺:
    x > ⅟n′ > ⅟n > 0
    It (my statement) is your statement.
    It is provable.
    It is, of course, not wrong.

    But there must be some facts which
    make it wrong.

    If I understand you correctly,
    | ⅟137 > ⅟138 > ⅟139 > 0
    isn't a factᵂᴹ.

    Here and perhaps elsewhere,
    only the same number being less than
    each unit.fraction
    is one of your factsᵂᴹ.

    Am I understanding you correctly?

    Same with this statement:
    ∃^ℵo y ∈ {1/n : n ∈ ℕ},
    ∀ x ∈ (0, 1]:
    0 < y < x .
    It is wrong!

    ¬∃^ℵo y ∈ {1/n : n ∈ ℕ},
    ∀ x ∈ (0, 1]:
    0 < y < x .

    Can you spot the difference between
    | ¬∃{⅟n,⅟n′} ⊆ ⅟ℕ₁:
    | ∀x ∈ ℝ⁺:
    | x > ⅟n′ > ⅟n > 0
    and
    | ∃{⅟n,⅟n′} ⊆ ⅟ℕ₁:
    | ∀x ∈ ℝ⁺:
    | x > ⅟n′ > ⅟n > 0
    ?

    It can only be wrong only if
    there are x > 0 existing between
    this subset of ℵo unit fractions
    interrupting it. Or why should
    it be wrong?

    | ¬∃^ℵo y ∈ {1/n : n ∈ ℕ},
    | ∀ x ∈ (0, 1]:
    | 0 < y < x .
    isn't wrong.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Thu Feb 15 12:53:53 2024
    Le 15/02/2024 à 00:30, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 2/14/2024 4:22 AM, WM wrote:
    Same with this statement:
    ∃^ℵo y ∈ {1/n : n ∈ ℕ},
    ∀ x ∈ (0, 1]:
    0 < y < x .
    It is wrong!

    It can only be wrong only if
    there are x > 0 existing between
    this subset of ℵo unit fractions
    interrupting it. Or why should
    it be wrong?

    | ¬∃^ℵo y ∈ {1/n : n ∈ ℕ},
    | ∀ x ∈ (0, 1]:
    | 0 < y < x .
    isn't wrong.

    No. But there must be a reason. The reason is this: Between every pair of
    unit fractions there are points x > 0 which are not unit fractions. Eveb
    if infinitely any unit fractions are existing, then the first pair is
    isolated by x > 0 between them.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Fritz Feldhase on Thu Feb 15 12:59:25 2024
    Fritz Feldhase schrieb am Mittwoch, 14. Februar 2024 um 18:17:54 UTC+1:
    On Wednesday, February 14, 2024 at 10:22:40 AM UTC+1, WM wrote:

    ∃^ℵo y ∈ {1/n : n ∈ ℕ}: ∀ x ∈ (0, 1]: y < x .
    It is wrong!

    (während ∀ x ∈ (0, 1]: ∃^ℵo y ∈ {1/n : n ∈ ℕ}: y < x wahr ist).

    why [is] it wrong?

    Because there is no y ∈ {1/n : n ∈ ℕ} such that y < y.

    let alone ℵo such unit fractions smaller thn every unit fraction.

    Therefore this is wrong too.
    ∀ x ∈ (0, 1]: ∃^ℵo y ∈ {1/n : n ∈ ℕ}: y < x.

    Counterexample: The smallest unit fraction.

    Note that after *every* unit fractions the function NUF(x) pauses. There
    cannot be an increase from NUF(0) = 0 to NUF(x>0) > 0 without NUF passing
    1.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Thu Feb 15 13:03:40 2024
    Le 14/02/2024 à 13:34, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/14/24 4:26 AM, WM wrote:

    Look, this statement:
    ∃^ℵo y ∈ {1/n : n ∈ ℕ}, ∀ x ∈ (0, 1]: 0 < y < x .
    It is wrong!

    Why do you think it should be right?

    It should be right if ∀x ∈ (0, 1]: NUF(x) = ℵo.

    It can only be wrong only if there are x > 0 existing between this subset
    of ℵo unit fractions interrupting it. Or why should it be wrong?

    Because of the properties of infinite sets.

    Hogwash

    You are just using finite logic on infinte sets.

    There is only finite logic.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Thu Feb 15 13:05:21 2024
    Le 14/02/2024 à 13:36, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/14/24 4:29 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 13/02/2024 à 13:21, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/13/24 5:36 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 12/02/2024 à 20:38, Jim Burns a écrit :

    Hence,
    ∀x ∈ (0,1]: NUF(x) = ℵ₀

    Two unit fractions, whatever their index may be, take infinitely many
    points. Hence not even two, let alone more, can lie before every x > 0. >>>
    But can before ANY x > 0.

    The pair cannot be before the x between them. And since between every
    pair of all the infinitely many, there are x, there cannot be pairs
    before every x.

    Of course there can.

    Waffle.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Thu Feb 15 10:27:45 2024
    On 2/15/2024 7:53 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 15/02/2024 à 00:30, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 2/14/2024 4:22 AM, WM wrote:

    Same with this statement:
    ∃^ℵo y ∈ {1/n : n ∈ ℕ},
    ∀ x ∈ (0, 1]:
    0 < y < x .
    It is wrong!

    It can only be wrong only if
    there are x > 0 existing between
    this subset of ℵo unit fractions
    interrupting it. Or why should it be wrong?

    | ¬∃^ℵo y ∈ {1/n : n ∈ ℕ},
    | ∀ x ∈ (0, 1]:
    | 0 < y < x .
    isn't wrong.

    No. But there must be a reason.

    | ¬∃^ℵo y ∈ {1/n : n ∈ ℕ},
    | ∀ x ∈ (0, 1]:
    | 0 < y < x .
    does not have the (wrong) consequence
    ☠ ¬∀x ∈ (0,1]: NUF(x) = ℵ₀
    which you (WM) wish it had.

    | ∀ x ∈ (0, 1]:
    | ∃^ℵo y ∈ {1/n : n ∈ ℕ},
    | 0 < y < x .
    also isn't wrong,
    and it has the (correct bc logic) consequence
    | ∀x ∈ (0,1]: NUF(x) = ℵ₀

    No. But there must be a reason.
    The reason is this:
    Between every pair of unit fractions
    there are points x > 0 which
    are not unit fractions.
    Eveb if
    infinitely any unit fractions are existing,
    then
    the first pair

    Elaborate on
    how you have _already proved_
    that a first pair exists.

    All of this is _in pursuit of_
    a proof that a (darkᵂᴹ) first pair exists.
    You're acting like you already have that proof.
    Show me that earlier proof, please.

    then
    the first pair
    is isolated by x > 0 between them.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Thu Feb 15 16:55:10 2024
    Le 15/02/2024 à 16:27, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 2/15/2024 7:53 AM, WM wrote:

    No. But there must be a reason.
    The reason is this:
    Between every pair of unit fractions
    there are points x > 0 which
    are not unit fractions.
    Even if
    infinitely any unit fractions are existing,
    then
    the first pair

    Elaborate on
    how you have _already proved_
    that a first pair exists.

    All of this is _in pursuit of_
    a proof that a (darkᵂᴹ) first pair exists.
    You're acting like you already have that proof.
    Show me that earlier proof, please.

    An increase from NUF(0) = 0 to NUF(x>0) > 0 cannot happen unless NUF
    increases. It cannot increase other than when passing unit fractions. It
    cannot pass more than one unit fraction at a single point because ∀n ∈
    ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) = d_n > 0 .

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Thu Feb 15 16:46:31 2024
    Le 14/02/2024 à 19:38, Jim Burns a écrit :
    On 2/14/2024 4:22 AM, WM wrote:

    Elaborate on
    why you think that
    an uninterrupted sequence _doesn't_
    continue uninterrupted on
    the other side of an interruption.

    That is excluded because the unit fractions of the sequence themselves are interrupting x > 0.

    Do you (WM) deny that mₓ exists,
    contrary to the Archimedean property?

    We have the choice between two alternatives (like often in life):
    Either the Archimedean property holds only for visible natural numbers
    (that is suggesting itself because never anybody could prove it for dark numbers), or not all unit fractions have distances.
    Of course ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) = d_n > 0 could also be violated for
    dark unit fractions. But in my opinion that appears less probable. In any
    case only one alternative is possible.


    Do you (WM) deny that final.ordinal.addition
    is provably closed in the final.ordinals?

    It is closed in the collection of visible numbers. Addition will never
    lead to numbers with less than ℵo not reached successors.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Thu Feb 15 19:23:29 2024
    On 2/14/2024 5:12 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On 02/14/2024 12:16 PM, Chris M. Thomasson wrote:

    [...]

    Clearly there's a distinction between
    "infinitely-many" and "infinitely-grand",
    yet, what is it?

    The distinction more enlightening to me
    is between "finitely.many" and "not.that".

    "Not.that" is found in many different places,
    with descriptions appropriate to each place.
    Wherever there's "finitely.many", it seems to be
    the same "finitely.many".

    What we mean by a natural number is preceded by
    finitely.many natural numbers.

    An object preceded by
    more than any natural number
    is preceded by not.that.

    For example,
    ω is preceded by each natural number.
    ω is not.that (AKA infinite).

    Other objects are preceded by each natural number,
    ω+1, ω+ω, ω⋅ω, ωᐜ, ...
    What we mean by ω is specifically the first object
    preceded by each natural number, preceding
    ω+1, ω+ω, ω⋅ω, ωᐜ, ...

    ω is the first infinite ordinal.

    Clearly there's a distinction between
    "infinitely-many" and "infinitely-grand",
    yet, what is it?

    There is one ordinal.set {<ω} of ordinals < ω
    I would say {<ω} is infinitely.grand and
    the elements of {<ω} are infinitely.many.

    {{<ω}} is finitely.grand.
    For each n ∈ {<ω}, {<n} is finitely.grand.

    The idea that there's
    a "projective point at infinity", or, that there's
    "fixed point, at infinity", or, that there's
    "one-point compactification, at infinity", or,
    that there's "a prime, or a composite, at infinity",
    or, all these things about the numbers in the numbers,
    has that
    for these sorts "number theorists" and "geometers",
    that they think they can think they can.

    A list of the various kinds of infinity
    floats around the internet and
    occasionally bobs to the surface.
    Caveat lector, but
    it seem to me that the various infinities are
    different ways to make the very.vague "not.that"
    usefully less.vague.

    To each circumstance, its "not.that".
    From each "not.that", its divergent consequences.

    Posit an effectively large number called "infinity".
    It's called "effective infinity".
     Being all rational,
    it's large enough to act like infinity.

    Large enough that
    being less than infinite has
    no _practical_ effect (in circumstance X)
    can still mean finite.
    I'll call that "practically infinite" in order to
    stay distinct from your "effectively infinite".

    "Practically infinite" is finite.

    By definition,
    there's no practical distinction,
    but there's an important logical distinction.

    We reason incredibly.efficiently about
    vast domains by stating
    claims true for each one of that domain,
    and then augmenting with
    claims not.first.false for each one of that domain.

    If we start by stating
    | This object is finite
    (true of each in the vast domain of finites)
    that will also be true of
    the practically infinite.
    To wherever we reason from there,
    our conclusions will also be for
    the practically infinite.

    That is why,
    even if they're practically infinite,
    the practically infinite don't really
    act like the infinite.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Thu Feb 15 21:36:54 2024
    On 2/15/24 8:03 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 14/02/2024 à 13:34, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/14/24 4:26 AM, WM wrote:

    Look, this statement:
    ∃^ℵo y ∈ {1/n : n ∈ ℕ}, ∀ x ∈ (0, 1]: 0 < y < x .
    It is wrong!

    Why do you think it should be right?

    It should be right if ∀x ∈ (0, 1]: NUF(x) = ℵo.

    Why?

    And what is the problem with it.

    Your statement says that for every x in the range (0,1] (not the range
    itself), there exist y's less than that x, which is a true statement,
    and in fact, for ANY x we can choose, there will exist ℵo y's that are elements of the unit fractions below it.

    This may seem impossible, but is a consequence of the fact that these
    numbers can get unboundedly small, and thus there is no "smallesst" or
    even a smallest finite set of them.




    It can only be wrong only if there are x > 0 existing between this
    subset
    of ℵo unit fractions interrupting it. Or why should it be wrong?

    Because of the properties of infinite sets.

    Hogwash

    Nope. Your idea that this is "hogwash" just shows you don't understand
    how the infinite works.


    You are just using finite logic on infinte sets.

    There is only finite logic.

    Regards, WM

    If there is only finite logic, then there are no infinite sets, like the Natural Numbers.

    There isn't even a value ℵo

    So, you are admitting you are wrong.

    You can't build infinite sets with logic that is solely finite.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Fri Feb 16 03:21:07 2024
    On 2/15/2024 9:35 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On 02/15/2024 04:23 PM, Jim Burns wrote:

    If we start by stating
    | This object is finite
    (true of each in the vast domain of finites)
    that will also be true of
    the practically infinite.
    To wherever we reason from there,
    our conclusions will also be for
    the practically infinite.

    That is why,
    even if they're practically infinite,
    the practically infinite don't really
    act like the infinite.

    You know,
    "iota" is a word, besides that
    iota is a letter of the Greek alphabet, and
    "iota" is a word, and its
    definition in some dictionaries, is,
    "smallest positive quantity".

    Sure, why not?
    A definition tells us how a word is to be used.
    A definition shouldn't tell us more than that.
    Then it steps over the border into claims.land.

    Tell me what you mean by a word.
    Okay, fine.
    I will believe that you know what you mean.

    Tell me that
    it exists, what that word means,
    or it has the least.upper.bound property,
    or it lives in New Zealand.
    Sorry, no.
    I want more than your authority.
    I want evidence, reasoning.
    Claim ≠ definition.

    0 < ι ∧ ¬∃xₓ: 0 < xₓ < ι
    is an acceptable definition of 'ι'
    It tells us how the word 'ι' is to be used.

    The definition of 'ι'
    doesn't tell us whether ι exists,
    as it shouldn't.
    ∃ι ∈ ℕ
    ¬∃ι ∈ ℚ
    ¬∃ι ∈ ℝ

    ℕ holds a smallest positive.
    ℝ does not hold a smallest positive.
    ℚ does not hold a smallest positive.

    | Assume otherwise.
    | Assume ι ∈ ℚ: 0 < ι ∧
    | ∀xₓ ∈ ℚ: ¬(0 < xₓ < ι)
    |
    | Counter.example: xₓ = ι/2
    | 0 < xₓ < ι
    | Contradiction.

    So, "iota-values" really seems apropos
    what to call
    a range of constantly-different monotone
    strictly increasing values between zero and one,
    an infinitude of them.

    Do you have a definition? Yes.
    Does what you have defined exist?
    Remember ι
    Those are separate questions.


    Consider
    a range of constantly-different monotone
    strictly increasing values between zero and one,
    an infinitude of them.
    I abbreviate that to [0,1]\ι

    Define a next.operator ̅⯭
    ∀x ∈ [0,1)\ι: ∃​̅⯭x ∈ (0,1]\ι:
    x < ̅⯭x ∧ ¬∃xₓ ∈ [0,1]\ι: x < xₓ < ̅⯭x

    It is a constantly.different strictly.increasing
    next.operator.
    ∀x,x′ ∈ [0,1)\ι: ̅⯭x-x = ̅⯭x′-x′ = ι > 0

    Are there an infinitude of them?
    No.

    Perhaps there are
    an effective infinitude of them.
    Perhaps a practical infinitude.
    But those are finite infinitudes
    Infinite infinitudes have properties which
    finite infinitudes lack.

    ...which is an excellent argument against using
    this kind of terminology in the first lace.

    ι > 0
    Therefore, there is
    a finitely.denominated unit.fraction ⅟n
    between ι and 0
    |[0,1]\ι| ≤ n+1

    | Assume otherwise.
    | Assume ι is a positive lower bound of
    | finitely.denominated unit.fractions.
    | 0 < ι ≤ᣔ ⅟ℕ₁
    |
    | β is the greatest.lower.bound of ⅟ℕ₁
    |
    | β exists, or else
    | a function exists which is
    | continuous everywhere and
    | skips over some points between.
    |
    | 0 < ι ≤ β
    | 0 < β/2 < β < 2β
    | 2β isn't a lower bound of ⅟ℕ₁
    | β is the greatest lower bound of ⅟ℕ₁
    | β/2 is a lower bound of ⅟ℕ₁
    |
    | β < 2β
    | 2β isn't a lower bound of ⅟ℕ₁
    | finitely.denominated ⅟m₂ᵦ < 2β exists.
    | finitely.denominated ⅟(4⋅m₂ᵦ) < β/2 exists.
    | β/2 isn't a lower bound of ⅟ℕ₁
    |
    | However,
    | β/2 < β
    | β/2 is a lower bound of ⅟ℕ₁
    | Contradiction.

    Therefore,
    there is a finitely.denominated unit.fraction ⅟n
    between ι and 0
    |[0,1]\ι| ≤ n+1

    For a range of constantly-different monotone
    strictly increasing values between zero and one,
    there aren't an infinitude of them.

    You can define whatever you choose to define,
    but
    not everything you can choose to define
    includes the rationals and
    excludes skipping functions continuous everywhere.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Fritz Feldhase on Fri Feb 16 09:44:59 2024
    Fritz Feldhase schrieb am Freitag, 16. Februar 2024 um 01:53:20 UTC+1:

    Actually, in the context of "classical mathematics", there is indeed no smallest
    unit fraction. (If u is a unit fraction, 1/(1/u + 1) is a smaller one.)

    Right. But there is no completed infinity in classical mathematics either.


    On the other hand, there is!

    In fact it is unavoidable if infinity is completed.
    An increase from NUF(0) = 0 to NUF(x>0) > 0 cannot happen unless NUF
    increases. It cannot increase other than when passing unit fractions. It
    cannot pass, between 0 and x > 0, more than one unit fraction at a single
    point because
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) = d_n > 0 .

    Gruß, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Fri Feb 16 09:53:11 2024
    Le 16/02/2024 à 03:36, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/15/24 8:03 AM, WM wrote:

    There is only finite logic.

    If there is only finite logic, then there are no infinite sets, like the Natural Numbers.

    Wrong.

    There isn't even a value ℵo.

    Wrong.

    You can't build infinite sets with logic that is solely finite.

    All logic is finite. Try to understand ZF as a start. Nothing infinite in
    the formalism.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Fri Feb 16 09:50:11 2024
    Le 16/02/2024 à 03:36, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/15/24 8:05 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 14/02/2024 à 13:36, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/14/24 4:29 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 13/02/2024 à 13:21, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/13/24 5:36 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 12/02/2024 à 20:38, Jim Burns a écrit :

    Hence,
    ∀x ∈ (0,1]: NUF(x) = ℵ₀

    Two unit fractions, whatever their index may be, take infinitely
    many points. Hence not even two, let alone more, can lie before
    every x > 0.

    But can before ANY x > 0.

    The pair cannot be before the x between them. And since between every
    pair of all the infinitely many, there are x, there cannot be pairs
    before every x.


    THAT pair may not be before the x between them, but before the x exists
    a pair of values, in fact, there exists ℵo values.

    All are pairs with x between them.

    The "x" between them is not the same "x" that the pair was before.

    That isnot necessary because every pair has this property.

    Every "x" has ℵo numbers before it, so we can find a number of pairs.

    All having x between them. Why should this fact vanish?

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Fri Feb 16 09:55:56 2024
    Le 16/02/2024 à 03:36, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/15/24 7:59 AM, WM wrote:

    Note that after *every* unit fractions the function NUF(x) pauses. There
    cannot be an increase from NUF(0) = 0 to NUF(x>0) > 0 without NUF
    passing 1.

    OF course there can, as long as there is no "first" (i.e. lowest) unit fraction.

    THe problem is that your "NUF" function can't actually be constructed
    per you definition, since it assumes the ability to "count" from an
    "end" that doesn't actually have a point at the "end" of it.

    NUF(0) = 0 and NUF(1/10) = ℵo are well defined.
    An increase from NUF(0) = 0 to NUF(x>0) > 0 cannot happen unless NUF
    increases. It cannot increase other than by passing unit fractions. It
    cannot pass more than one unit fraction at a single point because
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) = d_n > 0. Simple as that.

    Gruß, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Fri Feb 16 10:54:54 2024
    On 2/16/24 4:55 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 16/02/2024 à 03:36, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/15/24 7:59 AM, WM wrote:

    Note that after *every* unit fractions the function NUF(x) pauses.
    There cannot be an increase from NUF(0) = 0 to NUF(x>0) > 0 without
    NUF passing 1.

    OF course there can, as long as there is no "first" (i.e. lowest) unit
    fraction.

    THe problem is that your "NUF" function can't actually be constructed
    per you definition, since it assumes the ability to "count" from an
    "end" that doesn't actually have a point at the "end" of it.

    NUF(0) = 0 and NUF(1/10) = ℵo are well defined.

    except that ℵo isn't a defined number in the system you are claiming to
    be working in.

    If you accept ℵo as a number, it says you are in the domain of
    trans-finite math, and must accept its rules, which you do not.

    Thus, your definition is just a LIE based on non-sense.

    ℵo does not exist in the domain of "natural mathematics", only the
    abstract concept of infinity, that isn't a "value"

    You need to accept a matheology to get definition to give you a value
    like ℵo.

    An increase from NUF(0) = 0 to NUF(x>0) > 0 cannot happen unless NUF increases. It cannot increase other than by passing unit fractions. It
    cannot pass more than one unit fraction at a single point because
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) = d_n > 0. Simple as that.

    Gruß, WM




    No, it can not have a finite number unless there exists a "smallest"
    unit fraction. Since there doesn't exist such a thing, it never has such
    a value.

    The definition that it only increases as "unit fractions" is thus, an ill-defined requrement, making NUF(x) ill-definied.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Fri Feb 16 10:55:05 2024
    On 2/16/24 4:50 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 16/02/2024 à 03:36, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/15/24 8:05 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 14/02/2024 à 13:36, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/14/24 4:29 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 13/02/2024 à 13:21, Richard Damon a écrit :
    On 2/13/24 5:36 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 12/02/2024 à 20:38, Jim Burns a écrit :

    Hence,
    ∀x ∈ (0,1]: NUF(x) = ℵ₀

    Two unit fractions, whatever their index may be, take infinitely >>>>>>> many points. Hence not even two, let alone more, can lie before
    every x > 0.

    But can before ANY x > 0.

    The pair cannot be before the x between them. And since between
    every pair of all the infinitely many, there are x, there cannot be
    pairs before every x.


    THAT pair may not be before the x between them, but before the x
    exists a pair of values, in fact, there exists ℵo values.

    All are pairs with x between them.

    But the pairs were a pair below an x.

    You are confusing what x meant/


    The "x" between them is not the same "x" that the pair was before.

    That isnot necessary because every pair has this property.


    But it is.

    Green is not Orange, even though on the color wheel Green is between
    Blue and Yellow and Blue and Yellow are to the side Orange.

    You don't get to "reset" the value of x in the middle.

    That isn't how qualifier logic works.



    Every "x" has ℵo numbers before it, so we can find a number of pairs.

    All having x between them. Why should this fact vanish?

    The have AN x between them, but not the x that pair was defined to be below.

    Your statements are just being inconsistent.


    Regards, WM



    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to All on Sat Feb 17 08:29:42 2024
    Le 16/02/2024 à 18:25, Ross Finlayson a écrit :
    On 02/16/2024 01:44 AM, WM wrote:
    Fritz Feldhase schrieb am Freitag, 16. Februar 2024 um 01:53:20 UTC+1:

    Actually, in the context of "classical mathematics", there is indeed
    no smallest unit fraction. (If u is a unit fraction, 1/(1/u + 1) is a
    smaller one.)

    Right. But there is no completed infinity in classical mathematics either. >>>
    On the other hand, there is!

    In fact it is unavoidable if infinity is completed.
    An increase from NUF(0) = 0 to NUF(x>0) > 0 cannot happen unless NUF
    increases. It cannot increase other than when passing unit fractions. It
    cannot pass, between 0 and x > 0, more than one unit fraction at a
    single point because
    ∀n ∈ ℕ: 1/n - 1/(n+1) = d_n > 0 .

    In "classical mathematics", how do you even draw a line?

    Using a ruler.

    "Modern geometers have recognized the need for an additional
    postulate, sometimes called ''the postulate of continuity,''

    For my above example we need no continuity but only some brain.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Sat Feb 17 14:01:20 2024
    On 2/16/2024 4:50 AM, WM wrote:
    Le 16/02/2024 à 03:36, Richard Damon a écrit :

    THAT pair may not be before the x between them,
    but before the x exists a pair of values,
    in fact, there exists ℵo values.

    All are pairs with x between them.

    No x is between all pairs.

    The "x" between them is not
    the same "x" that the pair was before.

    That isnot necessary because
    every pair has this property.

    No x has the property pf
    being between every each pair.


    Do you (WM) still say
    you don't use the invalid swap
    ☠ ∀x∃y≠x: x<y ⊢ ∃y∀x≠y: x<y
    ?

    It shouldn't disrupt your plans
    to point out that
    | ∀x∃y≠x: x<y ⊢ ¬∃y∀x≠y: x<y

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mild Shock@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Mon Feb 19 18:25:20 2024
    Not a clown. A fraud. You are constantly emitting
    fake news. Just try a minimum verification before
    you claim something from the stomach.

    The scientific approach to make a claim about
    somebody (like Wolfram) or something (his book),
    is to give a relevant citation, that you think supports

    your claim! You can electronically
    borrow the book free of charge:

    A new kind of science by Wolfram, Stephen
    Publication date 2002
    https://archive.org/details/newkindofscience00wolf/


    Ross Finlayson schrieb:
    So, if I am like a clown sometimes, it is to share being human,
    behaviors and norms are rather usual, and expectations of the
    demonstration of comprehension of fundamental foundations the
    theory, are expected to be same for all.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mild Shock@21:1/5 to Mild Shock on Mon Feb 19 20:36:38 2024
    Your posts, Rossy Boy, are as colorful as the eternal rainbow
    of the smoke comming from the chimeys of a big steel mill.

    The dynamics you depict when your reproduce mathematics or physics
    reflects your disposition between resigned and ambitious.

    Credits: Keisuke Kinoshita, 1958.

    Must be the influence of WWII, that these films are so
    stiff, the performers have a stick up their asses.

    What influenced Rossy Boy to become similarly nauseating?

    Mild Shock schrieb:

    You got shipwrecked, and are ashore of a lost lagoon.
    But who are the coloured ones that steal the show?

    Credits: Paramount Pictures, 1958.

    Mild Shock schrieb am Montag, 19. Februar 2024 um 20:13:38 UTC+1:
    Your posts are full of cynicism and galloping horses.
    Your method is mechanical and desultory. Just
    not good enough. Only interesting as a punch face.

    Ross Finlayson schrieb am Montag, 19. Februar 2024 um 19:14:20 UTC+1:
    Dear readers, please have that I'll always try
    to speak to your highest intellect, while providing
    a contemporary, fair, telling, modicum of wit.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mild Shock@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Tue Feb 20 08:34:38 2024
    You only make it worse!

    There are roundabout arguments that, for example,
    the FINITE ORDINALS, as a set, consequently contain
    themselves, as an element. This is a direct
    compactness result.

    If you want to have ordinals that contain themselves,
    you need to mention an encoding. Because per se,
    we understand by ordinal an order type.

    There ware various encodings for finite ordinals around:
    1) von Neuman encoding, based on succ(X) = X u {X} and 0 = {}
    2) Zermelo encoding, bsaed on succ(X) = {X} and 0 = {}
    3) Your Powerset idea, based on succ(X) = P(X) and 0 = {}

    All 3 have the property that:

    /* provable */
    n in n+1 and n is finite

    Proof:
    case 1): n+1 = n u {n}, n in n+1 because n in {n}.
    further succ(X) sendes an already finite set into a finite set.
    case 2): n+1 = {n}, n in n+1 because n in {n}.
    further succ(X) sendes an already finite set into a finite set.
    case 3): n+1 = P(n), n in n+1 because n in P(n).
    further succ(X) sendes an already finite set into a finite set.
    Q.E.D.

    But none has the property that omega = { n } contains
    itself, the proof of contradiction applies irrelevant
    of the encoding, it only makes use of the

    notion finite and infinite:

    /* provable */
    ~(omega in omega) & (Y in omega => Y finite)

    Proof:
    (Y in omega => Y finite) follows by the claim that
    omega = { n }, i.e. the least set that contains all finite
    ordinals in the corresponding encoding. If it would
    contain something infinite it would not be the least

    set that contains all finite ordinals, would have some
    extra in it. Violating the very construction of omega from
    the finite ordinals.
    Q.E.D.


    Ross Finlayson schrieb:
    On 02/19/2024 05:01 PM, Mild Shock wrote:
    The contradiction is very easy:

    Lets say X is the set of all finite ordinals.

    - observe that X is an infinite ordinal.
    - observe that if Y in X, then Y is a finite ordinal.
    - hence if X in X it would be an infinite and finite ordinal at the
    same time.
    - an X cannot be infinite and finite at the same time.
    Q.E.D:

    Ross Finlayson schrieb am Dienstag, 20. Februar 2024 um 00:04:06 UTC+1:
    There are roundabout arguments that, for example, the finite
    ordinals,
    as a set, consequently contain themselves, as an element. This is a
    direct compactness result.
    (Maybe that's just me.)

    Imagine if ordinals' proper model was that the successor
    was powerset, instead of just any old ordered pair.

    So, those together are the "sets that don't contain themselves",
    the sets of ordinals.

    Quantifying over those, results the "Russell set the ordinal",
    it contains itself.

    So here Y isn't necessarily a finite ordinal.

    Q.E.R.


    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Mild Shock@21:1/5 to Mild Shock on Tue Feb 20 08:56:49 2024
    You could use an encoding of finite ordinals
    into infinite objects, like:

    0 = omega, 1 = omega+1, etc..

    Then my proof doesn't work so easily. You can then
    use the regularity axiom, to show:

    /* provable */
    ~(omega in omega)

    Axiom of regularity
    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Axiom_of_regularity

    Is this your A "paradox" is not a set in ZF?
    In non-ZF you could aim at making omega a Quine atom: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Urelement#Quine_atoms

    Or any other construction and encoding where you
    would sneak in a set into itself.


    Mild Shock schrieb:
    You only make it worse!

    There are roundabout arguments that, for example,
    the FINITE ORDINALS, as a set, consequently contain
    themselves, as an element. This is a direct
    compactness result.

    If you want to have ordinals that contain themselves,
    you need to mention an encoding. Because per se,
    we understand by ordinal an order type.

    There ware various encodings for finite ordinals around:
    1) von Neuman encoding, based on succ(X) = X u {X} and 0 = {}
    2) Zermelo encoding, bsaed on succ(X) = {X} and 0 = {}
    3) Your Powerset idea, based on succ(X) = P(X) and 0 = {}

    All 3 have the property that:

    /* provable */
    n in n+1 and n is finite

    Proof:
    case 1): n+1 = n u {n}, n in n+1 because n in {n}.
    further succ(X) sendes an already finite set into a finite set.
    case 2): n+1 = {n}, n in n+1 because n in {n}.
    further succ(X) sendes an already finite set into a finite set.
    case 3): n+1 = P(n), n in n+1 because n in P(n).
    further succ(X) sendes an already finite set into a finite set.
    Q.E.D.

    But none has the property that omega = { n } contains
    itself, the proof of contradiction applies irrelevant
    of the encoding, it only makes use of the

    notion finite and infinite:

    /* provable */
    ~(omega in omega) & (Y in omega => Y finite)

    Proof:
    (Y in omega => Y finite) follows by the claim that
    omega = { n }, i.e. the least set that contains all finite
    ordinals in the corresponding encoding. If it would
    contain something infinite it would not be the least

    set that contains all finite ordinals, would have some
    extra in it. Violating the very construction of omega from
    the finite ordinals.
    Q.E.D.


    Ross Finlayson schrieb:
    On 02/19/2024 05:01 PM, Mild Shock wrote:
    The contradiction is very easy:

    Lets say X is the set of all finite ordinals.

    - observe that X is an infinite ordinal.
    - observe that if Y in X, then Y is a finite ordinal.
    - hence if X in X it would be an infinite and finite ordinal at the
    same time.
    - an X cannot be infinite and finite at the same time.
    Q.E.D:

    Ross Finlayson schrieb am Dienstag, 20. Februar 2024 um 00:04:06 UTC+1:
    There are roundabout arguments that, for example, the finite ordinals,
    as a set, consequently contain themselves, as an element. This is a
    direct compactness result.
    (Maybe that's just me.)

    Imagine if ordinals' proper model was that the successor
    was powerset, instead of just any old ordered pair.

    So, those together are the "sets that don't contain themselves",
    the sets of ordinals.

    Quantifying over those, results the "Russell set the ordinal",
    it contains itself.

    So here Y isn't necessarily a finite ordinal.

    Q.E.R.


    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Mild Shock on Thu Feb 22 14:01:09 2024
    Mild Shock schrieb am Dienstag, 20. Februar 2024 um 20:51:19 UTC+1:

    FromTheRafters schrieb am Donnerstag, 18. Januar 2024 um 13:44:43 UTC+1:
    WM explained :

    Nevertheless ***all*** unit fractions have gaps between each other. There is

    no exception.

    Yes, there are gaps in Q+ with respect to the positive reals fractional parts. Unless "***all*** unit fractions" means the set of unit
    fractions,

    Nonsense. I mean all points of unit fractions. After each one there is a
    gap. Hence NUF(x) can only increase by 1 in every case.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)