• Re: Incompleteness of Cantor's enumeration of the rational numbers

    From WM@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Mon Nov 4 12:26:26 2024
    On 03.11.2024 23:18, Jim Burns wrote:

    There aren't any neighboring intervals.
    Any two intervals have intervals between them.

    That is wrong in geometry. The measure outside of the intervals is
    infinite. Hence there exists at least one point outside. This point has
    two nearest intervals

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Mon Nov 4 09:37:30 2024
    On 11/4/2024 6:26 AM, WM wrote:
    On 03.11.2024 23:18, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/3/2024 3:38 AM, WM wrote:

    Further there are never
    two irrational numbers
    without a rational number between them.

    (Even the existence of neighbouring intervals
    is problematic.)

    There aren't any neighboring intervals.
    Any two intervals have intervals between them.

    That is wrong in geometry.
    The measure outside of the intervals is infinite.
    Hence there exists at least one point outside.
    This point has two nearest intervals

    This point,
    which is on the boundary of two intervals,
    is not two irrational points.

    Further there are never
    two irrational numbers
    without an interval between them.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Mon Nov 4 18:32:10 2024
    On 04.11.2024 15:37, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/4/2024 6:26 AM, WM wrote:
    On 03.11.2024 23:18, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/3/2024 3:38 AM, WM wrote:

    Further there are never
    two irrational numbers
    without a rational number between them.

    (Even the existence of neighbouring intervals
    is problematic.)

    There aren't any neighboring intervals.
    Any two intervals have intervals between them.

    That is wrong in geometry.
    The measure outside of the intervals is infinite.
    Hence there exists at least one point outside.
    This point has two nearest intervals

    This point,
    which is on the boundary of two intervals,
    is not two irrational points.

    You are wrong. The intervals together cover a length of less than 3. The
    whole length is infinite. Therefore there is plenty of space for a point
    not in contact with any interval.

    Further there are never
    two irrational numbers
    without an interval between them.

    Not in reality. But in the used model.
    The rationals are dense but the intervals are not. This proves that the rationals are not countable.

    Regards, WM



    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Chris M. Thomasson on Mon Nov 4 17:02:47 2024
    On 11/4/2024 3:54 PM, Chris M. Thomasson wrote:
    On 11/4/2024 6:37 AM, Jim Burns wrote:

    Further there are never
    two irrational numbers
    without an interval between them.

    Unless they equal each other? ;^)

    And thus are one, not two, points?

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Tue Nov 5 01:07:42 2024
    Am 05.11.2024 um 00:08 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:
    On 11/4/2024 2:02 PM, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/4/2024 3:54 PM, Chris M. Thomasson wrote:
    On 11/4/2024 6:37 AM, Jim Burns wrote:

    Further there are never
    two irrational numbers
    without an interval between them.

    Unless they equal each other? ;^)

    And thus are one, not two, points?


    Well, yeah in a sense.

    A = (-1, .5, 3, 7)
    B = (-1, .5, 3, 7)

    A = B = true

    Well, rather:

    "A = B" is true.

    After all, (-1, .5, 3, 7) =/= true (I'd say). :-P

    __________________________________________________

    Actually, some authors would prefer to write:

    "there are never two different irrational numbers without an [nonempty] interval between them".

    It's a matter of "style" or "precision", if you like.

    If we talk about "two" real numbers x, y [in math], usually x = y is NOT excluded.

    For example,

    for any two real numbers x, y ... bla bla

    USUALLY does not exclude x = y. [Might look strange, but is just the
    usual math lingo.]

    .
    .
    .

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Tue Nov 5 01:19:50 2024
    Am 05.11.2024 um 01:07 schrieb Moebius:

    For example,

           for any two real numbers x, y ... bla bla

    USUALLY does not exclude x = y. [Might look strange, but is just the
    usual math lingo.]

    Hint: Archimedes Plutonium had some problems with the convention. Seems
    that Jim wants to follow his lead.

    .
    .
    .

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Tue Nov 5 01:18:58 2024
    Am 05.11.2024 um 01:07 schrieb Moebius:

    For example,

           for any two real numbers x, y ... bla bla

    USUALLY does not exclude x = y. [Might look strange, but is just the
    usual math lingo.]

    Hint: Archimedes Plutonium hat some problems with the convention. Seems
    that Jim wants to follow his lead.

    .
    .
    .

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Tue Nov 5 01:20:19 2024
    Am 05.11.2024 um 01:07 schrieb Moebius:

    For example,

           for any two real numbers x, y ... bla bla

    USUALLY does not exclude x = y. [Might look strange, but is just the
    usual math lingo.]

    Hint: Archimedes Plutonium had some problems with that convention. Seems
    that Jim wants to follow his lead.

    .
    .
    .

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Tue Nov 5 03:27:35 2024
    Am 05.11.2024 um 01:20 schrieb Moebius:

    Hint: Archimedes Plutonium had some problems with that convention. Seems
    that Jim wants to follow his lead.

    Actually, I'd recommend not to follow JB, FtA and/or RD blindly.
    Sometimes they just talk nonsense.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Tue Nov 5 03:31:13 2024
    Am 05.11.2024 um 03:27 schrieb Moebius:
    Am 05.11.2024 um 01:20 schrieb Moebius:

    Hint: Archimedes Plutonium had some problems with that convention.
    Seems that Jim wants to follow his lead.

    Actually, I'd recommend not to follow JB, FtA and/or RD blindly.
    Sometimes they just talk nonsense.

    Though all of them seem to be quite bright. :-P

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Richard Damon on Sat Nov 9 12:46:01 2024
    On 08.11.2024 18:05, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/8/24 11:43 AM, WM wrote:

    The infinite of the real axis is a big supply but an as big drain.

    What "drain", the numbers exist.

    But their density is everywhere the same.

    I take it as evident that intervals of the measure 1/5 of the positive
    real axis will not, by any shuffling, cover the real axis completely,
    let alone infinitely often. I think who believes this is a deplorable
    fanatic if not a fool.

    Since 1/5 of infinity isn't a finite measure, you can't use finite logic
    to handle them.

    Since 1/5 is a finite number and for every finite set the covering is
    1/5, the limit is 1/5 too.

    You are just proving your use of broken logic.

    Chuckle. Everybody who believes that the intervals
    I(n) = [n - 1/10, n + 1/10] 0--------_1_--------_2_--------_3_--------_4_--------_5_--------_...
    could grow in length or number to cover the whole real axis is a fool or
    worse.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Sat Nov 9 12:45:05 2024
    On 08.11.2024 19:01, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/8/2024 5:18 AM, WM wrote:

    My understanding of mathematics and geometry
    is that
    reordering cannot increase the measure
    (only reduce it by overlapping).
    This is a basic axiom which
    will certainly be agreed to by
    everybody not conditioned by matheology.

    By
    "everybody not conditioned by matheology"
    you mean
    "everybody who hasn't thought much about infinity"

    Everybody who believes that the intervals
    I(n) = [n - 1/10, n + 1/10]
    could grow in length or number to cover the whole real axis is a fool or
    worse.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to joes on Sat Nov 9 12:49:44 2024
    On 08.11.2024 20:05, joes wrote:
    Am Fri, 08 Nov 2024 17:43:15 +0100 schrieb WM:

    I take it as evident that intervals of the measure 1/5 of the positive
    real axis will not, by any shuffling, cover the real axis completely,
    let alone infinitely often. I think who believes this is a deplorable
    fanatic if not a fool.
    What is the measure you are using and what does it give for the real
    axis?

    The measure is the density 1/5 for every finite segment and its limit 1/5.

    Regards, WM


    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Sat Nov 9 23:01:41 2024
    Am 09.11.2024 um 22:45 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:
    On 11/9/2024 1:42 PM, WM wrote:

    But note that Cantor's bijection between naturals and rationals does
    not insert any non-natural number into ℕ.

    Huh?!

    It confirms only that [both] sets [have the same size, actually aleph_0].

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Moebius on Sat Nov 9 22:42:01 2024
    On 08.11.2024 21:36, Moebius wrote:
    Am 08.11.2024 um 21:35 schrieb Moebius:

    What is the measure you are using and what does it give for the real
    axis?

    Ob Du es nochmal schaffst, auf diesen saudummen Scheißdreck NICHT zu
    antworten?

    Ich kann es jedenfalls nicht mehr sehen/lesen.

    Kein Wunder, weil es Deinen starken Glauben erschüttert.

    Use the intervals I(n) = [n - sqrt(2)/2^n, n + sqrt(2)/2^n]. Since n and
    q_n can be in bijection, these intervals are sufficient to cover all
    q_n. That means by clever reordering them you can cover the whole
    positive axis.

    The measure of all intervals J(n) = [n - √2/10, n + √2/10] is smaller
    than 3. If no irrationals are outside, then nothing is outside, then the measure of the real axis is smaller than 3. That is wrong. Therefore
    there are irrationals outside. That implies that rationals are outside.
    That implies that Cantor's above sequence does not contain all rationals.

    And an even more suggestive approximation:
    Replace the I(n) by intervals J(n) = [n - 1/10, n + 1/10].
    These intervals (without splitting or modifying them) can be reordered,
    to cover the whole positive axis except boundaries.

    But note that Cantor's bijection between naturals and rationals does not
    insert any non-natural number into ℕ. It confirms only that both sets
    are very large. Therefore also the above sequence of intervals keeps the
    same intervals and the same reality. And the same density 1/5 for every
    finite interval and therefore also in the limit.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Sat Nov 9 18:27:42 2024
    On 11/9/2024 6:45 AM, WM wrote:
    On 08.11.2024 19:01, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/8/2024 5:18 AM, WM wrote:

    My understanding of mathematics and geometry
    is that
    reordering cannot increase the measure
    (only reduce it by overlapping).
    This is a basic axiom which
    will certainly be agreed to by
    everybody not conditioned by matheology.

    By
    "everybody not conditioned by matheology"
    you mean
    "everybody who hasn't thought much about infinity"

    Everybody who believes that the intervals
    I(n) = [n - 1/10, n + 1/10]
    could grow in length or number
    to cover the whole real axis
    is a fool or worse.

    Our sets do not change.

    The set
    {[n-⅒,n+⅒]: n∈ℕ⁺}
    with the midpoints at
    ⟨ 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, ... ⟩
    does not _change_ to the set
    {[iₙ/jₙ-⅒,iₙ/jₙ+⅒]: n∈ℕ⁺}
    with the midpoints at
    ⟨ 1/1, 1/2, 2/1, 1/3, 2/2, ... ⟩

    ----
    Either
    all instances of a 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺 about a set
    are _only_ true or _only_ false
    or
    a set changes.


    In the first case, with the not.changing sets,
    a finite 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲 of 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀 which
    has only true.or.not.first.false 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀
    has only true 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀.

    Even though
    we are _not_ physically able to check, for each number
    in an infinite set of numbers,
    that a 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺 is true about it,
    we _are_ physically able to check, for each 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺
    in a finite 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲 of 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀,
    that it is not.first.false in that 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲.

    Also, we already know some 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀 to be true.

    Some finite 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲𝘀 of 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀 are
    known to be only true.or.not.first.false 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀,
    and thus known to be only true 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀. Un.physically.checkable numbers do not
    prevent us from knowing they're true 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀.


    In the second case, with the changing sets,
    who knows?
    Perhaps something else could be done,
    but not that.


    In any case,
    what.we.do is the first case, with
    its not.changing sets and
    its known.about infinity.

    For that reason (and more, I suspect),
    our sets do not change.

    Everybody who believes that
    the intervals
    I(n) = [n - 1/10, n + 1/10]
    could grow in length or number
    to cover the whole real axis
    is a fool or worse.

    Our sets do not change.

    Infinite sets can correspond to
    other infinite sets which,
    without much thought about infinity,
    would seem to be a different "size".

    Consider geometry.

    Similar triangles have
    corresponding sides in the same ratio.

    Consider these points, line.segments, and triangles
    in the ⟨x,y⟩.plane

    A = ⟨0,-1⟩
    B = ⟨0,0⟩
    C = ⟨x,0⟩ with 0 < x < 1
    D = ⟨1,0⟩
    E = ⟨1,y⟩ with points A C E collinear.

    △ABC and △EDC are similar
    △ABC ∼ △EDC
    μA͞B = 1
    μB͞C = x
    μE͞D = y
    μD͞C = 1-x

    Similar triangles.
    μA͞B/μB͞C = μE͞D/μD͞C
    1/x = y/(1-x)

    y = 1/x - 1
    x = 1/(y+1)

    To each point C = ⟨x,0⟩ in (0,1)×{0}
    there corresponds
    exactly one point E = ⟨1,y⟩ in {1}×(0,+∞)
    and vice versa.

    (0,1)×{0} is not stretched over {1}×(0,+∞)
    {1}×(0,+∞) is not shrunk to (0,1)×{0}
    They both _are_
    And their points correspond
    by line A͞C͞E through point A.


    Consider again the two sets of midpoints
    ⟨ 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, ... ⟩ and
    ⟨ 1/1, 1/2, 2/1, 1/3, 2/2, ... ⟩

    They both _are_
    And their points correspond
    by i/j ↦ n = (i+j-1)(i+j-2)/2+i

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Sun Nov 10 10:35:40 2024
    On 10.11.2024 00:27, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/9/2024 6:45 AM, WM wrote:

    Everybody who believes that the intervals
    I(n) = [n - 1/10, n + 1/10]
    could grow in length or number
    to cover the whole real axis
    is a fool or worse.

    Our sets do not change.

    The set
      {[n-⅒,n+⅒]: n∈ℕ⁺}
    with the midpoints at
      ⟨ 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, ... ⟩
    does not _change_ to the set
      {[iₙ/jₙ-⅒,iₙ/jₙ+⅒]: n∈ℕ⁺}
    with the midpoints at
      ⟨ 1/1, 1/2, 2/1, 1/3, 2/2, ... ⟩

    It cannot do so because the reality of the rationals is much larger than
    the reality of the naturals.

    ----
    Either
    all instances of a 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺 about a set
    are _only_ true or _only_ false
    or
    a set changes.


    In the first case, with the not.changing sets,
    a finite 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲 of 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀 which
     has only true.or.not.first.false 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀
    has only true 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀.

    But it will never complete an infinite set of claims. It will forever
    remain in the status nascendi. Therefore irrelevant for actual or
    completed infinity.

    So yes, you can shift the intervals to midpoints of every finite initial segment of the sequence 1/1, 1/2, 2/1, 1/3, 2/2, 3/1, 1/4, 2/3, 3/2,
    4/1, 1/5, 2/4, 3/3, 4/2, 5/1, 1/6, 2/5, 3/4, 4/3, 5/2, 6/1, ...

    But you must remove them from larger natural numbers. That will never
    change.

    In the second case, with the changing sets,
    who knows?
    Perhaps something else could be done,
    but not that.

    Certainly not. The intervals can neither grow in size nor in multitude.

    Infinite sets can correspond to
    other infinite sets which,
    without much thought about infinity,
    would seem to be a different "size".

    But they cannot become such sets.
    Consider again the two sets of midpoints
    ⟨ 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, ... ⟩ and
    ⟨ 1/1, 1/2, 2/1, 1/3, 2/2, ... ⟩

    They both _are_
    And their points correspond
    by i/j ↦ n = (i+j-1)(i+j-2)/2+i

    But they cannot be completely transformed into each other. That is
    prohibited by geometry. It is possible for every finite initial segment
    of the above sequence, but not possible to replace all the given
    intervals to cover all rational midpoints.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Moebius on Sun Nov 10 10:18:35 2024
    On 09.11.2024 23:01, Moebius wrote:

    It confirms only that both sets have the same size, actually aleph_0.

    True but irrelevant. For covering of all rationals by all naturals there
    must be the same reality, but that is not.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Sun Nov 10 12:49:56 2024
    On 11/10/2024 4:35 AM, WM wrote:
    On 10.11.2024 00:27, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/9/2024 6:45 AM, WM wrote:

    Everybody who believes that the intervals
    I(n) = [n - 1/10, n + 1/10]
    could grow in length or number
    to cover the whole real axis
    is a fool or worse.

    Our sets do not change.

    The set
       {[n-⅒,n+⅒]: n∈ℕ⁺}
    with the midpoints at
       ⟨ 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, ... ⟩
    does not _change_ to the set
       {[iₙ/jₙ-⅒,iₙ/jₙ+⅒]: n∈ℕ⁺}
    with the midpoints at
       ⟨ 1/1, 1/2, 2/1, 1/3, 2/2, ... ⟩

    It cannot do so because
    the reality of the rationals is much larger than
    the reality of the naturals.

    The set
    {3,4,5}
    does not _change_ to the set
    {6,7,8}
    because
    our sets do not change.

    The word 'set' has many uses.
    In some uses of 'set', sets change.
    Break a plate, and your dinnerware set changes.

    Not here.
    In this use of 'set',
    as in mathematics more generally,
    sets do not change.

    Add 3 to each of {3,4,5}.
    You do not change {3,4,5}.
    {3,4,5} continues to be {3,4,5}.
    You get a different set, {6,7,8].
    {6,7,8} has never been {3,4,5}.

    The not.changing nature of our sets is a choice,
    although it is such an ancient, universal, and
    enormously.useful choice that it is easy
    to overlook that a choice has been made.
    But our sets could have been like dinnerware sets.

    However,
    our sets are not like dinnerware sets.
    Our sets do not change.

    ⎛ I have argued for the correctness of that choice.
    ⎜ But, however good or bad my argument is,
    ⎜ that is the choice.
    ⎜ Pretending otherwise is like
    ⎝ pretending dogs are cats.

    Either
    all instances of a 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺 about a set
    are _only_ true or _only_ false
    or
    a set changes.


    In the first case, with the not.changing sets,
    a finite 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲 of 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀 which >>   has only true.or.not.first.false 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀
    has only true 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀.

    But it

    "It" refers to who or what?
    Me? You? Chuck Norris? That finite 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲?

    I will continue talking about that 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲.

    But it will never complete
    an infinite set of claims.

    We do not need an infinite 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲 of 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀 completed.
    We do not want an infinite 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲 of 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀 completed.

    For that finite 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲, because 𝗶𝘁 is finite, it is enough for us to see that
    each 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺 in 𝗶𝘁 is true.or.not.first.false.
    If we see that, we know that
    each 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺 in 𝗶𝘁 is true.

    Each 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺 in 𝗶𝘁 is true,
    even if
    a 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺 refers to one of infinitely.many.

    There may be infinitely.many possible.referents,
    but we know the 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺 is true
    because
    there are only finitely.many 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀.

    It will forever remain in the status nascendi.
    Therefore
    irrelevant for actual or completed infinity.

    A finite 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲 of 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀, each of which
    is true.or.not.first.false,
    will forever remain
    a finite 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲 of 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀, each of which
    is true.or.not.first.false.

    Infinite sets can correspond to
    other infinite sets which,
    without much thought about infinity,
    would seem to be a different "size".

    But they cannot become such sets.

    Our sets do not change.

    If matheologians would "concede" a claim which
    they do not make and have never made,
    would you (WM) stop
    filling your students' heads with that gibberish?

    Consider again the two sets of midpoints
    ⟨ 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, ... ⟩ and
    ⟨ 1/1, 1/2, 2/1, 1/3, 2/2, ... ⟩

    They both _are_
    And their points correspond
    by i/j ↦ n = (i+j-1)(i+j-2)/2+i

    But they cannot be completely transformed
    < into each other.

    Our sets do not change.

    ? That is prohibited by geometry.

    Consider geometry.

    Similar triangles have
    corresponding sides in the same ratio.

    Consider these points, line.segments, and triangles
    in the ⟨x,y⟩.plane

    A = ⟨0,-1⟩
    B = ⟨0,0⟩
    C = ⟨x,0⟩ with 0 < x < 1
    D = ⟨1,0⟩
    E = ⟨1,y⟩ with points A C E collinear.

    △ABC and △EDC are similar
    △ABC ∼ △EDC
    μA͞B = 1
    μB͞C = x
    μE͞D = y
    μD͞C = 1-x

    Similar triangles.
    μA͞B/μB͞C = μE͞D/μD͞C
    1/x = y/(1-x)

    y = 1/x - 1
    x = 1/(y+1)

    To each point C = ⟨x,0⟩ in (0,1)×{0}
    there corresponds
    exactly one point E = ⟨1,y⟩ in {1}×(0,+∞)
    and vice versa.

    (0,1)×{0} is not stretched over {1}×(0,+∞)
    {1}×(0,+∞) is not shrunk to (0,1)×{0}
    They both _are_
    And their points correspond
    by line A͞C͞E through point A.


    Consider again the two sets of midpoints
    ⟨ 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, ... ⟩ and
    ⟨ 1/1, 1/2, 2/1, 1/3, 2/2, ... ⟩

    They both _are_
    And their points correspond
    by i/j ↦ n = (i+j-1)(i+j-2)/2+i

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Mon Nov 11 09:41:41 2024
    On 10.11.2024 18:49, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/10/2024 4:35 AM, WM wrote:

    The set
      {3,4,5}
    does not _change_ to the set
      {6,7,8}
    because
    our sets do not change.

    But points or intervals in geometry can be translated on the real axis.

    Our sets do not change.

    But points or intervals in geometry can be translated on the real axis.


    In the first case, with the not.changing sets,
    a finite 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲 of 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀 which >>>   has only true.or.not.first.false 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀
    has only true 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀.

    But it

    "It" refers to who or what?

    To that finite 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲.

    But it will never complete
    an infinite set of claims.

    We do not need an infinite 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲 of 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀 completed.
    We do not want an infinite 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲 of 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀 completed.

    But you claim that _all_ fractions are in bijection with all natural
    numbers, don't you?
    It will forever remain in the status nascendi.
    Therefore
    irrelevant for actual or completed infinity.

    A finite 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲 of 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀, each of which
    is true.or.not.first.false,
    will forever remain
    a finite 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲 of 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀, each of which
    is true.or.not.first.false.

    Therefore such a sequence does not entitle you to claim infinite mappings.

    Infinite sets can correspond to
    other infinite sets which,
    without much thought about infinity,
    would seem to be a different "size".

    But they cannot become such sets.

    Our sets do not change.

    My intervals I(n) = [n - 1/10, n + 1/10] must be translated to all the midpoints 1/1, 1/2, 2/1, 1/3, 2/2, 3/1, 1/4, 2/3, 3/2, 4/1, 1/5, 2/4,
    3/3, 4/2, 5/1, 1/6, 2/5, 3/4, 4/3, 5/2, 6/1, ... if you want to
    contradict my claim.

    But they cannot be completely transformed
    < into each other.

    Our sets do not change.

    But intervals can be shifted.
    Consider again the two sets of midpoints
    ⟨ 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, ... ⟩ and
    ⟨ 1/1, 1/2, 2/1, 1/3, 2/2, ... ⟩

    They both _are_
    And their points correspond
    by i/j ↦ n = (i+j-1)(i+j-2)/2+i

    The first few terms do correspond or can be made c orresponding. That
    can be proven by translating the due intervals. But the full claim is
    nonsense because it is impossible to satisfy.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Chris M. Thomasson on Mon Nov 11 10:00:11 2024
    On 10.11.2024 21:36, Chris M. Thomasson wrote:
    On 11/10/2024 1:35 AM, WM wrote:
    On 10.11.2024 00:27, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/9/2024 6:45 AM, WM wrote:

    Everybody who believes that the intervals
    I(n) = [n - 1/10, n + 1/10]
    could grow in length or number
    to cover the whole real axis
    is a fool or worse.

    Our sets do not change.

    But intervals on the real axis can be translated.

    The set
       {[n-⅒,n+⅒]: n∈ℕ⁺}
    with the midpoints at
       ⟨ 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, ... ⟩
    does not _change_ to the set
       {[iₙ/jₙ-⅒,iₙ/jₙ+⅒]: n∈ℕ⁺}
    with the midpoints at
       ⟨ 1/1, 1/2, 2/1, 1/3, 2/2, ... ⟩

    It cannot do so because the reality of the rationals is much larger
    than the reality of the naturals.[...]

    Cantor pairing can create a unique pair of natural numbers from a single natural number. Why do think of rationals at all!?

    There it is easier to contradict Cantor, because naturals and rationals
    can be interpreted as points on the real axis.
    If pairing of naturals and rationals is possible for the complete set,
    then all intervals with natural numbers as midpoints
    I(n) = [n - 1/10, n + 1/10]
    can be translated until all rational numbers
    1/1, 1/2, 2/1, 1/3, 2/2, 3/1, 1/4, 2/3, 3/2, 4/1, 1/5, 2/4, 3/3, 4/2,
    5/1, 1/6, 2/5, 3/4, 4/3, 5/2, 6/1, ...
    are midpoints.

    Obviously that is impossible because the density 1/5 of the intervals
    can never increase. It is possible however to shift an arbitrarily large
    (a potentially infinite) number of intervals to rational midpoints.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Mon Nov 11 13:23:49 2024
    On 11/11/2024 3:41 AM, WM wrote:
    On 10.11.2024 18:49, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/10/2024 4:35 AM, WM wrote:
    On 10.11.2024 00:27, Jim Burns wrote:

    In the first case, with the not.changing sets,
    a finite 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲 of 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀 which
      has only true.or.not.first.false 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀
    has only true 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀.

    But it

    "It" refers to who or what?

    To that finite 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲.

    But it will never complete
    an infinite set of claims.

    We do not need an infinite 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲 of 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀 completed.
    We do not want an infinite 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲 of 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀 completed.

    But you claim that
    _all_ fractions are in bijection with
    all natural numbers,
    don't you?

    Yes, I claim that.
    This is one 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺:
    ⎛ All fractions are in bijection with
    ⎝ all natural numbers.

    We can peel that claim apart,
    truthfully and finitely saying what it means, and
    we can situate 𝗶𝘁 in a finite 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲 of 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀,
    each 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺 of which is true.or.not.first.false.
    Such a 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲 has only true 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀. That 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺, being in that 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲, is a true 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺.

    ⎛ I have been 𝗳𝗹𝗶𝗽𝗽𝗶𝗻𝗴 back 𝗮𝗻𝗱 𝗳𝗼𝗿𝘁𝗵 between 𝗳𝗼𝗻𝘁𝘀,
    ⎜ in an attempt to visibly mark a distinction between
    ⎜ claims as bearers of meaning and
    ⎜ 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀 as objects, as vibrations in the air,
    ⎜ smears of colored bear fat on a cave wall, bits, or pixels.

    ⎜ Finite sequences of smears of bear fat have
    ⎜ certain properties which we ("we" very broadly)
    ⎜ have learned to use in our exploration of infinity.

    ⎜ Note: that's _finite_ sequences.
    ⎜ Issues involving Scrooge McDuck and Disappearing Bob
    ⎝ do not come into play for these properties.

    It will forever remain in the status nascendi.
    Therefore
    irrelevant for actual or completed infinity.

    A finite 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲 of 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀, each of which
    is true.or.not.first.false,
    will forever remain
    a finite 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲 of 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀, each of which
    is true.or.not.first.false.

    Therefore
    such a sequence does not entitle you
    to claim infinite mappings.

    No.
    Such a 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲 does entitle me.

    A finite 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲 of 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀, each of which
    is true.or.not.first.false,
    is
    a finite 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲 of 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀, each of which
    is true.

    Infinite sets can correspond to
    other infinite sets which,
    without much thought about infinity,
    would seem to be a different "size".

    But they cannot become such sets.

    Our sets do not change.

    My intervals I(n) = [n - 1/10, n + 1/10]
    must be translated to all the midpoints
    1/1, 1/2, 2/1, 1/3, 2/2, 3/1, 1/4, 2/3, 3/2, 4/1, 1/5,
    2/4, 3/3, 4/2, 5/1, 1/6, 2/5, 3/4, 4/3, 5/2, 6/1, ...
    if you want to contradict my claim.

    Your 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀 start with "Sets change".
    If we are in the same discussion,
    they are already contradicted at that point,

    If we aren't in same discussion,
    I don't see how to respond sensibly.
    End.of.debate, I guess? If there ever was a debate?

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Mon Nov 11 13:38:56 2024
    On 11/11/2024 4:00 AM, WM wrote:
    On 10.11.2024 21:36, Chris M. Thomasson wrote:
    On 11/10/2024 1:35 AM, WM wrote:
    On 10.11.2024 00:27, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/9/2024 6:45 AM, WM wrote:

    Everybody who believes that the intervals
    I(n) = [n - 1/10, n + 1/10]
    could grow in length or number
    to cover the whole real axis
    is a fool or worse.

    Our sets do not change.

    But intervals on the real axis can be translated.

    The interval [4-⅒,4+⅒] can be translated to
    the interval [1/3-⅒,1/3+⅒].

    [4-⅒,4+⅒] does not change to [1/3-⅒,1/3+⅒]
    [4-⅒,4+⅒] will continue being after translation.
    [1/3-⅒,1/3+⅒] has never been [4-⅒,4+⅒].

    Our sets do not change.
    Everybody who believes that
    intervals could grow in length or number
    is deeply mistaken about
    what our whole project is.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Mon Nov 11 21:37:15 2024
    On 11.11.2024 19:38, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/11/2024 4:00 AM, WM wrote:

    But intervals on the real axis can be translated.

    The interval [4-⅒,4+⅒] can be translated to
    the interval [1/3-⅒,1/3+⅒].

    Obviously.

    [4-⅒,4+⅒] does not change to [1/3-⅒,1/3+⅒]
    [4-⅒,4+⅒] will continue being after translation.
    [1/3-⅒,1/3+⅒] has never been [4-⅒,4+⅒].

    That denies geometry. I use geometry. Your set theory must shy away from
    it. Geometry can be expressed by algebra. What remains for your set theory?

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Mon Nov 11 21:33:28 2024
    On 11.11.2024 19:23, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/11/2024 3:41 AM, WM wrote:

    But it will never complete
    an infinite set of claims.

    We do not need an infinite 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲 of 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀 completed.
    We do not want an infinite 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲 of 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀 completed.

    But you claim that
    _all_ fractions are in bijection with
    all natural numbers,
    don't you?

    Yes, I claim that.

    For that claim you need an infinite set of claims.

    This is one 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺:
    ⎛ All fractions are in bijection with
    ⎝ all natural numbers.

    It is wrong.

    My intervals I(n) = [n - 1/10, n + 1/10]
    must be translated to all the midpoints
    1/1, 1/2, 2/1, 1/3, 2/2, 3/1, 1/4, 2/3, 3/2, 4/1, 1/5,
    2/4, 3/3, 4/2, 5/1, 1/6, 2/5, 3/4, 4/3, 5/2, 6/1, ...
    if you want to contradict my claim.

    Your 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀 start with "Sets change".

    No, I claim that intervals can be translated. (The set of intervals
    remains constant in size and multitude.) For every finite subset this is possible.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Tue Nov 5 12:25:37 2024
    On 11/4/2024 12:32 PM, WM wrote:
    On 04.11.2024 15:37, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/4/2024 6:26 AM, WM wrote:
    On 03.11.2024 23:18, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/3/2024 3:38 AM, WM wrote:

    Further there are never
    two irrational numbers
    without a rational number between them.

    (Even the existence of neighbouring intervals
    is problematic.)

    There aren't any neighboring intervals.
    Any two intervals have intervals between them.

    That is wrong in geometry.
    The measure outside of the intervals is infinite.
    Hence there exists at least one point outside.
    This point has two nearest intervals

    This point,
    which is on the boundary of two intervals,
    is not two irrational points.

    You are wrong.
    The intervals together cover a length of less than 3.
    The whole length is infinite.
    Therefore there is plenty of space for
    a point not in contact with any interval.

    ⎛ Assuming the covering intervals are translated
    ⎜ to where they are end.to.end.to.end,
    ⎜ there is plenty of space for
    ⎝ not.in.contact exterior points.

    I mean 'exterior' in the topological sense.

    For a point x in the boundary ∂A of set A
    each open set Oₓ which holds x
    holds points in A and points not.in A

    An interior point of A is
    is in A and not.in ∂A

    An exterior point of A is
    not.in A and not.in ∂A

    ⎛ Assuming end.to.end.to.end intervals,
    ⎜ there are exterior points
    ⎝ a distance 10¹⁰⁰⁰⁰⁰ from any interval.

    However,
    the intervals aren't end.to.end.to.end.
    Their midpoints are
    the differences of ratios of countable.to,
    and not any other points.

    Each of {...,-3,-2,-1,0,1,2,3,...} is
    the midpoint of an interval.
    There can't be any exterior point
    a distance 1 from any interval.

    There can't be any exterior point
    a distance ⅟2 from any interval.
    Nor ⅟3. Nor ⅟4. Nor any positive distance.

    An exterior point which is not
    a positive distance from any interval
    is not an exterior point.

    Therefore,
    in what is _almost_ your conclusion,
    there are no exterior points.

    Instead, there are boundary points.
    For each x not.in the intervals,
    each open set Oₓ which holds x
    holds points in the intervals and
    points not.in the intervals.
    x is a boundary point.

    All of the line except at most 2³ᐟ²⋅ε is
    boundary of the intervals.


    This is a figure.ground inversion of
    how we are used to thinking about boundaries,
    the expanse of a square's interior with
    the boundary _line_ around it, ...

    ⎛ In the limit, there is no interior, too.
    ⎜ And no exterior.
    ⎝ It's only boundary.

    However, ℚ is not a square, nor is it
    close to anything else we could call a figure.

    ⎛ This is a nice example of the difference between
    ⎝ what is intuitive and what is true.

    Further there are never
    two irrational numbers
    without an interval between them.

    Not in reality. But in the used model.

    What you're saying is:
    ⎛ I (WM) am not.talking about
    ⎝ what you all are talking about.

    Which, in itself, is fine.
    Billions of other people are not.talking about
    what we all are talking about.

    However, those people talking about
    pop stars, or cosmology, or the rainy season
    aren't imagining that they're talking about
    what we all are talking about.
    Which is what you are imagining, apparently.

    The rationals are dense

    Yes.
    Each multi.point interval [x,x′] holds
    rationals.

    but the intervals are not.

    No.
    Each multi.point interval [x,x′] holds
    ε.cover intervals.

    This proves that
    the rationals are not countable.

    ⎛ i/j ↦ kᵢⱼ = (i+j-1)(i+j-2)/2+i
    ⎜ k ↦ iₖ+jₖ = ⌈(2⋅k+¼)¹ᐟ²+½⌉
    ⎜ iₖ = k-(iₖ+jₖ-1)(iₖ+jₖ-2)/2
    ⎝ jₖ = k-iₖ
    proves that
    the rationals are countable.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Tue Nov 5 13:15:59 2024
    On 11/5/2024 12:25 PM, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/4/2024 12:32 PM, WM wrote:

    [...]

    ⎛ i/j ↦ kᵢⱼ = (i+j-1)(i+j-2)/2+i
    ⎜ k ↦ iₖ+jₖ = ⌈(2⋅k+¼)¹ᐟ²+½⌉
    ⎜  iₖ = k-(iₖ+jₖ-1)(iₖ+jₖ-2)/2
    ⎝  jₖ = k-iₖ

    jₖ = (iₖ+jₖ)-iₖ

    proves that
    the rationals are countable.



    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Wed Nov 6 11:35:36 2024
    On 05.11.2024 18:25, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/4/2024 12:32 PM, WM wrote:

    The intervals together cover a length of less than 3.
    The whole length is infinite.
    Therefore there is plenty of space for
    a point not in contact with any interval.

    ⎛ Assuming the covering intervals are translated
    ⎜ to where they are end.to.end.to.end,
    ⎜ there is plenty of space for
    ⎝ not.in.contact exterior points.

    This plentiness does not change when the intervals are translated.

    I mean 'exterior' in the topological sense.

    For a point x in the boundary ∂A of set A
    each open set Oₓ which holds x
    holds points in A and points not.in A

    The intervals are closed with irrational endpoints.

    Each of {...,-3,-2,-1,0,1,2,3,...} is
    the midpoint of an interval.
    There can't be any exterior point
    a distance 1 from any interval.

    There can't be any exterior point
    a distance ⅟2 from any interval.
    Nor ⅟3. Nor ⅟4. Nor any positive distance.

    Nice try. But there are points outside of intervals, and they are closer
    to interval ends than to the interior, independent of the configuration
    of the intervals. Note that only 3/oo of the points are inside.

    An exterior point which is not
    a positive distance from any interval
    is not an exterior point.

    Positive is what you can define, but there is much more in smaller
    distance. Remember the infinitely many unit fractions within every eps >
    0 that you can define.

    Therefore,
    in what is _almost_ your conclusion,
    there are no exterior points.

    There are 3/oo of all points exterior.

    Instead, there are boundary points.
     For each x not.in the intervals,
     each open set Oₓ which holds x
     holds points in the intervals and
     points not.in the intervals.
    x is a boundary point.

    The intervals are closed
    The rationals are dense

    Yes.
    Each multi.point interval [x,x′] holds
    rationals.

    but the intervals are not.

    No.

    Therefore not all rationals are enumerated.
    ⎛ i/j ↦ kᵢⱼ = (i+j-1)(i+j-2)/2+i
    ⎜ k ↦ iₖ+jₖ = ⌈(2⋅k+¼)¹ᐟ²+½⌉
    ⎜  iₖ = k-(iₖ+jₖ-1)(iₖ+jₖ-2)/2
    ⎝  jₖ = k-iₖ
    proves that
    the rationals are countable.

    Contradiction. Something of your theory is inconsistent.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Wed Nov 6 09:22:05 2024
    On 11/6/2024 5:35 AM, WM wrote:
    On 05.11.2024 18:25, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/4/2024 12:32 PM, WM wrote:

    The intervals together cover a length of less than 3.
    The whole length is infinite.
    Therefore there is plenty of space for
    a point not in contact with any interval.

    ⎛ Assuming the covering intervals are translated
    ⎜ to where they are end.to.end.to.end,
    ⎜ there is plenty of space for
    ⎝ not.in.contact exterior points.

    This plentiness does not change
    when the intervals are translated.

    ⎛ When the intervals are end.to.end.to.end,
    ⎜ there are exterior points
    ⎝ a distance 10¹⁰⁰⁰⁰⁰ from any interval.

    Are there points 10¹⁰⁰⁰⁰⁰ from any interval
    when midpoints of intervals include
    each of {...,-3,-2,-1,0,1,2,3,...} ?

    Isn't that a plentiness which changes?

    I mean 'exterior' in the topological sense.

    For a point x in the boundary ∂A of set A
    each open set Oₓ which holds x
    holds points in A and points not.in A

    The intervals are closed with irrational endpoints.

    'Exterior' seems like a good way to say
    'not in contact'.

    It seems to me that you have a better argument
    with open intervals instead of closed,
    but let them be closed, if you like.

    Either way,
    there are no points 10¹⁰⁰⁰⁰⁰ from any interval.

    Each of {...,-3,-2,-1,0,1,2,3,...} is
    the midpoint of an interval.
    There can't be any exterior point
    a distance 1 from any interval.

    There can't be any exterior point
    a distance ⅟2 from any interval.
    Nor ⅟3. Nor ⅟4. Nor any positive distance.

    Nice try.
    But there are points outside of intervals,

    Are any of these points.outside
    ⅟2 from any interval? ⅟3? ⅟4?

    and they are closer to interval ends
    than to the interior, independent of
    the configuration of the intervals.

    Shouldn't I be pointing that out
    to you?

    If there is no point with more.than.⅟2
    between it and any midpoint,
    shouldn't there be fewer.than.no points
    with more.than.⅟2 between it and
    any closer endpoint?

    Note that
    only 3/oo of the points are inside.

    Yes, less than 2³ᐟ²⋅ε

    If the intervals were open,
    all of that would be "inside"
    in the interior of their union.

    Of the rest,
    none of it is more.than.⅟2 from any interval.

    An exterior point which is not
    a positive distance from any interval
    is not an exterior point.

    Positive is what you can define,

    Positive ℕ⁺ holds countable.to from.1
    Positive ℚ⁺ holds ratios of elements of ℕ⁺
    Positive ℝ⁺ holds points.between.splits of Q⁺

    but there is much more in smaller distance.

    Distances are positive or zero.
    Two distinct points are a positive distance apart.

    Remember the infinitely many unit fractions
    within every eps > 0 that you can define.

    For each of the infinitely.many unit fractions
    there is no point a distance of that unit fraction
    or more from any interval.

    Therefore,
    in what is _almost_ your conclusion,
    there are no exterior points.

    There are 3/oo of all points exterior.

    Did you intend to write "interior"?

    An exterior point is in
    an open interval holding no rational.

    There are no
    open intervals holding no rational.

    There are no exterior points.

    However,
    there are boundary points.
    All but 2³ᐟ²⋅ε are boundary points.

    Instead, there are boundary points.
      For each x not.in the intervals,
      each open set Oₓ which holds x
      holds points in the intervals and
      points not.in the intervals.
    x is a boundary point.

    The intervals are closed

    We are only told
    that Oₓ is an open set holding x
    not that Oₓ is one of the ε.cover of ℚ
    The question is whether x is a boundary point.

    The rationals are dense

    Yes.
    Each multi.point interval [x,x′] holds
    rationals.

    but the intervals are not.

    No.
    Each multi.point interval [x,x′] holds
    ε.cover intervals.

    Therefore not all rationals are enumerated.

    Explain why.

    ⎛ i/j ↦ kᵢⱼ = (i+j-1)(i+j-2)/2+i
    ⎜ k ↦ iₖ+jₖ = ⌈(2⋅k+¼)¹ᐟ²+½⌉
    ⎜  iₖ = k-(iₖ+jₖ-1)(iₖ+jₖ-2)/2
    ⎜ jₖ = (iₖ+jₖ)-iₖ
    ⎝ (iₖ+jₖ-1)(iₖ+jₖ-2)/2+iₖ = k
    proves that
    the rationals are countable.

    Contradiction.

    It contradicts a non.empty exterior.
    It doesn't contradict an almost.all boundary.

    Something of your theory is inconsistent.

    Your intuition is disturbed by
    an almost.all boundary.

    Disturbed intuitions and inconsistencies
    are different.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Wed Nov 6 17:24:25 2024
    On 06.11.2024 15:22, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/6/2024 5:35 AM, WM wrote:
    On 05.11.2024 18:25, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/4/2024 12:32 PM, WM wrote:

    The intervals together cover a length of less than 3.
    The whole length is infinite.
    Therefore there is plenty of space for
    a point not in contact with any interval.

    ⎛ Assuming the covering intervals are translated
    ⎜ to where they are end.to.end.to.end,
    ⎜ there is plenty of space for
    ⎝ not.in.contact exterior points.

    This plentiness does not change
    when the intervals are translated.

    ⎛ When the intervals are end.to.end.to.end,
    ⎜ there are exterior points
    ⎝ a distance 10¹⁰⁰⁰⁰⁰ from any interval.

    Are there points 10¹⁰⁰⁰⁰⁰ from any interval
    when midpoints of intervals include
    each of {...,-3,-2,-1,0,1,2,3,...} ?

    In fact, when ordered that way they include only intervals around the
    positive integers because the natural numbers already are claimed to be indexing all fractions. (Hence not more intervals are required.)

    Isn't that a plentiness which changes?

    No.

    The intervals are closed with irrational endpoints.

    'Exterior' seems like a good way to say
    'not in contact'.

    Every point outside is not an endpoint and is not in contact.

    It seems to me that you have a better argument
    with open intervals instead of closed,
    but let them be closed, if you like.

    Closed intervals with irrational endpoints prohibit any point outside.
    Boundary or not! Of course there are points outside. This shows that the rationals are not countable.

    Either way,
    there are no points 10¹⁰⁰⁰⁰⁰ from any interval.

    Each of {...,-3,-2,-1,0,1,2,3,...} is
    the midpoint of an interval.
    There can't be any exterior point
    a distance 1 from any interval.

    There can't be any exterior point
    a distance ⅟2 from any interval.
    Nor ⅟3. Nor ⅟4. Nor any positive distance.

    Nice try.
    But there are points outside of intervals,

    Are any of these points.outside
     ⅟2 from any interval? ⅟3? ⅟4?

    If not, then the measure of the real axis is less than 3.>
    If there is no point with more.than.⅟2
    between it and any midpoint,

    In your first configuration, there are points with more than 1/3 between
    it and a midpoint. If the intervals are translated, the distance may
    become smaller for some points but necessarily becomes larger for
    others. Shuffling does not increase the sum of the intervals.
    There are 3/oo of all points exterior.

    Did you intend to write "interior"?

    Of course.

    An exterior point is in
    an open interval holding no rational.

    and therefore no irrational either.

    There are no
    open intervals holding no rational.

    That is true but shows that not all rationals are caught in intervals
    because they are not countabel.

    There are no exterior points.

    If and only if all rationals could be enumerated!
    That has been disproved.

    Therefore not all rationals are enumerated.

    Explain why.

    There are rationals outside of all intervals in the infinite space
    outside of the intervals covering less than 3 of the infinite space.

    Contradiction.

    It contradicts a non.empty exterior.
    It doesn't contradict an almost.all boundary.

    There is no difference between outside, exterior and you "boundary
    points". The latter are only created by your inability to define small
    enough intervals.

    Something of your theory is inconsistent.

    Your intuition is disturbed by
    an almost.all boundary.

    No. Your boundary is nonsense. If a point is outside of an interval,
    then it is irrelevant whether you can construct an open interval not
    covering points of the interior. It is outside.

    Disturbed intuitions and inconsistencies
    are different.

    Tricks relating to your inability are not acceptable.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Wed Nov 6 17:36:43 2024
    On 05.11.2024 18:25, Jim Burns wrote:


    Instead, there are boundary points.
     For each x not.in the intervals,
     each open set Oₓ which holds x
     holds points in the intervals and
     points not.in the intervals.
    x is a boundary point.

    For every definable x we can decide whether it is inside the interval
    including its endpoints or outside. No open intervals are necesseary or
    useful. Your trick is cunning bot not accepted.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Wed Nov 6 14:08:58 2024
    On 11/6/2024 11:24 AM, WM wrote:
    On 06.11.2024 15:22, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/6/2024 5:35 AM, WM wrote:

    The intervals are closed with irrational endpoints.

    'Exterior' seems like a good way to say
    'not in contact'.

    Every point outside is not an endpoint

    Yes.

    and is not in contact.

    You don't know that.

    The _union_ of
    arbitrarily.many _open_ sets
    is an open set.

    However,
    the _union_ of
    these infinitely.many _closed_ intervals
    with irrational endpoints
    is an open interval
    with rational endpoints.

    ⋃{[⅟(k+√2),1-⅟(k+√2)]: k∈ℕ} = (0,1)

    Recall that
    0 = glb.{⅟(k+√2): k∈ℕ}
    0 ∉ {⅟(k+√2): k∈ℕ}
    1 = lub.{1-⅟(k+√2): k∈ℕ}
    1 ∉ {1-⅟(k+√2): k∈ℕ}

    Something of your theory is inconsistent.

    Your intuition is disturbed by
    an almost.all boundary.

    No. Your boundary is nonsense.

    "My" boundary is a definition.
    It states what we take the term "boundary" to mean.
    The open sets involved exist or not.exist,
    independently of whether we use or not.use
    the term "boundary".

    The term "boundary" helps clarify
    what I admit is a confusing situation.
    _Of course_ you (WM) object to clarity.
    Clarity is your nemesis.

    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Boundary_(topology)
    ⎛ It is the set of points p ∈ X such that
    ⎜ every neighborhood of p contains
    ⎜ at least one point of S and
    ⎝ at least one point not of S :

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Wed Nov 6 20:50:23 2024
    On 06.11.2024 20:08, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/6/2024 11:24 AM, WM wrote:
    On 06.11.2024 15:22, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/6/2024 5:35 AM, WM wrote:

    The intervals are closed with irrational endpoints.

    'Exterior' seems like a good way to say
    'not in contact'.

    Every point outside is not an endpoint

    Yes.

    and is not in contact.

    You don't know that.

    From every positive point we know that it is not 0 and not in contact
    with (-oo, 0]. Same for every point not in an interval.

    The _union_ of
    arbitrarily.many _open_ sets
    is an open set.
    However,
    the _union_ of
    these infinitely.many _closed_ intervals
     with irrational endpoints
    is an open interval
     with rational endpoints.

    We use only intervals, not limits. A point is in an interval or it is not.

    "My" boundary is a definition.

    But it is irrelevant here like the offside rule in soccer.

    The term "boundary" helps clarify
    what I admit is a confusing situation.

    No,it is not confusing at all. For every interval we can decide whether
    a poin is inside or outside.
    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Boundary_(topology)
    ⎛ It is the set of points p ∈ X such that
    ⎜ every neighborhood of p contains
    ⎜ at least one point of S and
    ⎝ at least one point not of S :

    But there are no points outside of intervals because, if Cantor has
    enumerated all rationals, then all rationals are caught and irrationals
    cannot be outside. Therefore a boundary is excluded. Points p can only
    exist insideof intervals.

    Further: For every point x and for every interval we can find x - e
    where e is the endpoint of an interval. No boundary is useful, in
    particular because the infinite positive real axis except 3 unit
    intervals cannot be covered by the blurred boundary.

    Regards, WM



    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Wed Nov 6 15:20:22 2024
    On 11/6/2024 2:50 PM, WM wrote:
    On 06.11.2024 20:08, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/6/2024 11:24 AM, WM wrote:
    On 06.11.2024 15:22, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/6/2024 5:35 AM, WM wrote:

    The intervals are closed with irrational endpoints.

    'Exterior' seems like a good way to say
    'not in contact'.

    Every point outside is not an endpoint

    Yes.

    and is not in contact.

    You don't know that.

    From every positive point we know that
    it is not 0 and
    not in contact with (-oo, 0].
    Same for every point not in an interval.

    Is 0 "not in contact with" [-1,0) ⊆ ℝ
    where
    ℝ is points.between.splits of ℚ
    ℚ is differences of ℚ⁺
    ℚ⁺ is ratios of ℕ⁺
    ℕ⁺ is countable.to from 1
    ?

    The _union_ of
    arbitrarily.many _open_ sets
    is an open set.
    However,
    the _union_ of
    these infinitely.many _closed_ intervals
      with irrational endpoints
    is an open interval
      with rational endpoints.

    We use only intervals, not limits.
    A point is in an interval or it is not.

    A point can be not.in the closure of each
    of infinitely.many sets
    and also in the closure of their union.

    An ε.cover of ℚ holds infinitely.many sets.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Thu Nov 7 01:00:11 2024
    Am 06.11.2024 um 21:59 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:
    On 11/6/2024 8:36 AM, WM wrote:
    On 05.11.2024 18:25, Jim Burns wrote:


    Instead, there are boundary points.
      For each x not.in the intervals,
      each open set Oₓ which holds x
      holds points in the intervals and
      points not.in the intervals.
    x is a boundary point.

    For every definable x we can decide whether it is inside the interval
    including its endpoints or outside. No open intervals are necesseary
    or useful. Your trick is cunning bot not accepted.

    For any z we can decide if its inside or outside of <whatever>

    Hint: In contrast to WM's psychomath we do not have to "decide" if a
    number z is inside or outside of a certain interval. It IS EITHER inside
    of the interval OR NOT. (No "decision" necessary.)

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Moebius on Thu Nov 7 10:04:42 2024
    On 07.11.2024 01:00, Moebius wrote:

    Hint: we do not have to "decide" if a
    number z is inside or outside of a certain interval. It IS EITHER inside
    of the interval OR NOT. (No "decision" necessary.)

    And when we cover the real axis by intervals --------_1_--------_2_--------_3_--------_4_--------_5_--------_...
    J(n) = [n - √2/10, n + √2/10]
    in a clever way, then all rational numbers are midpoints of intervals
    and no irrational number is outside of all intervals.
    That is the power of infinity!!!

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Thu Nov 7 09:46:05 2024
    On 06.11.2024 21:20, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/6/2024 2:50 PM, WM wrote:

    From every positive point we know that
    it is not 0 and
    not in contact with (-oo, 0].
    Same for every point not in an interval.

    Is 0 "not in contact with" [-1,0) ⊆ ℝ

    0 is not a positive point.
    A point can be not.in the closure of each
    of infinitely.many sets
    and also in the closure of their union.

    These ideas are irrelevant because we can use the following estimation
    that should convince everyone:

    Use the intervals I(n) = [n - sqrt(2)/2^n, n + sqrt(2)/2^n]. Since n and
    q_n can be in bijection, these intervals are sufficient to cover all
    q_n. That means by clever reordering them you can cover the whole
    positive axis except "boundaries".

    And an even more suggestive approximation:
    Replace the I(n) by intervals J(n) = [n - 1/10, n + 1/10] (as soon as
    the I(n) are smaller than 2/10).
    These intervals (without splitting or modifying them) can be reordered,
    to cover the whole positive axis except boundaries.
    Reordering them again in an even cleverer way, they can be used to cover
    the whole positive and negative real axes except boundaries. And
    reordering them again, they can be used to cover 100 real axes in parallel.

    Even using only intervals J(P) = [p - 1/10, p + 1/10] where p is a prime
    number can accomplish the same.

    Is this the power of infinity?
    Or is it only the inertia of brains conquered by matheology?

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Thu Nov 7 06:18:37 2024
    On 11/7/2024 3:46 AM, WM wrote:
    On 06.11.2024 21:20, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/6/2024 2:50 PM, WM wrote:

    From every positive point we know that
    it is not 0 and
    not in contact with (-oo, 0].
    Same for every point not in an interval.

    Is 0 "not in contact with" [-1,0) ⊆ ℝ

    0 is not a positive point.

    I want to find out from you (WM)
    what "not in contact with" means.

    For a point
    in the boundary but not in the set,
    is it "not in contact with" the set?
    Is it "in contact with" the set?

    Point x′ is in the boundary of set S
    iff
    each interval [x,x″] such that
    x′ is in its interior, x < x′ < x″,
    holds points in S and points not.in S

    For S = [-1,0) and x = 0
    each [x,x″] such that x < 0 < x″
    holds points in [-1,0) and points not.in [-1,0)

    0 is in the boundary of [-1,0)
    Is 0 "in contact with" [-1,0) ?

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Thu Nov 7 14:03:23 2024
    On 07.11.2024 12:18, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/7/2024 3:46 AM, WM wrote:

    I want to find out from you (WM)
    what "not in contact with" means.

    For a point
    in the boundary but not in the set,
    is it "not in contact with" the set?
    Is it "in contact with" the set?

    It is not in contact with the set. "For every eps" is not a valid
    criterion because eps depends on what you can define, not on what
    exists. The endpoint is in contact with the set.

    0 is in the boundary of [-1,0) > Is 0 "in contact with" [-1,0) ?

    I am not an expert on these things. I would say it is in contact with
    the set because a point of the set is next to it. The closure of a set
    is in contact with the set.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Thu Nov 7 10:29:03 2024
    On 11/7/2024 8:03 AM, WM wrote:
    On 07.11.2024 12:18, Jim Burns wrote:

    I want to find out from you (WM)
    what "not in contact with" means.

    For a point
    in the boundary but not in the set,
    is it "not in contact with" the set?
    Is it "in contact with" the set?

    It is not in contact with the set.
    "For every eps" is not a valid criterion
    because eps depends on
    what you can define, not on what exists.
    The endpoint is in contact with the set.

    0 is in the boundary of [-1,0)
    Is 0 "in contact with" [-1,0) ?

    I am not an expert on these things.
    I would say
    it is in contact with the set
    because a point of the set is next to it.
    The closure of a set is in contact with the set.

    That's what I thought you meant.
    If, otherwise,
    "not in contact with" meant "not in",
    the easier, clearer way to say that is "not in".
    Thank you for clarifying.

    ----
    ⎛ The boundary of a set S holds
    ⎜ those points x′ such that
    ⎜ each interval [x,x″] with
    ⎜ x′ in its interior, x < x′ < x″,
    ⎝ holds points in S and points not.in S

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Thu Nov 7 18:59:02 2024
    On 07.11.2024 16:29, Jim Burns wrote:

    ⎛ The boundary of a set S holds
    ⎜ those points x′ such that
    ⎜ each interval [x,x″] with
    ⎜ x′ in its interior, x < x′ <  x″,
    ⎝ holds points in S and points not.in S

    Do you think you need the boundary in my last example?

    When we cover the real axis by intervals --------_1_--------_2_--------_3_--------_4_--------_5_--------_...
    J(n) = [n - √2/10, n + √2/10]
    and shuffle them in a clever way, then all rational numbers are
    midpoints of intervals and no irrational number is outside of all intervals.
    Do you believe this???

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Thu Nov 7 14:06:25 2024
    On 11/7/2024 3:46 AM, WM wrote:
    On 06.11.2024 21:20, Jim Burns wrote:

    [...]

    Use the intervals
    I(n) = [n - sqrt(2)/2^n, n + sqrt(2)/2^n].
    Since n and q_n can be in bijection,
    these intervals are sufficient to cover all q_n.
    That means by clever reordering them
    you can cover the whole positive axis
    except "boundaries".

    Yes. Except boundaries.
    ⎛ The boundary of a set S holds
    ⎜ those points x′ such that
    ⎜ each interval [x,x″] with
    ⎜ x′ in its interior, x < x′ < x″,
    ⎝ holds points in S and points not.in S

    ℝ is the set of points.between.splits of ℚ

    Consider ℝ.points x < x″ with
    their foresplits F F″ and hindsplits H H″ of ℚ
    F ᵉᵃᶜʰ< x ≤ᵉᵃᶜʰ H and F∪H = ℚ
    F″ ᵉᵃᶜʰ< x ≤ᵉᵃᶜʰ H″ and F″∪H″ = ℚ

    F ≠⊂ F″
    H ⊃≠ H″
    F″∩H ≠ {}

    F″∩H is
    the set of rationals between x and x″
    F″∩H is not empty, because x < x″

    Each ℝ.interval [x,x″] holds rationals.


    There is an enumeration of ℚ⁺
    the set of ratios of ℕ⁺ countable.to from.1
    ⎛ i/j ↦ kᵢⱼ = (i+j-1)(i+j-2)/2+i
    ⎜ k ↦ iₖ/jₖ
    ⎜ iₖ+jₖ = ⌈(2⋅k+¼)¹ᐟ²+½⌉
    ⎜ iₖ = k-((iₖ+jₖ)-1)((iₖ+jₖ)-2)/2
    ⎜ jₖ = (iₖ+jₖ)-iₖ
    ⎝ (iₖ+jₖ-1)(iₖ+jₖ-2)/2+iₖ = k

    ⎛ If you must have ℚ instead of ℚ⁺
    ⎜ I can add bells and whistles to the enumeration.
    ⎜ It won't significantly change the argument,
    ⎝ but it will give you more squiggles to look at.

    There is an ε.cover of ℚ⁺
    -- not scrunched together, but spread across ℚ⁺ --
    of closed intervals with irrational endpoints
    ⎛ ε.cover = {[x⁽ᵋₖ,xᵋ⁾ₖ]:k∈ℕ⁺}
    ⎜ x⁽ᵋₖ = iₖ/jₖ-2ᵏ⁻¹ᐟ²⋅ε
    ⎝ xᵋ⁾ₖ = iₖ/jₖ+2ᵏ⁻¹ᐟ²⋅ε

    Consider a point xᵒᵘᵗ not.in the ε.cover.
    xᵒᵘᵗ ∉ ⋃(ε.cover)
    For each interval [x,x″] such that x < xᵒᵘᵗ < x″
    there are points in ℚ⁺ which are also in ⋃(ε.cover)
    there are points not.in ⋃(ε.cover): xᵒᵘᵗ

    xᵒᵘᵗ is in the boundary of ⋃(ε.cover)

    That means by clever reordering them
    you can cover the whole positive axis
    except "boundaries".

    Yes.
    In that clever re.ordering, not scrunched together,
    the whole positive axis
    is in the ε.cover or
    in the boundary of the ε.cover.

    A boundary so much more than its set
    is not what we think of as "boundary"
    but ℚ⁺ is not what we thing of as "interval".

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Thu Nov 7 20:33:09 2024
    On 07.11.2024 20:06, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/7/2024 3:46 AM, WM wrote:

    That means by clever reordering them
    you can cover the whole positive axis
    except "boundaries".

    Yes.
    In that clever re.ordering, not scrunched together,
    the whole positive axis
    is in the ε.cover or
    in the boundary of the ε.cover.

    It is impossible however to cover the real axis (even many times) by the intervals
    J(n) = [n - 1/10, n + 1/10].
    No boundaries are involved because every interval of length 1/5 contains infinitely many rationals and therefore is essentially covered by
    infinitely many intervals of length 1/5 - if Cantor is right.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Thu Nov 7 15:32:20 2024
    On 11/7/2024 12:59 PM, WM wrote:
    On 07.11.2024 16:29, Jim Burns wrote:

    ⎛ The boundary of a set S holds
    ⎜ those points x′ such that
    ⎜ each interval [x,x″] with
    ⎜ x′ in its interior, x < x′ < x″,
    ⎝ holds points in S and points not.in S

    Do you think you need the boundary in my last example?

    When we cover the real axis by intervals --------_1_--------_2_--------_3_--------_4_--------_5_--------_...
    J(n) = [n - √2/10, n + √2/10]
    and shuffle them in a clever way,
    then all rational numbers are midpoints of intervals
    and no irrational number is outside of all intervals.

    No irrational is not in contact with
    the union of intervals.
    That's different from
    ⎛ no irrational is not covered by
    ⎝ the union of intervals.
    The first is true, the second is false.

    The first is true because,
    for each irrational x,
    each interval of which x is in its interior
    holds rationals, and
    rationals are points in the union of intervals.

    There is an enumeration of ℚ⁺
    the set of ratios of ℕ⁺ countable.to from.1
    ⎛ i/j ↦ kᵢⱼ = (i+j-1)(i+j-2)/2+i
    ⎜ k ↦ iₖ/jₖ
    ⎜ iₖ+jₖ = ⌈(2⋅k+¼)¹ᐟ²+½⌉
    ⎜ iₖ = k-((iₖ+jₖ)-1)((iₖ+jₖ)-2)/2
    ⎜ jₖ = (iₖ+jₖ)-iₖ
    ⎝ (iₖ+jₖ-1)(iₖ+jₖ-2)/2+iₖ = k

    #x#ₖ is the -k.th digit of
    the decimal representation of real number x

    d is a Cantorian anti.diagonal of
    the Cantorian rational.list ⟨iₖ/jₖ⟩
    #d#ₖ = (#iₖ/jₖ#ₖ+5) mod 10

    The closest that d and iₖ/jₖ could be
    would be if, miraculously, all prior digits matched.
    Even with that and the worst case for following digits,
    |d-iₖ/jₖ| ≥ 4×10⁻ᵏ

    Consider this ε.cover of
    closed intervals with irrational endpoints.
    ⎛ ε.cover = {[x⁽ᵋₖ,xᵋ⁾ₖ]:k∈ℕ⁺}
    ⎜ x⁽ᵋₖ = iₖ/jₖ-2¹ᐟ²⋅10⁻ᵏ
    ⎝ xᵋ⁾ₖ = iₖ/jₖ+2¹ᐟ²⋅10⁻ᵏ

    The infinite sum of measures = 2³ᐟ²/9
    d is _not in contact with_ each interval.

    However,
    each interval of which d is in its interior
    holds rationals, which are points in ⋃(ε.cover)
    Thus, d is _in contact with_ ⋃(ε.cover)
    but not with any of its intervals.

    Do you believe this???

    Don't you believe this???

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Thu Nov 7 22:06:39 2024
    On 07.11.2024 21:32, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/7/2024 12:59 PM, WM wrote:

    When we cover the real axis by intervals
    --------_1_--------_2_--------_3_--------_4_--------_5_--------_...
    J(n) = [n - √2/10, n + √2/10]
    and shuffle them in a clever way,
    then all rational numbers are midpoints of intervals
    and no irrational number is outside of all intervals.

    No irrational is not in contact with
    the union of intervals.

    On the contrary, every irrational (and every rational) is in contact
    with infinitely many intervals, because in the length of √2/5 there are infinitely many rationals and therefore infinitely many midpoints of
    intervals.

    The first is true because,
    for each irrational x,
    each interval of which x is in its interior
    holds rationals, and
    rationals are points in the union of intervals.

    There is an enumeration of ℚ⁺

    If it is true, then the measure of the intervals of 3/10 of the real
    axis grows to infinitely many times the real axis.

    The infinite sum of measures = 2³ᐟ²/9
    d is _not in contact with_ each interval.

    The intervals are shifted such that every rational number is the
    midpoint of an interval. Every point p on the real axis is covered by infinitely many intervals, namely by all intervals having midpoint
    rationals q with
    d - √2/10 < q < d + √2/10.

    However,
    each interval of which d is in its interior
    holds rationals, which are points in ⋃(ε.cover)
    Thus, d is _in contact with_ ⋃(ε.cover)
    but not with any of its intervals.

    The intervals have length √2/5. There is no ε.

    Do you believe this???

    Don't you believe this???

    No, it violates mathematics and logic when by reordering the measure of
    a set of disjunct intervals grows.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Thu Nov 7 18:29:49 2024
    On 11/7/2024 2:33 PM, WM wrote:
    On 07.11.2024 20:06, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/7/2024 3:46 AM, WM wrote:
    On 07.11.2024 16:29, Jim Burns wrote:

    and shuffle them in a clever way,
    then all rational numbers are midpoints of intervals
    and no irrational number is outside of all intervals.

    That means by clever reordering them
    you can cover the whole positive axis
    except "boundaries".

    "Except boundaries" is the key phrase.

    Yes.
    In that clever re.ordering, not scrunched together,
    the whole positive axis
    is in the ε.cover or
    in the boundary of the ε.cover.

    It is impossible however to cover
    the real axis (even many times) by
    the intervals
    J(n) = [n - 1/10, n + 1/10].

    Those are not the cleverly.re.ordered intervals.
    These are:

    ⎛ ε.cover = {[x⁽ᵋₖ,xᵋ⁾ₖ]:k∈ℕ⁺}
    ⎜ x⁽ᵋₖ = iₖ/jₖ-2¹ᐟ²⋅10⁻ᵏ
    ⎝ xᵋ⁾ₖ = iₖ/jₖ+2¹ᐟ²⋅10⁻ᵏ

    There is an enumeration of ℚ⁺
    the set of ratios of ℕ⁺ countable.to from.1
    ⎛ i/j ↦ kᵢⱼ = (i+j-1)(i+j-2)/2+i
    ⎜ k ↦ iₖ/jₖ
    ⎜ iₖ+jₖ = ⌈(2⋅k+¼)¹ᐟ²+½⌉
    ⎜ iₖ = k-((iₖ+jₖ)-1)((iₖ+jₖ)-2)/2
    ⎜ jₖ = (iₖ+jₖ)-iₖ
    ⎝ (iₖ+jₖ-1)(iₖ+jₖ-2)/2+iₖ = k

    d is a Cantorian anti.diagonal of
    the Cantorian rational.list ⟨iₖ/jₖ⟩
    #d#ₖ = (#iₖ/jₖ#ₖ+5) mod 10

    #x#ₖ is the -k.th digit of
    the decimal representation of real number x

    For each interval [x⁽ᵋₖ,xᵋ⁾ₖ] in ε.cover
    d is "not in contact with" [x⁽ᵋₖ,xᵋ⁾ₖ]

    However,
    d is "in contact with" ⋃(ε.cover)

    d is in the closure of ⋃(ε.cover)
    and not.in the closure of any of its intervals.

    No boundaries are involved because
    every interval of length 1/5 contains
    infinitely many rationals and
    therefore is essentially covered by
    infinitely many intervals of length 1/5
    - if Cantor is right.

    I haven't claimed anything at all about
    your all.1/5.length intervals.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Fri Nov 8 11:18:47 2024
    On 08.11.2024 00:29, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/7/2024 2:33 PM, WM wrote:

    It is impossible however to cover
    the real axis (even many times) by
    the intervals
    J(n) = [n - 1/10, n + 1/10].

    Those are not the cleverly.re.ordered intervals.
    They are the intervals that we start with.
    No boundaries are involved because
    every interval of length 1/5 contains infinitely many rationals and
    therefore is essentially covered by infinitely many intervals of
    length 1/5
    - if Cantor is right.

    I haven't claimed anything at all about
    your all.1/5.length intervals.
    Then consider the two only alternatives: Either by reordering (one after
    the other or simultaneously) the measure of these intervals can grow
    from 1/10 of the real axis to infinitely many times the real axis, or not.

    My understanding of mathematics and geometry is that reordering cannot
    increase the measure (only reduce it by overlapping). This is a basic
    axiom which will certainly be agreed to by everybody not conditioned by matheology. But there is also an analytical proof: Every reordering of
    any finite set of intervals does not increase their measure. The limit
    of a constant sequence is this constant however.

    This geometrical consequence of Cantor's theory has, to my knowledge,
    never been discussed. By the way I got the idea after a posting of
    yours: Each of {...,-3,-2,-1,0,1,2,3,...} is the midpoint of an interval.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Fri Nov 8 07:28:53 2024
    On 11/8/24 5:18 AM, WM wrote:
    On 08.11.2024 00:29, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/7/2024 2:33 PM, WM wrote:

    It is impossible however to cover
    the real axis (even many times) by
    the intervals
    J(n) = [n - 1/10, n + 1/10].

    Those are not the cleverly.re.ordered intervals.
    They are the intervals that we start with.
    No boundaries are involved because
    every interval of length 1/5 contains infinitely many rationals and
    therefore is essentially covered by infinitely many intervals of
    length 1/5
    - if Cantor is right.

    I haven't claimed anything at all about
    your all.1/5.length intervals.
    Then consider the two only alternatives: Either by reordering (one after
    the other or simultaneously) the measure of these intervals can grow
    from 1/10 of the real axis to infinitely many times the real axis, or not.

    My understanding of mathematics and geometry is that reordering cannot increase the measure (only reduce it by overlapping). This is a basic
    axiom which will certainly be agreed to by everybody not conditioned by matheology. But there is also an analytical proof: Every reordering of
    any finite set of intervals does not increase their measure. The limit
    of a constant sequence is this constant however.

    This geometrical consequence of Cantor's theory has, to my knowledge,
    never been discussed. By the way I got the idea after a posting of
    yours: Each of {...,-3,-2,-1,0,1,2,3,...} is the midpoint of an interval.

    Regards, WM


    which makes the error that the properties of finite objects apply to the infinite objects, which isn't true, and what just breaks your logic.

    You take it as a given, but that just means that your logic is unable to actually handle the infinite.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Richard Damon on Fri Nov 8 17:43:15 2024
    On 08.11.2024 13:28, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/8/24 5:18 AM, WM wrote:

    My understanding of mathematics and geometry is that reordering cannot
    increase the measure (only reduce it by overlapping). This is a basic
    axiom which will certainly be agreed to by everybody not conditioned
    by matheology. But there is also an analytical proof: Every reordering
    of any finite set of intervals does not increase their measure. The
    limit of a constant sequence is this constant however.

    This geometrical consequence of Cantor's theory has, to my knowledge,
    never been discussed. By the way I got the idea after a posting of
    yours: Each of {...,-3,-2,-1,0,1,2,3,...} is the midpoint of an interval.

    which makes the error that the properties of finite objects apply to the infinite objects, which isn't true, and what just breaks your logic.

    The infinite of the real axis is a big supply but an as big drain.

    You take it as a given, but that just means that your logic is unable to actually handle the infinite.

    I take it as evident that intervals of the measure 1/5 of the positive
    real axis will not, by any shuffling, cover the real axis completely,
    let alone infinitely often. I think who believes this is a deplorable
    fanatic if not a fool.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Fri Nov 8 12:05:40 2024
    On 11/8/24 11:43 AM, WM wrote:
    On 08.11.2024 13:28, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/8/24 5:18 AM, WM wrote:

    My understanding of mathematics and geometry is that reordering
    cannot increase the measure (only reduce it by overlapping). This is
    a basic axiom which will certainly be agreed to by everybody not
    conditioned by matheology. But there is also an analytical proof:
    Every reordering of any finite set of intervals does not increase
    their measure. The limit of a constant sequence is this constant
    however.

    This geometrical consequence of Cantor's theory has, to my knowledge,
    never been discussed. By the way I got the idea after a posting of
    yours: Each of {...,-3,-2,-1,0,1,2,3,...} is the midpoint of an
    interval.

    which makes the error that the properties of finite objects apply to
    the infinite objects, which isn't true, and what just breaks your logic.

    The infinite of the real axis is a big supply but an as big drain.

    What "drain", the numbers exist.


    You take it as a given, but that just means that your logic is unable
    to actually handle the infinite.

    I take it as evident that intervals of the measure 1/5 of the positive
    real axis will not, by any shuffling, cover the real axis completely,
    let alone infinitely often. I think who believes this is a deplorable
    fanatic if not a fool.

    Regards, WM


    Since 1/5 of infinity isn't a finite measure, you can't use finite logic
    to handle them.

    You are just proving your use of broken logic.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Fri Nov 8 13:01:08 2024
    On 11/8/2024 5:18 AM, WM wrote:
    On 08.11.2024 00:29, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/7/2024 2:33 PM, WM wrote:

    It is impossible however to cover
    the real axis (even many times) by
    the intervals
    J(n) = [n - 1/10, n + 1/10].

    Those are not the cleverly.re.ordered intervals.

    They are the intervals that we start with.

    Starting intervals
    {[n-⅒,n+⅒]: n∈ℕ⁺}
    with midpoints
    { 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, ... }
    and cleverly.shifted intervals
    {[iₙ/jₙ-⅒,iₙ/jₙ+⅒]: n∈ℕ⁺}
    with midpoints
    { 1/1, 1/2, 2/1, 1/3, 2/2, ... }

    ⎛ n ↦ iₙ/jₙ
    ⎜ iₙ+jₙ = ⌈(2⋅n+¼)¹ᐟ²+½⌉
    ⎜ iₙ = n-((iₙ+jₙ)-1)((iₙ+jₙ)-2)/2
    ⎜ jₙ = (iₙ+jₙ)-iₙ
    ⎝ (iₙ+jₙ-1)(iₙ+jₙ-2)/2+iₙ = n

    No boundaries are involved because
    every interval of length 1/5 contains
    infinitely many rationals and
    therefore is essentially covered by
    infinitely many intervals of length 1/5
    - if Cantor is right.

    I haven't claimed anything at all about
    your all.1/5.length intervals.

    Then consider the two only alternatives:
    Either by reordering
    (one after the other or simultaneously)
    the measure of these intervals

    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Measure_(mathematics)
    ⎛ Let X be a set and Σ a σ-algebra over X.
    ⎜ A set function μ from Σ to
    ⎜ the extended real number line [!]
    ⎜ is called a measure
    ⎜ if the following conditions hold:
    ⎜ • Non-negativity: For all E ∈ Σ, μ(E) ≥ 0.
    ⎜ • μ(∅) = 0.
    ⎜ • Countable additivity (or σ-additivity):
    ⎜ For all countable collections {Eₖ}ₖ⃛₌₁ of
    ⎜ pairwise disjoint sets in Σ,
    ⎝ μ(⋃ₖ⃛₌₁Eₖ) = ∑ₖ⃛₌₁μ(Eₖ).

    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Extended_real_number_line
    ⎛ In mathematics, the extended real number system
    ⎜ is obtained from the real number system ℝ
    ⎜ by adding two[!] elements denoted +∞ and −∞
    ⎜ that are respectively greater and lower than
    ⎝ every real number.

    The value of a measure is 0 or +∞ or
    a point (in ℝ⁺) between fore and hind of
    a split (of ℚ⁺) of all ratios of
    numbers (in ℕ⁺) the countable.to from.1
    (AKA finite).

    the measure of these intervals can grow
    from 1/10 of the real axis

    ≠ 0
    ≠ a point between a split of
    all ratios of the countable.to from.1
    = +∞

    to infinitely many times the real axis,

    ≠ 0
    ≠ a point between a split of
    all ratios of the countable.to from.1
    = +∞

    or not.

    The clever re.ordering does not
    increase the measure.
    It is +∞ before and +∞ after.

    +∞ has properties different from
    anything in (0,+∞)

    In particular,
    ∀x ∈ (0,+∞): ∃x′ ∈ (0,x): 5⋅x′ = x
    However,
    +∞ ∉ (0,+∞)
    ¬∃x′ ∈ (0,+∞): 5⋅x′ = +∞

    My understanding of mathematics and geometry
    is that
    reordering cannot increase the measure
    (only reduce it by overlapping).
    This is a basic axiom which
    will certainly be agreed to by
    everybody not conditioned by matheology.

    By
    "everybody not conditioned by matheology"
    you mean
    "everybody who hasn't thought much about infinity"

    But there is also an analytical proof:
    Every reordering of
    any finite set of intervals
    does not increase their measure.
    The limit of a constant sequence is
    this constant however.

    You are assuming that the measure of
    the all.⅕.intervals at their starting positions
    is some value outside the extended reals.
    Otherwise,
    for midpoints in {...,-2,-1,0,1,2,...}
    the measure is in [0,+∞]
    and not.in [0,+∞)
    and thus equals +∞

    This geometrical consequence of Cantor's theory
    has, to my knowledge, never been discussed.
    By the way I got the idea after a posting of yours:
    Each of {...,-3,-2,-1,0,1,2,3,...} is
    the midpoint of an interval.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From joes@21:1/5 to All on Fri Nov 8 19:05:04 2024
    Am Fri, 08 Nov 2024 17:43:15 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 08.11.2024 13:28, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/8/24 5:18 AM, WM wrote:

    My understanding of mathematics and geometry is that reordering cannot
    increase the measure (only reduce it by overlapping). This is a basic
    axiom which will certainly be agreed to by everybody not conditioned
    by matheology. But there is also an analytical proof: Every reordering
    of any finite set of intervals does not increase their measure. The
    limit of a constant sequence is this constant however.
    This geometrical consequence of Cantor's theory has, to my knowledge,
    never been discussed. By the way I got the idea after a posting of
    yours: Each of {...,-3,-2,-1,0,1,2,3,...} is the midpoint of an
    interval.
    which makes the error that the properties of finite objects apply to
    the infinite objects, which isn't true, and what just breaks your
    logic.
    The infinite of the real axis is a big supply but an as big drain.

    You take it as a given, but that just means that your logic is unable
    to actually handle the infinite.
    I take it as evident that intervals of the measure 1/5 of the positive
    real axis will not, by any shuffling, cover the real axis completely,
    let alone infinitely often. I think who believes this is a deplorable
    fanatic if not a fool.
    What is the measure you are using and what does it give for the real
    axis?

    --
    Am Sat, 20 Jul 2024 12:35:31 +0000 schrieb WM in sci.math:
    It is not guaranteed that n+1 exists for every n.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Fri Nov 8 21:35:09 2024
    Am 08.11.2024 um 20:05 schrieb joes:
    Am Fri, 08 Nov 2024 17:43:15 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 08.11.2024 13:28, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/8/24 5:18 AM, WM wrote:

    My understanding of mathematics and geometry is that reordering cannot >>>> increase the measure (only reduce it by overlapping). This is a basic
    axiom which will certainly be agreed to by everybody not conditioned
    by matheology. But there is also an analytical proof: Every reordering >>>> of any finite set of intervals does not increase their measure. The
    limit of a constant sequence is this constant however.
    This geometrical consequence of Cantor's theory has, to my knowledge,
    never been discussed. By the way I got the idea after a posting of
    yours: Each of {...,-3,-2,-1,0,1,2,3,...} is the midpoint of an
    interval.
    which makes the error that the properties of finite objects apply to
    the infinite objects, which isn't true, and what just breaks your
    logic.
    The infinite of the real axis is a big supply but an as big drain.

    You take it as a given, but that just means that your logic is unable
    to actually handle the infinite.
    I take it as evident that intervals of the measure 1/5 of the positive
    real axis will not, by any shuffling, cover the real axis completely,
    let alone infinitely often. I think who believes this is a deplorable
    fanatic if not a fool.

    What is the measure you are using and what does it give for the real
    axis?

    Ob Du es nochmal schaffst, auf diesen saudummen Scheißdreck NICHT zu antworten?

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Fri Nov 8 21:36:17 2024
    Am 08.11.2024 um 21:35 schrieb Moebius:
    Am 08.11.2024 um 20:05 schrieb joes:
    Am Fri, 08 Nov 2024 17:43:15 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 08.11.2024 13:28, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/8/24 5:18 AM, WM wrote:

    My understanding of mathematics and geometry is that reordering cannot >>>>> increase the measure (only reduce it by overlapping). This is a basic >>>>> axiom which will certainly be agreed to by everybody not conditioned >>>>> by matheology. But there is also an analytical proof: Every reordering >>>>> of any finite set of intervals does not increase their measure. The
    limit of a constant sequence is this constant however.
    This geometrical consequence of Cantor's theory has, to my knowledge, >>>>> never been discussed. By the way I got the idea after a posting of
    yours: Each of {...,-3,-2,-1,0,1,2,3,...} is the midpoint of an
    interval.
    which makes the error that the properties of finite objects apply to
    the infinite objects, which isn't true, and what just breaks your
    logic.
    The infinite of the real axis is a big supply but an as big drain.

    You take it as a given, but that just means that your logic is unable
    to actually handle the infinite.
    I take it as evident that intervals of the measure 1/5 of the positive
    real axis will not, by any shuffling, cover the real axis completely,
    let alone infinitely often. I think who believes this is a deplorable
    fanatic if not a fool.

    What is the measure you are using and what does it give for the real
    axis?

    Ob Du es nochmal schaffst, auf diesen saudummen Scheißdreck NICHT zu antworten?

    Ich kann es jedenfalls nicht mehr sehen/lesen. Daher kommst Du jetzt
    auch hier in mein Killfile. Tschüß!

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Tue Nov 12 00:00:07 2024
    On 11/11/2024 3:33 PM, WM wrote:
    On 11.11.2024 19:23, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/11/2024 3:41 AM, WM wrote:

    But it will never complete
    an infinite set of claims.

    We do not need an infinite 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲 of 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀 completed.
    We do not want an infinite 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲 of 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀 completed.

    But you claim that
    _all_ fractions are in bijection with
    all natural numbers,
    don't you?

    Yes, I claim that.

    For that claim you need an infinite set of claims.

    For that claim, I need
    a finite 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲 of 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀, in which each 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺 is true.or.not.first.false,
    and in which that is one of the 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀.

    This is one 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺:
    ⎛ All fractions are in bijection with
    ⎝ all natural numbers.

    It is wrong.

    It is one claim.

    A conceivable argument that
    claims.like.that are infinite and
    therefore are not expressible finitely
    fetches up hard against the bare fact of
    it having been expressed, here, a few lines up.


    I won't re.present here
    a finite 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲 of 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀, in which each 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺 is true.or.not.first.false,
    and in which that is one of the 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀.
    But I could.

    Suppose I did.
    Would you (WM) accept that 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺?

    My intervals I(n) = [n - 1/10, n + 1/10]
    must be translated to all the midpoints
    1/1, 1/2, 2/1, 1/3, 2/2, 3/1, 1/4, 2/3, 3/2, 4/1, 1/5,
    2/4, 3/3, 4/2, 5/1, 1/6, 2/5, 3/4, 4/3, 5/2, 6/1, ...
    if you want to contradict my claim.

    Your 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀 start with "Sets change".

    No, I claim that intervals can be translated.

    Which means what?
    Apparently, to you, it means that
    sets change.

    However,
    our sets do not change.

    (The set of intervals remains constant
    in size and multitude.)

    Our sets do not change.

    For every finite subset this is possible.

    Our sets do not change.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to FromTheRafters on Tue Nov 12 09:58:12 2024
    On 11.11.2024 22:50, FromTheRafters wrote:
    It happens that WM formulated :


    For that claim you need an infinite set of claims.

    Good thing we have such.

    No.

    This is one ?????:
    ⎛ All fractions are in bijection with
    ⎝ all natural numbers.

    It is wrong.

    You 'think' it is wrong because you intuitively think it 'should' be
    wrong. Saying it is wrong does not make it wrong no matter how many
    times that you say it.

    Therefore I prove it. The set of intervals I(n) = [n - 1/10, n + 1/10]
    cannot cover all fractions on the real axis.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From joes@21:1/5 to All on Tue Nov 12 11:23:47 2024
    Am Tue, 12 Nov 2024 09:58:12 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 11.11.2024 22:50, FromTheRafters wrote:
    It happens that WM formulated :

    For that claim you need an infinite set of claims.
    Good thing we have such.
    No.
    Yes, we do claim something for each, every one and all of the
    infinite set of (finite) natural numbers.

    This is one ?????:
    ⎛ All fractions are in bijection with ⎝ all natural numbers.
    It is wrong.
    You 'think' it is wrong because you intuitively think it 'should' be
    wrong. Saying it is wrong does not make it wrong no matter how many
    times that you say it.
    Therefore I prove it. The set of intervals I(n) = [n - 1/10, n + 1/10]
    cannot cover all fractions on the real axis.
    It absolutely does, for all fractions n.

    --
    Am Sat, 20 Jul 2024 12:35:31 +0000 schrieb WM in sci.math:
    It is not guaranteed that n+1 exists for every n.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Chris M. Thomasson on Tue Nov 12 15:05:18 2024
    On 11.11.2024 22:42, Chris M. Thomasson wrote:
    On 11/11/2024 1:00 AM, WM wrote:

    I(n) = [n - 1/10, n + 1/10]
    can be translated until all rational numbers
    1/1, 1/2, 2/1, 1/3, 2/2, 3/1, 1/4, 2/3, 3/2, 4/1, 1/5, 2/4, 3/3, 4/2,
    5/1, 1/6, 2/5, 3/4, 4/3, 5/2, 6/1,  ...
    are midpoints.

    Obviously that is impossible because the density 1/5 of the intervals
    can never increase. It is possible however to shift an arbitrarily
    large (a potentially infinite) number of intervals to rational midpoints.

    I don't think you know how to take any natural number and turn it into a unique pair, and then back again via Cantor pairing.

    I don't think that you understand what's going on here.

    Regards, WM


    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to joes on Tue Nov 12 15:30:25 2024
    On 12.11.2024 12:23, joes wrote:
    Am Tue, 12 Nov 2024 09:58:12 +0100 schrieb WM:

    Therefore I prove it. The set of intervals I(n) = [n - 1/10, n + 1/10]
    cannot cover all fractions on the real axis.
    It absolutely does, for all fractions n.

    The claim however is for all fractions q, most of which are different
    from n.

    The density is provably 1/5 for all finite initial segments of the real
    line. The sequence 1/5, 1/5, 1/5, ... has the limit 1/5. By translating intervals neither their size nor their multitude changes. Therefore
    never more than 1/5 of the real axis is covered. Most rationals remain
    naked.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Tue Nov 12 15:24:32 2024
    On 12.11.2024 06:00, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/11/2024 3:33 PM, WM wrote:

    This is one 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺:
    ⎛ All fractions are in bijection with
    ⎝ all natural numbers.

    It is wrong.

    It is one claim.

    It is one wrong claim.
    Apparently, to you, it means that
     sets change.

    It means that intervals I(n) = [n - 1/10, n + 1/10] can be shifted on
    the real axis without getting larger and without getting more. The set
    of intervals cannot change. The set of naturals differs from the set of rationals. Therefore the rationals cannot be covered by the naturals.
    Our sets do not change.

    So you deny the application of set theory to geometry including
    Banach-Tarski and therefore to algebra. What remains, what is it good for?

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Tue Nov 12 10:58:29 2024
    On 11/11/2024 3:33 PM, WM wrote:
    On 11.11.2024 19:23, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/11/2024 3:41 AM, WM wrote:

    My intervals I(n) = [n - 1/10, n + 1/10]
    must be translated to all the midpoints
    1/1, 1/2, 2/1, 1/3, 2/2, 3/1, 1/4, 2/3, 3/2, 4/1, 1/5,
    2/4, 3/3, 4/2, 5/1, 1/6, 2/5, 3/4, 4/3, 5/2, 6/1, ...
    if you want to contradict my claim.

    Your 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀 start with "Sets change".

    No, I claim that intervals can be translated.

    By which, you mean that translation changes intervals.

    Intervals do not change.
    "After" translation of [4-⅒,4+⅒] to [1/3-⅒,1/3+⅒]
    [4-⅒,4+⅒] will continue being [4-⅒,4+⅒]
    [1/3-⅒,1/3+⅒] will have never been [4-⅒,4+⅒]

    (The set of intervals remains constant
    in size and multitude.)

    The set of intervals remains constant. Absolutely.
    Sets do not change.
    Intervals do not change.
    Mathematical objects do not change.

    ⎛ But what about descriptions of change?
    ⎝ Matheologians are famous for those.

    The description of a cannon ball's arc,
    the description of the beat of a pendulum,
    these are what matheologians are famous for.
    But these are maps, not journeys.
    The maps do not change.

    Matheologians make true claims about
    each one of infinitely.many journeys,
    and then, they augment the description with
    further true.or.not.first.false claims.
    Without shooting cannons or swinging pendulums,
    we know that the further claims must be true.

    If the matheologians are clever enough or lucky enough,
    then the further true claims eliminate
    all but one description, and
    we have a map (which has never changed).

    The description and the further claims
    are finite. Our finiteness is no barrier to saying them,
    although we might not be clever or lucky enough
    to eliminate all but one.

    The description and the further claims
    are always and everywhere _about_
    the same infinitely.many, not.changing.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Tue Nov 12 17:43:32 2024
    On 12.11.2024 16:58, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/11/2024 3:33 PM, WM wrote:
    On 11.11.2024 19:23, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/11/2024 3:41 AM, WM wrote:

    My intervals I(n) = [n - 1/10, n + 1/10]
    must be translated to all the midpoints
    1/1, 1/2, 2/1, 1/3, 2/2, 3/1, 1/4, 2/3, 3/2, 4/1, 1/5,
    2/4, 3/3, 4/2, 5/1, 1/6, 2/5, 3/4, 4/3, 5/2, 6/1, ...
    if you want to contradict my claim.

    Your 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀 start with "Sets change".

    No, I claim that intervals can be translated.

    By which, you mean that translation changes intervals.

    No, the intervals remain constant in size and multitude.

    (The set of intervals remains constant
    in size and multitude.)

    The set of intervals remains constant. Absolutely.
    Sets do not change.
    Intervals do not change.
    Mathematical objects do not change.

    Therefore the intervals covering all naturals cannot cover more. But the rationals are more in the sense that they include all naturals and 1/2.
    By your argument Cantor has been falsified.

    Regards, WM

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Tue Nov 12 14:01:57 2024
    On 11/12/2024 11:43 AM, WM wrote:
    On 12.11.2024 16:58, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/11/2024 3:33 PM, WM wrote:
    On 11.11.2024 19:23, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/11/2024 3:41 AM, WM wrote:

    My intervals I(n) = [n - 1/10, n + 1/10]
    must be translated to all the midpoints
    1/1, 1/2, 2/1, 1/3, 2/2, 3/1, 1/4, 2/3, 3/2, 4/1, 1/5,
    2/4, 3/3, 4/2, 5/1, 1/6, 2/5, 3/4, 4/3, 5/2, 6/1, ...
    if you want to contradict my claim.

    Your 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀 start with "Sets change".

    No, I claim that intervals can be translated.

    By which, you mean that translation changes intervals.

    No, the intervals remain constant
    in size and multitude.

    Intervals which are constant _only_
    in size and multitude
    are not constant absolutely.

    (The set of intervals remains constant
    in size and multitude.)

    The set of intervals remains constant. Absolutely.
    Sets do not change.
    Intervals do not change.
    Mathematical objects do not change.

    Therefore
    the intervals covering all naturals
    cannot cover more.

    These intervals
    {[n-⅒,n+⅒]: n∈ℕ⁺}
    cover all naturals ℕ⁺ and
    do not cover all fractions ℕ⁺/ℕ⁺

    But the rationals are more in the sense that
    they include all naturals and 1/2.

    These intervals
    {[i/j-⅒,i/j+⅒]: i/j∈ℕ⁺/ℕ⁺}
    cover all fractions ℕ⁺/ℕ⁺

    These intervals
    {[n-⅒,n+⅒]: n∈ℕ⁺}
    and these intervals
    {[i/j-⅒,i/j+⅒]: i/j∈ℕ⁺/ℕ⁺}
    are different intervals.

    Our intervals do not change.
    Our sets do not change.
    Our mathematical objects do not change.

    By your argument
    Cantor has been falsified.

    _What you understand_ as Cantor
    has been falsified.

    I'd say "misunderstand", but
    I do not find it attractive to
    dress up as Jacques Derrida and
    deconstruct Georg Cantor.
    Let someone else do it, if they choose.

    That thing you think Cantor says,
    whether or not Cantor says it,
    is false.

    Our sets and other things of their ilk
    do not change.
    Our finite sequences of claims which
    are each true.or.not.first.false
    are each true.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Tue Nov 12 22:38:50 2024
    On 12.11.2024 20:01, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/12/2024 11:43 AM, WM wrote:

    No, the intervals remain constant
    in size and multitude.

    Intervals which are constant _only_
    in size and multitude
    are not constant absolutely.

    They would suffer to cover all rationals completely if Cantor's
    bijection was complete.
    These intervals
    {[n-⅒,n+⅒]: n∈ℕ⁺}
    cover all naturals ℕ⁺  and
    do not cover all fractions ℕ⁺/ℕ⁺

    Right.

    But the rationals are more in the sense that
    they include all naturals and 1/2.

    These intervals
    {[i/j-⅒,i/j+⅒]: i/j∈ℕ⁺/ℕ⁺}
    cover all fractions ℕ⁺/ℕ⁺

    But these are more intervals.

    These intervals
    {[n-⅒,n+⅒]: n∈ℕ⁺}
    and these intervals
    {[i/j-⅒,i/j+⅒]: i/j∈ℕ⁺/ℕ⁺}
    are different intervals.

    In particular the second kind of intervals must be more. And this is the solution: The identity of the intervals for the geometric covering is irrelevant. I will elaborate o this in the next posting.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Wed Nov 13 04:00:26 2024
    Am 13.11.2024 um 03:42 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:

    If a = b then they [a and b] are equal?

    or "identical", right.

    For instance 5 = 5, the self relation equality?

    Right. The relation "=" only holds "between" on and the same "entity"
    (object). :-P

    In the context of math we might even TRY to DEFINE "=" the following way:

    a = b :<-> each and every property which holds for a also holds
    for b, and vice versa.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Wed Nov 13 04:01:09 2024
    Am 13.11.2024 um 03:42 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:

    If a = b then they [a and b] are equal?

    or "identical", right.

    For instance 5 = 5, the self relation equality?

    Right. The relation "=" only holds "between" one and the same "entity" (object). :-P

    In the context of math we might even TRY to DEFINE "=" the following way:

    a = b :<-> each and every property which holds for a also holds
    for b, and vice versa.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Wed Nov 13 04:07:32 2024
    Am 13.11.2024 um 03:44 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:

    [...] different ways to represent zero?

    0 = 3-4+1 = 4-4 = 2*0 = 0

    ect.

    Right. "3-4+1", "4-4", "2*0", "0", are just different NAMEs (math:
    TERMs) to denote (refer to) _one and the same_ number, namely zero
    (usualy, denoted with "0").

    Hint: Suoerman is Clark Kent.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Wed Nov 13 02:18:46 2024
    On 11/12/2024 4:38 PM, WM wrote:
    On 12.11.2024 20:01, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/12/2024 11:43 AM, WM wrote:

    No, the intervals remain constant
    in size and multitude.

    Intervals which are constant _only_
    in size and multitude
    are not constant absolutely.

    They would suffer [suffice] to cover
    all rationals completely
    if Cantor's bijection was complete.

    I think that you want to use 'suffice' here.

    Your English is generally excellent,
    but 'suffice' is not a very common word.

    One instance I'm fond of:

    ⎛ Some say the world will end in fire,
    ⎜ Some say in ice.
    ⎜ From what I’ve tasted of desire
    ⎜ I hold with those who favor fire.
    ⎜ But if it had to perish twice,
    ⎜ I think I know enough of hate
    ⎜ To say that for destruction ice
    ⎜ Is also great
    ⎝ And would suffice.

    -- Robert Frost, "Fire and Ice"

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Wed Nov 13 09:20:41 2024
    On 13.11.2024 08:18, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/12/2024 4:38 PM, WM wrote:
    On 12.11.2024 20:01, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/12/2024 11:43 AM, WM wrote:

    No, the intervals remain constant
    in size and multitude.

    Intervals which are constant _only_
    in size and multitude
    are not constant absolutely.

    They would suffer [suffice] to cover
    all rationals completely
    if Cantor's bijection was complete.

    I think that you want to use 'suffice' here.

    Yes, thank you.

    Your English is generally excellent,

    Thank you.

    but 'suffice' is not a very common word.

    One instance I'm fond of:

    ⎛ Some say the world will end in fire,
    ⎜ Some say in ice.
    ⎜ From what I’ve tasted of desire
    ⎜ I hold with those who favor fire.
    ⎜ But if it had to perish twice,
    ⎜ I think I know enough of hate
    ⎜ To say that for destruction ice
    ⎜ Is also great
    ⎝ And would suffice.

    -- Robert Frost, "Fire and Ice"

    Nice. Ice fits better to the name of the poet. But I was stunned by the
    last rhyme. I would have pronounced suffice like police.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Wed Nov 13 04:08:58 2024
    On 11/12/2024 4:38 PM, WM wrote:
    On 12.11.2024 20:01, Jim Burns wrote:

    These intervals
    {[n-⅒,n+⅒]: n∈ℕ⁺}
    cover all naturals ℕ⁺  and
    do not cover all fractions ℕ⁺/ℕ⁺

    Right.

    But the rationals are more in the sense that
    they include all naturals and 1/2.

    These intervals
    {[i/j-⅒,i/j+⅒]: i/j∈ℕ⁺/ℕ⁺}
    cover all fractions ℕ⁺/ℕ⁺

    But these are more intervals.

    Are there more, though?
    Or are there fewer?
    i/j ↦ (i+j-1)(i+j-1)+2⋅i

    ⟨ 1/1 1/2 2/1 1/3 2/2 3/1 1/4 2/3 ... ⟩

    ⟨ 2 4 6 8 10 12 14 16 ... ⟩

    Or do infinite sets have different rules
    than finite sets do?

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Wed Nov 13 17:31:54 2024
    On 13.11.2024 10:08, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/12/2024 4:38 PM, WM wrote:

    But the rationals are more in the sense that
    they include all naturals and 1/2.

    These intervals
    {[i/j-⅒,i/j+⅒]: i/j∈ℕ⁺/ℕ⁺}
    cover all fractions ℕ⁺/ℕ⁺

    But these are more intervals.

    Are there more, though?
    Or are there fewer?
    i/j ↦ (i+j-1)(i+j-1)+2⋅i

    ⟨ 1/1 1/2 2/1 1/3 2/2 3/1 1/4 2/3 ... ⟩

    ⟨ 2   4   6   8   10  12  14  16 ... ⟩

    or

    ⟨ 1/1 1/2 2/1 1/3 2/2 3/1 1/4 2/3 ... ⟩

    ⟨ 2 3 5 7 11 13 17 19 ... ⟩


    or

    ⟨ 1/1 1/2 2/1 ... ⟩

    ⟨ 10^10 10^10^10 10^10^10^10 ... ⟩

    Or do infinite sets have different rules
    than finite sets do?

    If infinite sets obey the rules sketched above, then set theorists must
    discard geometry
    because by shifting intervals the relative covering 1/5 of ℝ+ becomes oo*ℝ, and analysis
    because the constant sequence 1/5, 1/5, 1/5, ... has limit oo,
    and logic
    because of Bob.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Wed Nov 13 14:38:01 2024
    On 11/13/2024 11:31 AM, WM wrote:
    On 13.11.2024 10:08, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/12/2024 4:38 PM, WM wrote:
    On 12.11.2024 20:01, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/12/2024 11:43 AM, WM wrote:

    But the rationals are more in the sense that
    they include all naturals and 1/2.

    These intervals
    {[i/j-⅒,i/j+⅒]: i/j∈ℕ⁺/ℕ⁺}
    cover all fractions ℕ⁺/ℕ⁺

    But these are more intervals.

    Are there more, though?
    Or are there fewer?
    i/j ↦ (i+j-1)(i+j-1)+2⋅i

    ⟨ 1/1 1/2 2/1 1/3 2/2 3/1 1/4 2/3 ... ⟩

    ⟨ 2   4   6   8   10  12  14  16 ... ⟩

    or
    ⟨ 1/1 1/2 2/1 1/3 2/2 3/1 1/4 2/3 ... ⟩

    ⟨ 2   3   5   7   11  13  17  19 ... ⟩

    or
    ⟨ 1/1        1/2       2/1  ... ⟩

    ⟨ 10^10   10^10^10  10^10^10^10  ... ⟩

    Yes,
    or those, too.

    _Without giving infinity much thought_
    they each make it appear that
    ⟨ 1/1 1/2 2/1 1/3 2/2 3/1 1/4 2/3 ... ⟩
    is strictly smaller than
    ⟨ 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 ... ⟩

    My modest proposal is that
    we stop declaring conclusions about infinity
    without giving infinity much thought.

    Or do infinite sets have different rules
    than finite sets do?

    If infinite sets obey the rules sketched above,

    ... _and are finite_ ...

    then set theorists must discard geometry
    because
    by shifting intervals
    the relative covering 1/5 of ℝ+ becomes oo*ℝ,
    and analysis
    because
    the constant sequence 1/5, 1/5, 1/5, ...
    has limit oo,
    and logic
    because of
    Bob.

    ----
    by shifting intervals
    the relative covering 1/5 of ℝ+ becomes oo*ℝ,

    By definition,
    the value of a measure is an extended real≥0

    An extended real≥0 is either
    Archimedean == having a countable.to bound, or
    non.Archimedean == not.having a countable.to bound.

    The extended reals≥0 have only
    the standard reals≥0, which are Archimedean, and
    a single non.Archimedean point≥0 +∞

    Neither the measure of the union of unshifted intervals
    nor the measure of the union of shifted intervals
    are Archimedean == neither has a countable.to bound.

    Both the measure of the interval.union before shifting
    and the measure of the interval.union after shifting
    are the single non.Archimedean value +∞

    No,
    the measure doesn't _become_ +∞
    It has the same value +∞ before and after shifting.

    ----
    the constant sequence 1/5, 1/5, 1/5, ...
    has limit oo,

    If
    f(x) = y is continuous at xₗᵢₘ
    then
    the limit yₗᵢₘ of the value equals
    the value f(xₗᵢₘ) of the limit

    ⎛ x₁ x₂ x₃ ... → xₗᵢₘ
    ⎜ f(xₙ) = yₙ
    ⎜ y₁ y₂ y₃ ... → yₗᵢₘ
    ⎝ ⇒ f(xₗᵢₘ) = yₗᵢₘ

    If
    any function which jumps
    (which crosses a line without intersecting it)
    cannot be continuous everywhere,
    then
    there are uncountably.many points,
    more points than names.for.points.

    If
    any function which jumps
    cannot be continuous everywhere,
    but
    there aren't uncountably.many points,
    then
    it's impossible for what's described to exist.

    ----
    Bob.

    KING BOB!
    https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=TjAg-8qqR3g

    If,
    in a set A which
    can match one of its proper subsets B,
    A ⊃≠ B ∧ |A| = |B|
    (B can overwrite A one.for.one),
    and,
    before overwriting, Bob is in A\B
    then
    after overwriting, Bob isn't in overwritten.A = B

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Wed Nov 13 22:29:18 2024
    On 13.11.2024 20:38, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/13/2024 11:31 AM, WM wrote:


    If infinite sets obey the rules sketched above,

    ... _and are finite_ ...

    Not necessary to apply logic, geometry and analysis.

    then set theorists must discard geometry
    because
     by shifting intervals
     the relative covering 1/5 of ℝ+ becomes oo*ℝ,
    and analysis
    because
     the constant sequence 1/5, 1/5, 1/5, ...
     has limit oo,
    and logic
    because of
     Bob.

    ----
     by shifting intervals
     the relative covering 1/5 of ℝ+ becomes oo*ℝ,

    By definition,
    the value of a measure is an extended real≥0

    The value of the relative measure is 1/5. For every finite interval this
    is true. The limit can be calculated in analysis of real numbers without extension.

    An extended real≥0 is either
    Archimedean == having a countable.to bound,  or
    non.Archimedean == not.having a countable.to bound.

    The extended reals≥0 have only
    the standard reals≥0, which are Archimedean, and
    a single non.Archimedean point≥0  +∞

    That is what I call ω. But the limit can be calculated from the reals
    alone, in particular when the sequence is constant.

    No,
    the measure doesn't _become_ +∞
    It has the same value +∞ before and after shifting.

    Take the relative measure that can be obtained from every finite
    interval of the real line.

    ----
     the constant sequence 1/5, 1/5, 1/5, ...
     has limit oo,

    Nonsense deleted.

    ----
     Bob.

    KING BOB!
    https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=TjAg-8qqR3g

    If,
     in a set A which
     can match one of its proper subsets B,

    That is nonsense too.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Thu Nov 14 00:27:27 2024
    Am 13.11.2024 um 03:44 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:

    [...] different ways to represent zero?

    0 = 3-4+1 = 4-4 = 2*0 = 0

    ect.

    Right. "3-4+1", "4-4", "2*0", "0", are just different NAMEs (math:
    TERMs) to denote (refer to) _one and the same_ number, namely zero
    (usualy, denoted with "0").

    Hint: Superman is Clark Kent.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Thu Nov 14 00:28:27 2024
    Am 14.11.2024 um 00:27 schrieb Moebius:
    Am 13.11.2024 um 03:44 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:

    [...] different ways to represent zero?

    0 = 3-4+1 = 4-4 = 2*0 = 0

    ect.

    Right. "3-4+1", "4-4", "2*0", "0", are just different NAMEs (math:
    TERMs) to denote (refer to) _one and the same_ number, namely zero
    (usualy, denoted with "0").

    Hint: Superman is Clark Kent.

    Superman = Clark Kent

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Wed Nov 13 18:16:37 2024
    On 11/13/2024 4:29 PM, WM wrote:
    On 13.11.2024 20:38, Jim Burns wrote:

    ----
     Bob.

    KING BOB!
    https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=TjAg-8qqR3g

    If,
      in a set A which
      can match one of its proper subsets B,

    That is nonsense too.

    A finite 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲 of 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀 in which each claim is true.or.not.first.false
    is
    a finite 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲 of 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀 in which each claim is true.

    Some claims are true and we know it
    because
    they claim that
    when we say this, we mean that,
    and we, conscious of our own minds, know that
    when we say this, we mean that.

    Some 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀 are not.first.false and we know it
    because
    we can see that
    no assignment of truth.values exists
    in which 𝘁𝗵𝗲𝘆 are first.false.
    𝗾 is not first.false in ⟨ 𝗽 𝗽⇒𝗾 𝗾 ⟩.

    Some finite 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲𝘀 of 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀 are
    each true.or.not.first.false
    and we know it.

    When we know that,
    we know each claim is true.

    We know each claim is true, even if
    it is a claim physically impossible to check,
    like it would be physically impossible
    to check each one of infinitely.many.

    We know because
    it's not checking the individuals
    by which we know.
    It's a certain sequence of claims existing
    by which we know.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to FromTheRafters on Wed Nov 13 20:43:00 2024
    On 11/13/2024 7:05 PM, FromTheRafters wrote:
    Jim Burns formulated on Wednesday :
    On 11/13/2024 4:29 PM, WM wrote:
    On 13.11.2024 20:38, Jim Burns wrote:

    ----
     Bob.

    KING BOB!
    https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=TjAg-8qqR3g

    If,
      in a set A which
      can match one of its proper subsets B,

    That is nonsense too.

    [repaired]

    A finite sequence of claims in which
    each claim is true.or.not.first.false
    is
    a finite sequence of claims in which
    each claim is true.

    Some claims are true and we know it
    because
    they claim that
    when we say this, we mean that,
    and we, conscious of our own minds, know that
    when we say this, we mean that.

    Some claims are not.first.false and we know it
    because
    we can see that
    no assignment of truth.values exists
    in which they are first.false.
    q is not first.false in ⟨ p p⇒q q ⟩.

    Some finite sequences of claims are
    each true.or.not.first.false
    and we know it.

    When we know that,
    we know each claim is true.

    We know each claim is true, even if
    it is a claim physically impossible to check,
    like it would be physically impossible
    to check each one of infinitely.many.

    We know because
    it's not checking the individuals
    by which we know.
    It's a certain sequence of claims existing
    by which we know.

    In my source window:

    [...]
    That is nonsense too.

    A finite 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲 of 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀 in
    which
    each claim is true.or.not.first.false
    is
    a finite 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲 of 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀 in
    which
    each claim is true.
    [...]

    ================================================
    I follow some of this mostly from context. :)

    Sorry about that.
    The other fonts weren't strictly necessary,
    I just had a brainstorm over
    how to (maybe) explain logical validity better,
    and I couldn't resist.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Thu Nov 14 11:20:33 2024
    On 14.11.2024 00:16, Jim Burns wrote:

    A finite 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲 of 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀 in which
    each claim is true.or.not.first.false
    is
    a finite 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲 of 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀 in which
    each claim is true.

    Some claims are true and we know it
    because
    they claim that
    when we say this, we mean that,
    and we, conscious of our own minds, know that
    when we say this, we mean that.

    Some 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀 are not.first.false and we know it
    because
    we can see that
    no assignment of truth.values exists
    in which 𝘁𝗵𝗲𝘆 are first.false.
    𝗾 is not first.false in ⟨ 𝗽 𝗽⇒𝗾 𝗾 ⟩.

    Some finite 𝘀𝗲𝗾𝘂𝗲𝗻𝗰𝗲𝘀 of 𝗰𝗹𝗮𝗶𝗺𝘀 are
    each true.or.not.first.false
    and we know it.

    When we know that,
    we know each claim is true.

    We know each claim is true, even if
    it is a claim physically impossible to check,
    like it would be physically impossible
    to check each one of infinitely.many.

    Here is a single claim which is true:

    The covering of a geometric figure by a set of similar smaller intervals
    is independent of the order of the intervals. That holds for every
    finite figure and, by applying the analytical limit, also for infinite
    figures like

    XOOO...
    XOOO...
    XOOO...
    XOOO...
    ...

    or

    0---------_1_--------_2_--------_3_---...

    Therefore a geometric representation let alone proof of most of Cantor's bijections is impossible.

    Belief in set theory excludes belief in geometry.

    All babble about Completely Scattered Space in cases of
    I(n) = [n - sqrt(2)/2^n, n + sqrt(2)/2^n]
    or
    I(n) = [n - 1/2^n, n + 1/2^n]
    is to no avail and useless from the outset.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Thu Nov 14 13:31:25 2024
    On 11/14/2024 5:20 AM, WM wrote:
    On 14.11.2024 00:16, Jim Burns wrote:

    Therefore
    a geometric representation let alone proof of
    most of Cantor's bijections is impossible.

    Consider geometry.

    For two triangles △A′B′C′ and △A″B″C″
    if
    △A′B′C′ and △A″B″C″ are similar triangles
    ⎛ μ∠C′A′B′ = μ∠C″A″B″
    ⎜ μ∠A′B′C′ = μ∠A″B″C″
    ⎜ μ∠B′C′A′ = μ∠B″C″A″
    ⎝ △A′B′C′ ∼ △A″B″C″
    then
    corresponding sides are in the same ratio
    ( μA︫︭′︭B︫′/μA︫︭″︭B︫″ = μB︫︭′︭C︫′/μB︫︭″︭C︫″ = μA︫︭′︭C︫′/μA︫︭″︭C︫″

    For similar △A′B′C′ ∼ △A″B″C″
    if μA︫︭′︭B︫′ = 1
    and μB︫︭″︭C︫″ = x
    then 1/μA︫︭″︭B︫″ = μB︫︭′︭C︫′/x
    and μA︫︭″︭B︫″ = μB︫︭′︭C︫′ = x¹ᐟ²

    For similar △A′B′C′ ∼ △A″B″C″
    if μA︫︭′︭B︫′ = 1
    and μA︫︭″︭B︫″ = x
    and μB︫︭′︭C︫′ = y
    then 1/x = y/μB︫︭″︭C︫″
    and μB︫︭″︭C︫″ = x⋅y

    For similar △A′B′C′ ∼ △A″B″C″
    if μA︫︭′︭B︫′ = 1
    and μA︫︭″︭B︫″ = x
    and μB︫︭″︭C︫″ = y
    then 1/x = μB︫︭′︭C︫′/y
    and μB︫︭′︭C︫′ = y/x

    The ceiling ⌈x⌉ of x is the first integer ≥ x

    Therefore
    a geometric representation let alone proof of
    most of Cantor's bijections is impossible.

    Cantor's bijection is
    k ↦ i/j
    i︭+︭j := ⌈(2⋅k+¼)¹ᐟ²+½⌉
    i := k-(i︭+︭j-1)⋅(i︭+︭j-2)/2
    j := i︭+︭j-i
    (i+j-1)⋅(i+j-2)/2+i = k

    Setting aside for a moment
    what you _think_ Cantor's bijection is,
    what part of _that_
    is impossible to represent geometrically?

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Thu Nov 14 23:19:59 2024
    Am 14.11.2024 um 23:09 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:
    On 11/13/2024 3:28 PM, Moebius wrote:
    Am 14.11.2024 um 00:27 schrieb Moebius:
    Am 13.11.2024 um 03:44 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:

    [...] different ways to represent zero?

    0 = 3-4+1 = 4-4 = 2*0 = 0

    ect.

    Right. "3-4+1", "4-4", "2*0", "0", are just different NAMEs (math:
    TERMs) to denote (refer to) _one and the same_ number, namely zero
    (usualy, denoted with "0").

    Hint: Superman is Clark Kent.

    Superman = Clark Kent


    Superman = Clark Kent = Kal-El

    Right. The names "Superman", "Clark Kent" and "Kal-El" denote one and
    the same person (being).

    We might extend that list by, say, "the only child of Jor-El and Lara
    Lor-Van", etc.

    0 = the predecessor of 1 = 1 - 1 = (the x in IR such that 1 + x = 1).

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Thu Nov 14 23:18:49 2024
    Am 14.11.2024 um 23:09 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:
    On 11/13/2024 3:28 PM, Moebius wrote:
    Am 14.11.2024 um 00:27 schrieb Moebius:
    Am 13.11.2024 um 03:44 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:

    [...] different ways to represent zero?

    0 = 3-4+1 = 4-4 = 2*0 = 0

    ect.

    Right. "3-4+1", "4-4", "2*0", "0", are just different NAMEs (math:
    TERMs) to denote (refer to) _one and the same_ number, namely zero
    (usualy, denoted with "0").

    Hint: Superman is Clark Kent.

    Superman = Clark Kent


    Superman = Clark Kent = Kal-El

    Right. The names "Superman", "Clark Kent" and "Kal-El" denote one and
    the same person (being).

    We might extend that list by, say, "the only child of Jor-El and Lara
    Lor-Van", etc.

    0 = the predecessor of 1 = 1 - 1 = the x in IR such that 1 + x = 1.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Thu Nov 14 23:47:15 2024
    Am 14.11.2024 um 23:27 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:
    On 11/14/2024 2:19 PM, Moebius wrote:
    Am 14.11.2024 um 23:09 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:
    On 11/13/2024 3:28 PM, Moebius wrote:
    Am 14.11.2024 um 00:27 schrieb Moebius:
    Am 13.11.2024 um 03:44 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:

    [...] different ways to represent zero?

    0 = 3-4+1 = 4-4 = 2*0 = 0

    ect.

    Right. "3-4+1", "4-4", "2*0", "0", are just different NAMEs (math:
    TERMs) to denote (refer to) _one and the same_ number, namely zero
    (usualy, denoted with "0").

    Hint: Superman is Clark Kent.

    Superman = Clark Kent


    Superman = Clark Kent = Kal-El

    Right. The names "Superman", "Clark Kent" and "Kal-El" denote one and
    the same person (being).

    We might extend that list by, say, "the only child of Jor-El and Lara
    Lor-Van", etc.

    0 = the predecessor of 1 = 1 - 1 = (the x in IR such that 1 + x = 1).


    For fun, define the "+" symbol to mean "having a child", so:

    (Jor-El + Lara Lor-Van) = (Superman = Clark Kent = Kal-El)

    ? lol.

    Nope, that won't work.

    For this we might define + , say, the following way:

    x + y = the child of x + y if x and y have exactly one child

    = the set of the children of x and y otherwise.

    Then

    Jor-El + Lara Lor-Van = Superman = Clark Kent = Kal-El

    and, say,

    Superman + Donald Trump = {} .

    "having a child (or children)" is a predicate, while "the child of ...
    and ..." is a term.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Thu Nov 14 23:48:39 2024
    Am 14.11.2024 um 23:27 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:
    On 11/14/2024 2:19 PM, Moebius wrote:
    Am 14.11.2024 um 23:09 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:
    On 11/13/2024 3:28 PM, Moebius wrote:
    Am 14.11.2024 um 00:27 schrieb Moebius:
    Am 13.11.2024 um 03:44 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:

    [...] different ways to represent zero?

    0 = 3-4+1 = 4-4 = 2*0 = 0

    ect.

    Right. "3-4+1", "4-4", "2*0", "0", are just different NAMEs (math:
    TERMs) to denote (refer to) _one and the same_ number, namely zero
    (usualy, denoted with "0").

    Hint: Superman is Clark Kent.

    Superman = Clark Kent


    Superman = Clark Kent = Kal-El

    Right. The names "Superman", "Clark Kent" and "Kal-El" denote one and
    the same person (being).

    We might extend that list by, say, "the only child of Jor-El and Lara
    Lor-Van", etc.

    0 = the predecessor of 1 = 1 - 1 = (the x in IR such that 1 + x = 1).


    For fun, define the "+" symbol to mean "having a child", so:

    (Jor-El + Lara Lor-Van) = (Superman = Clark Kent = Kal-El)

    ? lol.

    Nope, that won't work.

    For this we might define + , say, the following way:

    x + y = the child of x and y if x and y have exactly one child

    = the set of the children of x and y otherwise.

    Then

    Jor-El + Lara Lor-Van = Superman = Clark Kent = Kal-El

    and, say,

    Superman + Donald Trump = {} .

    "having a child (or children)" is a predicate, while "the child of ...
    and ..." is a term.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Thu Nov 14 23:55:31 2024
    Am 14.11.2024 um 23:48 schrieb Moebius:
    Am 14.11.2024 um 23:27 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:
    On 11/14/2024 2:19 PM, Moebius wrote:
    Am 14.11.2024 um 23:09 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:
    On 11/13/2024 3:28 PM, Moebius wrote:
    Am 14.11.2024 um 00:27 schrieb Moebius:
    Am 13.11.2024 um 03:44 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:

    [...] different ways to represent zero?

    0 = 3-4+1 = 4-4 = 2*0 = 0

    ect.

    Right. "3-4+1", "4-4", "2*0", "0", are just different NAMEs (math: >>>>>> TERMs) to denote (refer to) _one and the same_ number, namely zero >>>>>> (usualy, denoted with "0").

    Hint: Superman is Clark Kent.

    Superman = Clark Kent


    Superman = Clark Kent = Kal-El

    Right. The names "Superman", "Clark Kent" and "Kal-El" denote one and
    the same person (being).

    We might extend that list by, say, "the only child of Jor-El and Lara
    Lor-Van", etc.

    0 = the predecessor of 1 = 1 - 1 = (the x in IR such that 1 + x = 1).


    For fun, define the "+" symbol to mean "having a child", so:

    (Jor-El + Lara Lor-Van) = (Superman = Clark Kent = Kal-El)

    ? lol.

    Nope, that won't work.

    For this we might define + , say, the following way:

          x + y = the child of x and y    if x and y have exactly one child

                = the set of the children of x and y     otherwise.

    Then

          Jor-El + Lara Lor-Van = Superman = Clark Kent = Kal-El

    and, say,

          Superman + Donald Trump = {} .

    "having a child (or children)" is a predicate, while "the child of ...
    and ..." is a term.

    Actually, it would be even better to define + the following way:

    x + y = _the set_ of children of x and y (where x,y are
    persons)

    Then

    Jor-El + Lara Lor-Van = {Superman} = {Clark Kent} = {Kal-El} ,

    Adam + Eva = {Kain, Abel, ...}
    and
    Superman + Donald Trump = {} .

    Simpler and more consistent.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Fri Nov 15 11:10:04 2024
    On 14.11.2024 19:31, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/14/2024 5:20 AM, WM wrote:
    On 14.11.2024 00:16, Jim Burns wrote:

    Therefore
    a geometric representation let alone proof of
    most of Cantor's bijections is impossible.

    Consider geometry.

    For two triangles △A′B′C′ and △A″B″C″
    if
    △A′B′C′ and △A″B″C″ are similar triangles
    ⎛ μ∠C′A′B′ = μ∠C″A″B″
    ⎜ μ∠A′B′C′ = μ∠A″B″C″
    ⎜ μ∠B′C′A′ = μ∠B″C″A″
    ⎝ △A′B′C′ ∼ △A″B″C″
    then
    corresponding sides are in the same ratio
    ( μA︫︭′︭B︫′/μA︫︭″︭B︫″ = μB︫︭′︭C︫′/μB︫︭″︭C︫″ = μA︫︭′︭C︫′/μA︫︭″︭C︫″

    For similar △A′B′C′ ∼ △A″B″C″
    if μA︫︭′︭B︫′ = 1
     and μB︫︭″︭C︫″ = x
    then 1/μA︫︭″︭B︫″ = μB︫︭′︭C︫′/x
     and μA︫︭″︭B︫″ = μB︫︭′︭C︫′ = x¹ᐟ²

    For similar △A′B′C′ ∼ △A″B″C″
    if μA︫︭′︭B︫′ = 1
     and μA︫︭″︭B︫″ = x
     and μB︫︭′︭C︫′ = y
    then 1/x = y/μB︫︭″︭C︫″
     and μB︫︭″︭C︫″ = x⋅y

    For similar △A′B′C′ ∼ △A″B″C″
    if μA︫︭′︭B︫′ = 1
     and μA︫︭″︭B︫″ = x
     and μB︫︭″︭C︫″ = y
    then 1/x = μB︫︭′︭C︫′/y
     and μB︫︭′︭C︫′ = y/x

    The ceiling ⌈x⌉ of x is the first integer ≥ x

    Therefore
    a geometric representation let alone proof of
    most of Cantor's bijections is impossible.

    Your writing is unreadable but that does not matter because of course
    only a disproof is possible, since there are no bijections. One simple
    disproof is based on these intervals I(n) = [n - 1/10, n + 1/10].

    Cantor's bijection is
    k ↦ i/j
    i︭+︭j := ⌈(2⋅k+¼)¹ᐟ²+½⌉
    i := k-(i︭+︭j-1)⋅(i︭+︭j-2)/2
    j := i︭+︭j-i
    (i+j-1)⋅(i+j-2)/2+i = k

    Setting aside for a moment
    what you _think_ Cantor's bijection is,
    what part of _that_
    is impossible to represent geometrically?

    It is impossible to cover the matrix
    XOOO...
    XOOO...
    XOOO...
    XOOO...
    ...
    by shuffling, shifting, reordering the X, because they are not
    distinguishable.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Fri Nov 15 11:04:33 2024
    On 14.11.2024 19:31, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/14/2024 5:20 AM, WM wrote:

    Here is a single claim which is true:

    You don't say what reason you (WM) have
    for knowing that that single claim is true.

    It can be proven for every finite geometric figure that covering it by
    small pieces or intervals does not depend on the individuality and
    therefore on the order of the pieces.
    That means if there is a configuration where the figure is not covered completely, every possible shuffling will also fail.

    For infinite figures we use the analytical limit as is normal in
    mathematics.

    Example:
    XOOO...
    XOOO...
    XOOO...
    XOOO...
    ...
    One X per line is a density which can never be increased by reordering.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to joes on Fri Nov 15 12:43:47 2024
    On 15.11.2024 12:31, joes wrote:
    Am Fri, 15 Nov 2024 11:04:33 +0100 schrieb WM:

    It can be proven for every finite geometric figure that covering it by
    small pieces or intervals does not depend on the individuality and
    therefore on the order of the pieces.
    That means if there is a configuration where the figure is not covered
    completely, every possible shuffling will also fail.
    Duh. If some configuration doesn't cover it, shuffling the pieces changes nothing. But there may be other configurations that do cover the figure.

    All configurations possible by the initial set of pieces can be obtained
    by shifting them.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From joes@21:1/5 to All on Fri Nov 15 11:31:50 2024
    Am Fri, 15 Nov 2024 11:04:33 +0100 schrieb WM:

    It can be proven for every finite geometric figure that covering it by
    small pieces or intervals does not depend on the individuality and
    therefore on the order of the pieces.
    That means if there is a configuration where the figure is not covered completely, every possible shuffling will also fail.
    Duh. If some configuration doesn't cover it, shuffling the pieces changes nothing. But there may be other configurations that do cover the figure.

    --
    Am Sat, 20 Jul 2024 12:35:31 +0000 schrieb WM in sci.math:
    It is not guaranteed that n+1 exists for every n.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Fri Nov 15 12:54:52 2024
    On 11/15/2024 5:04 AM, WM wrote:
    On 14.11.2024 19:31, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/14/2024 5:20 AM, WM wrote:

    Here is a single claim which is true:

    You don't say what reason you (WM) have
    for knowing that that single claim is true.

    It can be proven

    for every finite geometric figure
    that covering it by small pieces or intervals
    does not depend on the individuality and
    therefore on the order of the pieces.
    That means
    if there is a configuration where
    the figure is not covered completely,
    every possible shuffling will also fail.

    For infinite figures
    we use the analytical limit
    as is normal in mathematics.

    The reason you (WM) give is that
    ☠⎛ whatever is true of all finite
    ☠⎝ is also true of the infinite.

    You (WM) are misinterpreting the infinite as
    ☠( just like the finite, but bigger.

    The finite are the countable.to from.nothing.
    Anything countable.to from.nothing is finite.
    It's what.we.mean.

    It isn't a boundary which distinguishes
    the infinite from the finite,
    not even a dark, inaccessible boundary.

    It is a property which distinguishes
    the infinite from the finite,
    being countable.to from nothing.


    Each countable.to from.nothing
    is countable.past
    to a further countable.to from.nothing.
    and thus
    is not.last countable.to from.nothing.

    There is no last.countable.to from.nothing,
    not even
    ☠( a dark last.countable.to from.nothing.


    Each finite is countable.to from.nothing.
    All the finites are not countable.to from.nothing.
    All the finites are infinitely.many.

    ⎛ A finite set A can be ordered so that,
    ⎜ for each subset B of A,
    ⎜ either B holds first.in.B and last.in.B
    ⎜ or B is empty.

    ⎜ An infinite set is not finite.
    ⎜ An infinite set C can _only_ be ordered so that
    ⎜ there is a non.empty subset D of C, such that
    ⎜ either first.in.D or last.in.D or both don't exist,
    ⎜ not visibly and not darkly.

    ⎝ And our sets do not change.

    It's what.we.mean.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Fri Nov 15 12:55:01 2024
    On 11/15/2024 5:10 AM, WM wrote:
    On 14.11.2024 19:31, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/14/2024 5:20 AM, WM wrote:

    Therefore
    a geometric representation let alone proof of
    most of Cantor's bijections is impossible.

    Consider geometry.

    For two triangles △A′B′C′ and △A″B″C″
    if
    △A′B′C′ and △A″B″C″ are similar triangles

    then
    corresponding sides are in the same ratio

    Therefore
    a geometric representation let alone proof of
    most of Cantor's bijections is impossible.

    Your writing is unreadable

    A geometric representation of
    square.root, multiplication, and division exist.
    One representation uses similar triangles.

    Also, a geometric representation of
    addition, subtraction, and order exist.

    Cantor's bijection ⟨i,j⟩ ↦ k ↦ ⟨i,j⟩
    ⎛ k = (i+j-1)⋅(i+j-2)/2+i
    ⎜ i = k-⌈(2⋅k+¼)¹ᐟ²-1/2⌉⋅⌈(2⋅k+¼)¹ᐟ²-3/2⌉/2
    ⎝ j = ⌈(2⋅k+¼)¹ᐟ²+1/2⌉⋅⌈(2⋅k+¼)¹ᐟ²-1/2⌉/2-1-k
    is composed of
    square.root, multiplication, division, addition,
    subtraction, and ⌈ceiling⌉ (order),
    for all of which geometric representations exist.

    but that does not matter because
    of course only a disproof is possible,
    since there are no bijections.

    After all bijections are excluded,
    of course there are no bijections.

    On the other hand,
    ⎛ k = (i+j-1)⋅(i+j-2)/2+i
    ⎜ i = k-⌈(2⋅k+¼)¹ᐟ²-1/2⌉⋅⌈(2⋅k+¼)¹ᐟ²-3/2⌉/2
    ⎝ j = ⌈(2⋅k+¼)¹ᐟ²+1/2⌉⋅⌈(2⋅k+¼)¹ᐟ²-1/2⌉/2-1-k
    exists.

    Setting aside for a moment
    what you _think_ Cantor's bijection is,
    what part of _that_
    is impossible to represent geometrically?

    It is impossible to cover the matrix
    XOOO...
    XOOO...
    XOOO...
    XOOO...
    ...
    by shuffling, shifting, reordering the X,
    because they are not distinguishable.

    ⟨k,1⟩ ↦ ⟨i,j⟩ ↤ ⟨k,1⟩

    ⎛ i = k-⌈(2⋅k+¼)¹ᐟ²-1/2⌉⋅⌈(2⋅k+¼)¹ᐟ²-3/2⌉/2
    ⎜ j = ⌈(2⋅k+¼)¹ᐟ²+1/2⌉⋅⌈(2⋅k+¼)¹ᐟ²-1/2⌉/2-1-k
    ⎝ k = (i+j-1)⋅(i+j-2)/2+i

    Each ⟨k,1⟩ sends X to ⟨i,j⟩
    Each ⟨i,j⟩ receives X from ⟨k,1⟩

    According to geometry.
    Which I predict makes geometry wrong[WM], too.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Fri Nov 15 15:06:12 2024
    On 11/15/2024 1:05 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On 11/15/2024 09:55 AM, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/15/2024 5:10 AM, WM wrote:
    On 14.11.2024 19:31, Jim Burns wrote:

    Setting aside for a moment
    what you _think_ Cantor's bijection is,
    what part of _that_
    is impossible to represent geometrically?

    It is impossible to cover the matrix
    XOOO...
    XOOO...
    XOOO...
    XOOO...
    ...
    by shuffling, shifting, reordering the X,
    because they are not distinguishable.

    ⟨k,1⟩ ↦ ⟨i,j⟩ ↤ ⟨k,1⟩

    ⎛ i = k-⌈(2⋅k+¼)¹ᐟ²-1/2⌉⋅⌈(2⋅k+¼)¹ᐟ²-3/2⌉/2
    ⎜ j = ⌈(2⋅k+¼)¹ᐟ²+1/2⌉⋅⌈(2⋅k+¼)¹ᐟ²-1/2⌉/2-1-k
    ⎝ k = (i+j-1)⋅(i+j-2)/2+i

    Each ⟨k,1⟩ sends X to ⟨i,j⟩
    Each ⟨i,j⟩ receives X from ⟨k,1⟩

    According to geometry.
    Which I predict makes geometry wrong[WM], too.

    Non-standard models of integers exist.

    Non.standard models of integers are not
    standard models of integers.

    Consider
    a finite sequence of claims which begins with
    a description of the standard model ℕ of integers,
    a description such as
    ⎛ i+1≠0 ∧ j≠k⇒j+1≠k+1
    ⎜ 0 ∈ ℕ ∧ '+1':ℕ→ℕ
    ⎜ 0 ∈ S ∧ '+1':S→S ⇒ ℕ ⊆ S
    ⎝ ...

    There are
    models for which that is incorrect.

    However,
    suppose we are discussing only
    models for which that is correct.

    In that case,
    those are true claims, and,
    if we augment that finite sequence with only
    claims which are true.or.not.first.false,
    each of those augmenting claims is true
    -- true about the standard model.

    If this claim sequence,
    which starts with a standard.model.description,
    is read as making claims about NON.standard models,
    we can't give a similar guarantee.

    Yes,
    not.first.false claims are still
    not.first.false claims,
    but, if they follow a false claim
    (about, let's say, a non.standard model),
    they can be true or false and still not.first.false.

    Non-standard models of integers exist.

    Yes, and,
    when we discuss non.standard models,
    we can assemble claim.sequences which
    start with a description of a non.standard model.
    And, when we do that,
    augmenting true.or.not.false claims
    will be true about the described non.standard models.

    However,
    non.standard models of integers are not
    standard models of integers.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Fri Nov 15 15:11:30 2024
    On 11/15/2024 1:24 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On 11/15/2024 10:05 AM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On 11/15/2024 09:55 AM, Jim Burns wrote:

    [...]

    Non-standard models of integers exist.

    "A restriction of comprehension is not a truth."

    A finite sequence of claims, each claim of which
    is true.or.not.first.false, is
    a finite sequence of claims, each claim of which
    is true.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Fri Nov 15 22:54:10 2024
    On 15.11.2024 18:55, Jim Burns wrote:

    Each ⟨k,1⟩ sends X to ⟨i,j⟩
    Each ⟨i,j⟩ receives X from ⟨k,1⟩

    Remember that your sets do not change.Therefore the number of X remains
    fixed. The X appearing in the upper lines are missing in the lower lines.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Fri Nov 15 22:53:36 2024
    On 15.11.2024 18:54, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/15/2024 5:04 AM, WM wrote:

    For infinite figures
    we use the analytical limit
    as is normal in mathematics.

    The reason you (WM) give is that
    ☠⎛ whatever is true of all finite
    ☠⎝ is also true of the infinite.

    Not "whatever" but well-established rules.

    You (WM) are misinterpreting the infinite as
    ☠( just like the finite, but bigger.

    You are believing that the infinite can do magic. I believe that limits
    of simple sequences can be calculated. The sequence 1/5, 1/5, 1/5, ...
    has the limit 1/5 after all terms. It does never deviate.

    The finite are the countable.to from.nothing.
    Anything countable.to from.nothing is finite.
    It's what.we.mean.

    Either we can calculate the infinite by means of the finite relations,
    or this will forever remain impossible. Only in the latter case your
    argument is acceptable. But why do you believe in Cantor's bijections if
    the infinite can disobey all logic?

    If it is possible that the set {10^10^10^n, 10^10^10^m, n, m ∈ ℕ} has precisely as many elements as the set of algebraic numbers (i.e., if
    there can exist a bijection), then there is no trust in bijections.

    If the intervals [n - 1/10, n + 1/10] can infinitely often cover the
    real line, then there is no trust in geometry.

    And our sets do not change.

    Then the density 1/5 will never change. Then never a new guest can be accomodated in the fully occupied Hilbert's hotel.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Fri Nov 15 17:41:52 2024
    On 11/15/2024 4:32 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On 11/15/2024 12:11 PM, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/15/2024 1:24 PM, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On 11/15/2024 10:05 AM, Ross Finlayson wrote:

    Non-standard models of integers exist.

    "A restriction of comprehension is not a truth."

    A finite sequence of claims, each claim of which
    is true.or.not.first.false,  is
    a finite sequence of claims, each claim of which
    is true.

    A fragment, then.

    ...a finite sequence of claims ABOUT
    an infinite sequence sequence of integers...

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Sat Nov 16 01:27:25 2024
    Am 15.11.2024 um 22:58 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:

    Ugg, an infinite set is never exhausted. Taking a gallon of water out of
    an infinite pool of water means you are holding a gallon water, but the infinite pool is still infinite. The same. Taking an infinite amount of
    water means the pool is still full of water.

    I already told you that this is not necessarily the case.

    See: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Ross%E2%80%93Littlewood_paradox#Vase_is_empty

    Hint: Let's consider your claim: "an infinite set is never exhausted".

    But IN \ {1} \ {2} \ {3} \ ... _should_ be {}, I'd say. After all, which natural number would "remain" (=be) in the set

    IN \ {1} \ {2} \ {3} \ ...

    ? :-P

    Yeah, slightly "paradoxical". IN \ {1} is infinite, IN \ {1} \ {2} is
    infinite, IN \ {1} \ {2} \ {3} is infinite, etc. Actually, for each and
    everey natural number n: IN \ {1} \ ... \ {n} is infinite (in THIS sense
    your "never" is true). But what's about IN \ {1} \ {2} \ {3} \ ...?
    WHICH natural number would be in this set? :-P

    Be aware of the infinite!

    Remember:

    > You (WM) are misinterpreting the infinite as
    > ☠( just like the finite, but bigger.

    .
    .
    .

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Sat Nov 16 02:14:58 2024
    Am 15.11.2024 um 22:58 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:
    On 11/15/2024 1:53 PM, WM wrote:

    The sequence 1/5, 1/5, 1/5, ... has the limit 1/5 after all terms.

    @Mückenheim: Du redest wieder einmal nur saudummen Scheißdreck daher.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Sat Nov 16 01:26:37 2024
    Am 15.11.2024 um 22:58 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:

    Ugg, an infinite set is never exhausted. Taking a gallon of water out of
    an infinite pool of water means you are holding a gallon water, but the infinite pool is still infinite. The same. Taking an infinite amount of
    water means the pool is still full of water.

    I already told you that this is not necessarily the case.

    See: hhttps://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Ross%E2%80%93Littlewood_paradox#Vase_is_empty

    Hint: Let's consider your claim: "an infinite set is never exhausted".

    But IN \ {1} \ {2} \ {3} \ ... _should_ be {}, I'd say. After all, which natural number would "remain" (=be) in the set

    IN \ {1} \ {2} \ {3} \ ...

    ? :-P

    Yeah, slightly "paradoxical". IN \ {1} is infinite, IN \ {1} \ {2} is
    infinite, IN \ {1} \ {2} \ {3} is infinite, etc. Actually, for each and
    everey natural number n: IN \ {1} \ ... \ {n} is infinite (in THIS sense
    your "never" is true). But what's about IN \ {1} \ {2} \ {3} \ ...?
    WHICH natural number would be in this set? :-P

    Be aware of the infinite!

    Remember:

    > You (WM) are misinterpreting the infinite as
    > ☠( just like the finite, but bigger.

    .
    .
    .

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Sat Nov 16 02:10:15 2024
    Am 16.11.2024 um 01:27 schrieb Moebius:

    Hint: Let's consider your claim: "an infinite set is never exhausted".

    But IN \ {1} \ {2} \ {3} \ ... _should_ be {}, I'd say. After all, which natural number would "remain" (=be) in the set

                  IN \ {1} \ {2} \ {3} \ ...

    ? :-P

    Yeah, slightly "paradoxical". IN \ {1} is infinite, IN \ {1} \ {2} is infinite, IN \ {1} \ {2} \ {3} is infinite, etc. Actually, for each and everey natural number n: IN \ {1} \ ... \ {n} is infinite (in THIS sense
    your "never" is true). But what's about IN \ {1} \ {2} \ {3} \ ...?
    WHICH natural number would be in this set? :-P

    Be aware of the infinite!

    Remember:

    ; You (WM) are misinterpreting the infinite as
    ; ☠( just like the finite, but bigger.

    .
    .
    .

    Actually, I'd prefer to consider a related problem (for certain
    technical reasons).

    Consider the (infinitely many) unions:

    {1} u {2}, {1} u {2} u {3}, ...

    Here you might claim: "an union of finite sets will never be infinite",
    after all for each and every n e IN:

    {1} u ... u {n}

    is finite (namely {1, ..., n}). (Hint: Thats WM's "position".)

    But actually,

    {1} u {2} u {3} u ...

    IS infinite, namely {1, 2, 3, ...} = IN.

    Technically, in set theory there's a certain union operation U which
    allows to "unite" infinitely many sets. There we would write:

    U{{1}, {2}, {3}, ...} = {1, 2, 3, ...} .

    [If we want to be PRECISE: U{{n} : n e IN} = IN.}

    Hope this helps.

    .
    .
    .

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Sat Nov 16 02:32:02 2024
    Am 15.11.2024 um 22:58 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson: [...]

    Try this one: https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=lNYcviXK4rg

    :-)

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Sat Nov 16 04:18:41 2024
    Am 16.11.2024 um 01:27 schrieb Moebius:
    Am 15.11.2024 um 22:58 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:

    [...] Taking a gallon of water out
    of an infinite pool of water means you are holding a gallon water, but
    the infinite pool is still infinite. The same. Taking an infinite
    amount of water means the pool is still full of water.

    I already told you that this is not necessarily the case.

    Assume that the H20 molecules in the pool are "numerated" by 1, 2, 3,
    ... (i.e. that ALL H20 molecules in the pool are "numerated" by natural numbers).

    Taking out the "infinite amount of H20 molecules" numerated by 1, 2, 3,
    ... would lead to an EMPTY pool.

    On the other hand, taking out the "infinite amount of H20 molecules"
    numerated by 2, 4, 6, ... would not drain the pool. :-P It would still
    be filled (sort of) with infinitely many H20 molecules. :-P

    Be aware if the infinite, man!

    .
    .
    .

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Sat Nov 16 22:33:17 2024
    Am 16.11.2024 um 22:09 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:
    On 11/16/2024 1:07 PM, Chris M. Thomasson wrote:

    (infinity - infinity) = infinity

    (infinity - infinity) = undefined

    Exactly!

    For example "aleph_0 - aleph_0" is not defined.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Moebius on Sat Nov 16 22:28:08 2024
    On 16.11.2024 04:18, Moebius wrote:

    Taking out the "infinite amount of H20 molecules" numerated by 1, 2, 3,
    ... would lead to an EMPTY pool.

    Although this can only be done collectively. Individually it is
    impossible, even if every take lasted only half the time of the previous
    take.

    On the other hand, taking out the "infinite amount of H20 molecules" numerated by 2, 4, 6, ... would not drain the pool. :-P It would still
    be filled (sort of) with infinitely many H20 molecules. :-P

    Be aware if the infinite, man!

    Be aware of logic! If you assume the ordered set of natural numbers

    1-2-3-4-5-6-7-...

    and take out the even numbers, then you obtain that is half the set

    1- -3- -5- -7-... .

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Sat Nov 16 22:36:41 2024
    Am 16.11.2024 um 22:11 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:
    On 11/16/2024 1:09 PM, Chris M. Thomasson wrote:

    (infinity - infinity) = undefined

    ?

    Right.

    Say taking all of the infinite even numbers away... That leaves an
    infinite number of odd numbers? This type of thought.

    Exactly.

    IN = {1, 2, 3, 4, ...} is infinite and E = {2, 4, 6, ...} is infinite.

    But {1, 2, 3, 4, ...} \ {2, 4, 6, ...} is still infinite.

    While on the other hand

    {1, 2, 3, 4, ...} \ {1, 2, 3, 4, ...} = {} (and hence not infinite).

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Sat Nov 16 23:11:30 2024
    Am 16.11.2024 um 22:48 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:
    On 11/16/2024 1:29 PM, FromTheRafters wrote:
    Chris M. Thomasson pretended:

    (infinity - infinity) = undefined

    ?

    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/
    L%27H%C3%B4pital%27s_rule#Other_indeterminate_forms

    Or this one: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Indeterminate_form

    "oo - oo" is an "indeterminate form".

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Sat Nov 16 22:51:22 2024
    Am 16.11.2024 um 22:48 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:
    On 11/16/2024 1:29 PM, FromTheRafters wrote:
    Chris M. Thomasson pretended :
    On 11/16/2024 1:07 PM, Chris M. Thomasson wrote:
    (infinity - infinity) = infinity

    (infinity - infinity) = undefined

    ?

    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/
    L%27H%C3%B4pital%27s_rule#Other_indeterminate_forms

    For some strange reason reading that made me think of the following song:

    https://youtu.be/Sdq4T3iRV80?list=RDMMy3hf0T4qpYg

    lol!

    Yusuf / Cat Stevens --- good man! Damn!

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Sat Nov 16 22:53:03 2024
    Am 16.11.2024 um 22:51 schrieb Moebius:
    Am 16.11.2024 um 22:48 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:
    On 11/16/2024 1:29 PM, FromTheRafters wrote:
    Chris M. Thomasson pretended :
    On 11/16/2024 1:07 PM, Chris M. Thomasson wrote:
    (infinity - infinity) = infinity

    (infinity - infinity) = undefined

    ?

    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/
    L%27H%C3%B4pital%27s_rule#Other_indeterminate_forms

    For some strange reason reading that made me think of the following song:

    https://youtu.be/Sdq4T3iRV80?list=RDMMy3hf0T4qpYg

    lol!

    Yusuf / Cat Stevens --- good man! Damn!

    Btw. Yusuf = Cat Stevens.

    :-)

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Sat Nov 16 23:22:36 2024
    Am 16.11.2024 um 23:16 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:
    On 11/16/2024 2:11 PM, Moebius wrote:
    Am 16.11.2024 um 22:48 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:
    On 11/16/2024 1:29 PM, FromTheRafters wrote:
    Chris M. Thomasson pretended:

    (infinity - infinity) = undefined

    ?

    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/
    L%27H%C3%B4pital%27s_rule#Other_indeterminate_forms

    Or this one: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Indeterminate_form

    "oo - oo" is an "indeterminate form".


    I must be missing something: [...]

    [1] = a gallon of water out of an infinite pool
    [2] = another gallon of water out of an infinite pool
    [3] = on and on... taken to infinity...

    The pool would always have infinite water for this process?

    Assume that the H2O molecules in the pool are "numerated" by 1, 2, 3,
    ... (i.e. that ALL H2O molecules in the pool are "numerated" by natural numbers).

    Taking out the "infinite amount of H2O molecules" numerated by 1, 2, 3,
    ... would lead to an EMPTY pool.

    On the other hand, taking out the "infinite amount of H2O molecules"
    numerated by 2, 4, 6, ... would not drain the pool. 😛 It would still be filled (sort of) with infinitely many H20 molecules. 😛

    Be aware if the infinite, man!

    .
    .
    .

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Sat Nov 16 23:37:41 2024
    Am 16.11.2024 um 23:22 schrieb Moebius:
    Am 16.11.2024 um 23:16 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:
    On 11/16/2024 2:11 PM, Moebius wrote:
    Am 16.11.2024 um 22:48 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:
    On 11/16/2024 1:29 PM, FromTheRafters wrote:
    Chris M. Thomasson pretended:

    (infinity - infinity) = undefined

    ?

    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/
    L%27H%C3%B4pital%27s_rule#Other_indeterminate_forms

    Or this one: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Indeterminate_form

    "oo - oo" is an "indeterminate form".


    I must be missing something: [...]

    [1] = a gallon of water out of an infinite pool
    [2] = another gallon of water out of an infinite pool
    [3] = on and on... taken to infinity...

    The pool would always have infinite water for this process?

    Assume that the H2O molecules in the pool are "numerated" by 1, 2,
    3, ... (i.e. that ALL H2O molecules in the pool are "numerated" by
    natural numbers).

    Taking out the "infinite amount of H2O molecules" numerated by 1, 2,
    3, ... would lead to an EMPTY pool.

    Hint: If the first gallon of water consists of the H2O molecules
    numbered by 1, ..., n_1, the second gallon of water consists of the H2O molecules numbered by n_1, ..., n_2 (with n_2 > n_1), and so on, the
    "outcome" would be an empty pool. (Hint: try to name the number attached
    to an H2O molecule which "remains" in the pool.)

    On the other hand, taking out the "infinite amount of H2O molecules" numerated by 2, 4, 6, ... would not drain the pool. 😛 It would still be filled (sort of) with infinitely many H20 molecules. 😛

    Be aware if the infinite, man!

    .
    .
    .


    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Sat Nov 16 23:36:52 2024
    Am 16.11.2024 um 23:22 schrieb Moebius:
    Am 16.11.2024 um 23:16 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:
    On 11/16/2024 2:11 PM, Moebius wrote:
    Am 16.11.2024 um 22:48 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:
    On 11/16/2024 1:29 PM, FromTheRafters wrote:
    Chris M. Thomasson pretended:

    (infinity - infinity) = undefined

    ?

    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/
    L%27H%C3%B4pital%27s_rule#Other_indeterminate_forms

    Or this one: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Indeterminate_form

    "oo - oo" is an "indeterminate form".


    I must be missing something: [...]

    [1] = a gallon of water out of an infinite pool
    [2] = another gallon of water out of an infinite pool
    [3] = on and on... taken to infinity...

    The pool would always have infinite water for this process?

    Assume that the H2O molecules in the pool are "numerated" by 1, 2,
    3, ... (i.e. that ALL H2O molecules in the pool are "numerated" by
    natural numbers).

    Taking out the "infinite amount of H2O molecules" numerated by 1, 2,
    3, ... would lead to an EMPTY pool.

    Hint: If the first gallon of water consists of the H2O molecules
    numbered by 1, ..., n_1, the second gallon of water consists of the H2O molecules numbered by n_1, ..., n_2 (with n_2 > n_1), and so on, the
    "outcome" would be in an empty pool. (Hint: try to name the number
    attached to an H2O molecule which "remains" in the pool.)

    On the other hand, taking out the "infinite amount of H2O molecules" numerated by 2, 4, 6, ... would not drain the pool. 😛 It would still be filled (sort of) with infinitely many H20 molecules. 😛

    Be aware if the infinite, man!

    .
    .
    .


    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Sun Nov 17 00:40:44 2024
    Am 16.11.2024 um 23:22 schrieb Moebius:
    Am 16.11.2024 um 23:16 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:
    On 11/16/2024 2:11 PM, Moebius wrote:
    Am 16.11.2024 um 22:48 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:
    On 11/16/2024 1:29 PM, FromTheRafters wrote:
    Chris M. Thomasson pretended:

    (infinity - infinity) = undefined

    ?

    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/
    L%27H%C3%B4pital%27s_rule#Other_indeterminate_forms

    Or this one: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Indeterminate_form

    "oo - oo" is an "indeterminate form".


    I must be missing something: [...]

    [1] = a gallon of water out of an infinite pool
    [2] = another gallon of water out of an infinite pool
    [3] = on and on... taken to infinity...

    The pool would always have infinite water for this process?

    Assume that the H2O molecules in the pool are "numerated" by 1, 2,
    3, ... (i.e. that ALL H2O molecules in the pool are "numerated" by
    natural numbers).

    Taking out the "infinite amount of H2O molecules" numerated by 1, 2,
    3, ... would lead to an EMPTY pool.

    Hint: If the first gallon of water consists of the H2O molecules
    numbered by 1, ..., n_1, the second gallon of water consists of the H2O molecules numbered by (n_1)+1, ..., n_2 (with n_2 > (n_1)+1), and so on,
    the "outcome" would be an empty pool. (Hint: try to name the number
    attached to an H2O molecule which "remains" in the pool.)

    On the other hand, taking out the "infinite amount of H2O molecules" numerated by 2, 4, 6, ... would not drain the pool. 😛 It would still be filled (sort of) with infinitely many H20 molecules. 😛

    Be aware if the infinite, man!

    .
    .
    .


    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Sun Nov 17 01:58:33 2024
    Am 17.11.2024 um 01:09 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:
    On 11/16/2024 2:22 PM, Moebius wrote:
    Am 16.11.2024 um 23:16 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:
    On 11/16/2024 2:11 PM, Moebius wrote:
    Am 16.11.2024 um 22:48 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:
    On 11/16/2024 1:29 PM, FromTheRafters wrote:
    Chris M. Thomasson pretended:

    (infinity - infinity) = undefined

    ?

    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/
    L%27H%C3%B4pital%27s_rule#Other_indeterminate_forms

    Or this one: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Indeterminate_form

    "oo - oo" is an "indeterminate form".


    I must be missing something: [...]

    [1] = a gallon of water out of an infinite pool
    [2] = another gallon of water out of an infinite pool
    [3] = on and on... taken to infinity...

    The pool would always have infinite water for this process?

    Assume that the H2O molecules in the pool are "numerated" by 1, 2,
    3, ... (i.e. that ALL H2O molecules in the pool are "numerated" by
    natural numbers).

    Taking out the "infinite amount of H2O molecules" numerated by 1, 2,
    3, ... would lead to an EMPTY pool.

    On the other hand, taking out the "infinite amount of H2O molecules"
    numerated by 2, 4, 6, ... would not drain the pool. 😛 It would still
    be filled (sort of) with infinitely many H20 molecules. 😛

    Beware if the infinite, man!

    Shit.... Humm.... For fun, what about an infinite waterfall dumping into
    an already infinite pool, two separate objects. The pool will always
    accepts more water since it is infinite. Now, taking an infinite number
    of gallons of water out of the pool is interesting because of the
    infinite waterfall?
    Damn infinity! beware? ;^)

    Yeah, there's a reason for:

    "oo - oo" is an "indeterminate form".

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Moebius on Sun Nov 17 11:49:20 2024
    On 17.11.2024 00:40, Moebius wrote:

    Hint: If the first gallon of water consists of the H2O molecules
    numbered by 1, ..., n_1, the second gallon of water consists of the H2O molecules numbered by (n_1)+1, ..., n_2 (with n_2 > (n_1)+1), and so on,
    the "outcome" would be an empty pool.

    No. For every n_k almost all molecules remain.

    (Hint: try to name the number
    attached to an H2O molecule which "remains" in the pool.)

    They are dark.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Moebius on Sun Nov 17 11:40:54 2024
    On 16.11.2024 22:33, Moebius wrote:

    For example "aleph_0 - aleph_0" is not defined.

    Small wonder. ℵo means only infinitely many: |ℕ|, |ℚ|, and many others. |ℕ|-|ℕ| however is defined.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to FromTheRafters on Sun Nov 17 12:19:32 2024
    On 17.11.2024 12:01, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM was thinking very hard :
    On 16.11.2024 22:33, Moebius wrote:

    For example "aleph_0 - aleph_0" is not defined.

    Small wonder. ℵo means only infinitely many: |ℕ|, |ℚ|, and many others.
    |ℕ|-|ℕ| however is defined.

    No, it is not.

    If sets are invariable then ℕ \ ℕ is empty.
    If |ℕ| concerns only the elements of ℕ, then |ℕ|-|ℕ|= 0.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to FromTheRafters on Sun Nov 17 13:53:46 2024
    On 17.11.2024 12:38, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM presented the following explanation :
    On 17.11.2024 12:01, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM was thinking very hard :
    On 16.11.2024 22:33, Moebius wrote:

    For example "aleph_0 - aleph_0" is not defined.

    Small wonder. ℵo means only infinitely many: |ℕ|, |ℚ|, and many others.
    |ℕ|-|ℕ| however is defined.

    No, it is not.

    If sets are invariable then ℕ \ ℕ is empty.
    If |ℕ| concerns only the elements of ℕ, then |ℕ|-|ℕ|= 0.

    So, you're saying that if I take aleph_zero natural numbers and I remove
    the aleph_zero odd numbers from consideration in a new set, I will have
    a new emptyset instead of E?

    Try to understand. "aleph_0 - aleph_0" is not defined.

    Regards, WM

    Your math is seriously flawed.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to FromTheRafters on Sun Nov 17 18:38:00 2024
    On 17.11.2024 17:59, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM pretended :
    On 17.11.2024 12:38, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM presented the following explanation :
    On 17.11.2024 12:01, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM was thinking very hard :
    On 16.11.2024 22:33, Moebius wrote:

    For example "aleph_0 - aleph_0" is not defined.

    Small wonder. ℵo means only infinitely many: |ℕ|, |ℚ|, and many >>>>>> others.
    |ℕ|-|ℕ| however is defined.

    No, it is not.

    If sets are invariable then ℕ \ ℕ is empty.
    If |ℕ| concerns only the elements of ℕ, then |ℕ|-|ℕ|= 0.

    So, you're saying that if I take aleph_zero natural numbers and I
    remove the aleph_zero odd numbers from consideration in a new set, I
    will have a new emptyset instead of E?

    Try to understand. "aleph_0 - aleph_0" is not defined.

    Try to understand that |N| equals aleph_zero.

    Of course. ℵo equals |ℕ|, equals |ℚ|, equals all countable sets. It is simply another name for infinitely "many". |ℕ| however is a fixed
    infinite number. Note that sets are invariable.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From joes@21:1/5 to All on Sun Nov 17 19:08:54 2024
    Am Sun, 17 Nov 2024 18:38:00 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 17.11.2024 17:59, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM pretended :
    On 17.11.2024 12:38, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM presented the following explanation :
    On 17.11.2024 12:01, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM was thinking very hard :
    On 16.11.2024 22:33, Moebius wrote:

    For example "aleph_0 - aleph_0" is not defined.

    Small wonder. ℵo means only infinitely many: |ℕ|, |ℚ|, and many >>>>>>> others. |ℕ|-|ℕ| however is defined.

    No, it is not.

    If sets are invariable then ℕ \ ℕ is empty.
    If |ℕ| concerns only the elements of ℕ, then |ℕ|-|ℕ|= 0.

    So, you're saying that if I take aleph_zero natural numbers and I
    remove the aleph_zero odd numbers from consideration in a new set, I
    will have a new emptyset instead of E?

    Try to understand. "aleph_0 - aleph_0" is not defined.
    Try to understand that |N| equals aleph_zero.

    Of course. ℵo equals |ℕ|, equals |ℚ|, equals all countable sets. It is simply another name for infinitely "many". |ℕ| however is a fixed
    infinite number. Note that sets are invariable.

    Yes, those are all the same number.

    --
    Am Sat, 20 Jul 2024 12:35:31 +0000 schrieb WM in sci.math:
    It is not guaranteed that n+1 exists for every n.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to joes on Sun Nov 17 20:24:48 2024
    On 17.11.2024 20:08, joes wrote:
    Am Sun, 17 Nov 2024 18:38:00 +0100 schrieb WM:

    Of course. ℵo equals |ℕ|, equals |ℚ|, equals all countable sets. It is >> simply another name for infinitely "many". |ℕ| however is a fixed
    infinite number. Note that sets are invariable.

    Yes, those are all the same number.

    It is the "number" many. ℚ has all elements of ℕ and some more.
    Therefore the correct numbers are different.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From joes@21:1/5 to All on Sun Nov 17 20:16:18 2024
    Am Sun, 17 Nov 2024 12:19:32 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 17.11.2024 12:01, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM was thinking very hard :
    On 16.11.2024 22:33, Moebius wrote:

    For example "aleph_0 - aleph_0" is not defined.

    Small wonder. ℵo means only infinitely many: |ℕ|, |ℚ|, and many
    others. |ℕ|-|ℕ| however is defined.

    No, it is not.

    If sets are invariable then ℕ \ ℕ is empty.
    If |ℕ| concerns only the elements of ℕ, then |ℕ|-|ℕ|= 0.
    The number |N|=|Q|=Aleph_0 is the same regardless of the set.
    If you define the difference to be zero, it doesn't matter.

    --
    Am Sat, 20 Jul 2024 12:35:31 +0000 schrieb WM in sci.math:
    It is not guaranteed that n+1 exists for every n.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to FromTheRafters on Mon Nov 18 17:35:42 2024
    On 17.11.2024 21:51, FromTheRafters wrote:
    It happens that WM formulated :
    On 17.11.2024 17:59, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM pretended :
    On 17.11.2024 12:38, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM presented the following explanation :
    On 17.11.2024 12:01, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM was thinking very hard :
    On 16.11.2024 22:33, Moebius wrote:

    For example "aleph_0 - aleph_0" is not defined.

    Small wonder. ℵo means only infinitely many: |ℕ|, |ℚ|, and many >>>>>>>> others.
    |ℕ|-|ℕ| however is defined.

    No, it is not.

    If sets are invariable then ℕ \ ℕ is empty.
    If |ℕ| concerns only the elements of ℕ, then |ℕ|-|ℕ|= 0.

    So, you're saying that if I take aleph_zero natural numbers and I
    remove the aleph_zero odd numbers from consideration in a new set,
    I will have a new emptyset instead of E?

    Try to understand. "aleph_0 - aleph_0" is not defined.

    Try to understand that |N| equals aleph_zero.

    Of course. ℵo equals |ℕ|, equals |ℚ|, equals all countable sets. It is >> simply another name for infinitely "many". |ℕ| however is a fixed
    infinite number. Note that sets are invariable.

    But you said both that it equals zero and that it is undefined. You
    should pick one and be consistent.

    I said that |ℕ| and |ℚ| and |ℕ| - 5 and |ℕ| + 6 etc. equal ℵo. That means that ℵo is nothing but "infinitely many". Therefore ℵo - ℵo is undefined but |ℕ| - |ℕ| = 0 and |ℚ| - |ℕ| > 0.

    |ℕ| - |ℕ| = 0 because if you subtract one element from ℕ then you have
    no longer ℕ and therefore no longer |ℕ| describing it.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to FromTheRafters on Mon Nov 18 17:58:20 2024
    On 17.11.2024 21:59, FromTheRafters wrote:

    It is sometimes better to think of cardinality as a number indicating a notion of 'set size' rather than a notion of 'number many'. For finite
    sets these two notions merge.

    In the infinite they differ:
    ℵo is not the same as |ℕ| although |ℕ| is in the set of numbers
    described by ℵo.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to joes on Mon Nov 18 17:24:19 2024
    On 17.11.2024 21:16, joes wrote:
    Am Sun, 17 Nov 2024 12:19:32 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 17.11.2024 12:01, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM was thinking very hard :
    On 16.11.2024 22:33, Moebius wrote:

    For example "aleph_0 - aleph_0" is not defined.

    Small wonder. ℵo means only infinitely many: |ℕ|, |ℚ|, and many
    others. |ℕ|-|ℕ| however is defined.

    No, it is not.

    If sets are invariable then ℕ \ ℕ is empty.
    If |ℕ| concerns only the elements of ℕ, then |ℕ|-|ℕ|= 0.

    The number |N|=|Q|=Aleph_0 is the same regardless of the set.

    Yes it is the expression that the set has infinitely many elements. But
    it is not specific to any set.

    If you subtract any natural number from ℕ, then you have another set, no longer ℕ. But the cardinality remains ℵo. Therefore it does not describe the set ℕ.

    If you define the difference to be zero, it doesn't matter.

    Of course not. ℵo means infinitely many, not more.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to FromTheRafters on Mon Nov 18 18:52:41 2024
    On 18.11.2024 18:11, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM pretended :
    On 17.11.2024 21:59, FromTheRafters wrote:

    It is sometimes better to think of cardinality as a number indicating
    a notion of 'set size' rather than a notion of 'number many'. For
    finite sets these two notions merge.

    In the infinite they differ:
    ℵo is not the same as |ℕ| although |ℕ| is in the set of numbers
    described by ℵo.

    aleph_zero is the same object as the cardinality of N.

    Yes, but |ℕ| is the number of elements of ℕ.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to FromTheRafters on Mon Nov 18 19:20:24 2024
    On 18.11.2024 18:15, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM brought next idea :

    |ℕ| - |ℕ| = 0 because if you subtract one element from ℕ then you have
    no longer ℕ and therefore no longer |ℕ| describing it.

    Still wrong.

    If you remove one element from ℕ, then you have still ℵo but no longer
    all elements of ℕ. If |ℕ| describes the number of elements, then it has changed to |ℕ| - 1. If you don't like |ℕ| then call this number the
    number of natural numbers.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to FromTheRafters on Mon Nov 18 23:12:07 2024
    On 18.11.2024 22:53, FromTheRafters wrote:
    on 11/18/2024, WM supposed :
    On 18.11.2024 18:11, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM pretended :
    On 17.11.2024 21:59, FromTheRafters wrote:

    It is sometimes better to think of cardinality as a number
    indicating a notion of 'set size' rather than a notion of 'number
    many'. For finite sets these two notions merge.

    In the infinite they differ:
    ℵo is not the same as |ℕ| although |ℕ| is in the set of numbers
    described by ℵo.

    aleph_zero is the same object as the cardinality of N.

    Yes, but |ℕ| is the number of elements of ℕ.

    Or, more generally, it is the "SIZE" of the set. Size equals the number
    of elements in a *FINITE* set.

    You said aleph_zero minus aleph_zero was different to the cardinality of
    N

    |ℕ| is the number of elements, not the cardinality!

    aleph_zero *IS* the cardinality of N.

    Of course, but it is also the cardinality of all other countable sets
    which have more or fewer elements.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to FromTheRafters on Mon Nov 18 23:16:22 2024
    On 18.11.2024 22:58, FromTheRafters wrote:
    on 11/18/2024, WM supposed :
    On 18.11.2024 18:15, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM brought next idea :

    |ℕ| - |ℕ| = 0 because if you subtract one element from ℕ then you have
    no longer ℕ and therefore no longer |ℕ| describing it.

    Still wrong.

    If you remove one element from ℕ, then you have still ℵo but no longer >> all elements of ℕ.

    But you do have now a proper subset of the naturals the same size as
    before.

    It has one element less, hence the "size" ℵo is a very unsharp measure.

    If |ℕ| describes the number of elements, then it has changed to |ℕ| - 1.

    Minus one is not defined.

    Subtracting an element is defined. |ℕ| - 1 is defined as the number of elements minus 1.

    If you don't like |ℕ| then call this number the number of natural
    numbers.

    Why would I do that when it is the *SIZE* of the smallest infinite set.

    The set of prime numbers is smaller.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From joes@21:1/5 to All on Tue Nov 19 12:01:09 2024
    Am Mon, 18 Nov 2024 17:24:19 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 17.11.2024 21:16, joes wrote:
    Am Sun, 17 Nov 2024 12:19:32 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 17.11.2024 12:01, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM was thinking very hard :
    On 16.11.2024 22:33, Moebius wrote:

    For example "aleph_0 - aleph_0" is not defined.

    Small wonder. ℵo means only infinitely many: |ℕ|, |ℚ|, and many >>>>> others. |ℕ|-|ℕ| however is defined.

    No, it is not.

    If sets are invariable then ℕ \ ℕ is empty.
    If |ℕ| concerns only the elements of ℕ, then |ℕ|-|ℕ|= 0.

    The number |N|=|Q|=Aleph_0 is the same regardless of the set.

    Yes it is the expression that the set has infinitely many elements. But
    it is not specific to any set.
    Duh.

    If you subtract any natural number from ℕ, then you have another set, no longer ℕ. But the cardinality remains ℵo. Therefore it does not describe the set ℕ.
    I can't follow.

    --
    Am Sat, 20 Jul 2024 12:35:31 +0000 schrieb WM in sci.math:
    It is not guaranteed that n+1 exists for every n.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From joes@21:1/5 to All on Tue Nov 19 12:05:51 2024
    Am Mon, 18 Nov 2024 23:16:22 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 18.11.2024 22:58, FromTheRafters wrote:
    on 11/18/2024, WM supposed :
    On 18.11.2024 18:15, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM brought next idea :

    |ℕ| - |ℕ| = 0 because if you subtract one element from ℕ then you >>>>>> have no longer ℕ and therefore no longer |ℕ| describing it.
    |N\{0}| = |N| = Aleph_0

    If you remove one element from ℕ, then you have still ℵo but no longer >>> all elements of ℕ.
    But you do have now a proper subset of the naturals the same size as
    before.
    It has one element less, hence the "size" ℵo is a very unsharp measure.
    You can still say it is a subset, like Cantor did with "reality".

    If |ℕ| describes the number of elements, then it has changed to |ℕ| - >>> 1.
    Minus one is not defined.
    Subtracting an element is defined. |ℕ| - 1 is defined as the number of elements minus 1.
    And |N\{2}| = Aleph_0.

    If you don't like |ℕ| then call this number the number of natural
    numbers.
    Why would I do that when it is the *SIZE* of the smallest infinite set.
    The set of prime numbers is smaller.
    There are infinitely many of them.

    --
    Am Sat, 20 Jul 2024 12:35:31 +0000 schrieb WM in sci.math:
    It is not guaranteed that n+1 exists for every n.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From joes@21:1/5 to All on Tue Nov 19 12:11:02 2024
    Am Mon, 18 Nov 2024 19:20:24 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 18.11.2024 18:15, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM brought next idea :

    |ℕ| - |ℕ| = 0 because if you subtract one element from ℕ then you >>>> have no longer ℕ and therefore no longer |ℕ| describing it.

    If you remove one element from ℕ, then you have still ℵo but no longer all elements of ℕ.
    Yes, you have a subset of the same cardinality.

    If |ℕ| describes the number of elements, then it has
    changed to |ℕ| - 1.
    |N| - 1 = Aleph_0 - 1 = Aleph_0

    --
    Am Sat, 20 Jul 2024 12:35:31 +0000 schrieb WM in sci.math:
    It is not guaranteed that n+1 exists for every n.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to FromTheRafters on Tue Nov 19 15:46:25 2024
    On 18.11.2024 23:34, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM used his keyboard to write :

    N is the set, and |N| is the size of the set.

    If ℕ is an invariable set, then it has an invariable number of elements.
    The "size" ℵo cannot express this.

    aleph_zero *IS* the cardinality of N.

    Of course, but it is also the cardinality of all other countable sets
    which have more or fewer elements.

    No, only countably infinite sets. You have that all finite sets are
    countable too and have fewer elements.

    Only finite sets are countable. But all "countably" infinite sets have
    the same size, which according to the different numbers of elements is a
    very unsharp measure.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to joes on Tue Nov 19 16:31:19 2024
    On 19.11.2024 13:05, joes wrote:
    Am Mon, 18 Nov 2024 23:16:22 +0100 schrieb WM:

    |N\{0}| = |N| = Aleph_0
    And |N\{2}| = Aleph_0.

    Hence ℵo cannot describe the number of elements.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to joes on Tue Nov 19 16:33:59 2024
    On 19.11.2024 13:11, joes wrote:
    Am Mon, 18 Nov 2024 19:20:24 +0100 schrieb WM:

    If |ℕ| describes the number of elements, then it has
    changed to |ℕ| - 1.
    |N| - 1 = Aleph_0 - 1 = Aleph_0

    But the number of elements has decreased.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to FromTheRafters on Tue Nov 19 16:24:52 2024
    On 18.11.2024 23:40, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM wrote on 11/18/2024 :
    On 18.11.2024 22:58, FromTheRafters wrote:
    on 11/18/2024, WM supposed :
    On 18.11.2024 18:15, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM brought next idea :

    |ℕ| - |ℕ| = 0 because if you subtract one element from ℕ then you >>>>>>> have
    no longer ℕ and therefore no longer |ℕ| describing it.

    Still wrong.

    If you remove one element from ℕ, then you have still ℵo but no
    longer all elements of ℕ.

    But you do have now a proper subset of the naturals the same size as
    before.

    It has one element less, hence the "size" ℵo is a very unsharp measure.

    Comparing the size of sets by bijection. Bijection of finite sets give
    you a same number of elements, bijection of infinite sets give you same
    size of set.

    Why? Because only potential infinity is involved. True bijections pr5ove equinumerosity.
    If |ℕ| describes the number of elements, then it has changed to |ℕ| >>>> - 1.

    Minus one is not defined.

    Subtracting an element is defined. |ℕ| - 1 is defined as the number of
    elements minus 1.

    Nope!

    The number of ℕ \ {1} is 1 less than ℕ.

    If you don't like |ℕ| then call this number the number of natural
    numbers.

    Why would I do that when it is the *SIZE* of the smallest infinite set.

    The set of prime numbers is smaller.

    No, it is not.

    It is, because 4 and 8 are missing.

    There is a bijection.

    Only between numbers which have more successors than predecessors,
    although it is claimed that no successors are remaining.

    Regards, WM

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From joes@21:1/5 to All on Tue Nov 19 16:27:52 2024
    Am Tue, 19 Nov 2024 16:24:52 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 18.11.2024 23:40, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM wrote on 11/18/2024 :
    On 18.11.2024 22:58, FromTheRafters wrote:
    on 11/18/2024, WM supposed :
    On 18.11.2024 18:15, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM brought next idea :

    |ℕ| - |ℕ| = 0 because if you subtract one element from ℕ then you
    have no longer ℕ and therefore no longer |ℕ| describing it.
    If you remove one element from ℕ, then you have still ℵo but no
    longer all elements of ℕ.
    But you do have now a proper subset of the naturals the same size as
    before.
    It has one element less, hence the "size" ℵo is a very unsharp
    measure.
    Comparing the size of sets by bijection. Bijection of finite sets give
    you a same number of elements, bijection of infinite sets give you same
    size of set.
    Why? Because only potential infinity is involved. True bijections pr5ove equinumerosity.

    What is a "true" bijection?

    If |ℕ| describes the number of elements, then it has changed to |ℕ| >>>>> - 1.
    Minus one is not defined.
    Subtracting an element is defined. |ℕ| - 1 is defined as the number of >>> elements minus 1.
    Nope!
    The number of ℕ \ {1} is 1 less than ℕ.
    And what, pray tell, is Aleph_0 - 1 ?

    If you don't like |ℕ| then call this number the number of natural
    numbers.
    Why would I do that when it is the *SIZE* of the smallest infinite
    set.
    The set of prime numbers is smaller.
    No, it is not.
    It is, because 4 and 8 are missing.
    It is a subset.

    There is a bijection.
    Only between numbers which have more successors than predecessors,
    All of them do.

    although it is claimed that no successors are remaining.
    --
    Am Sat, 20 Jul 2024 12:35:31 +0000 schrieb WM in sci.math:
    It is not guaranteed that n+1 exists for every n.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to joes on Wed Nov 20 12:57:22 2024
    On 19.11.2024 17:27, joes wrote:
    Am Tue, 19 Nov 2024 16:24:52 +0100 schrieb WM:

    Why? Because only potential infinity is involved. True bijections prove
    equinumerosity.

    What is a "true" bijection?

    A true bijection between two sets proves that both sets have the same
    number of elements.

    The number of ℕ \ {1} is 1 less than ℕ.
    And what, pray tell, is Aleph_0 - 1 ?

    It is "infinitely many" like Aleph_0.

    > There is a bijection.
    Only between numbers which have more successors than predecessors,
    All of them do.

    Then the numbers of elements would be identical.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to FromTheRafters on Wed Nov 20 13:04:04 2024
    On 19.11.2024 17:42, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM submitted this idea :

    There is a bijection.

    Only between numbers which have more successors than predecessors,
    although it is claimed that no successors are remaining.

    You are not making any sense.

    It is set theory which is not making sense.
    Try to count to a natural number that has fewer successors than
    predecessors. Impossible. But set theory claims that all natural numbers
    can be counted to such that no successors remain.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to FromTheRafters on Wed Nov 20 13:01:29 2024
    On 19.11.2024 17:40, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM was thinking very hard :

    Only finite sets are countable.

    Wrong, it is countable if there is a bijection.

    They are erroneously called countable, but they are not countable.

    But all "countably" infinite sets have the same size, which according
    to the different numbers of elements is a very unsharp measure.

    That you don't like cardinal arithmetic, doesn't make cardinal
    arithmetic wrong.

    It does not make it wrong, but it unmasks it at imprecise. That's why I
    don't like it. We can do better.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to FromTheRafters on Wed Nov 20 17:51:19 2024
    On 20.11.2024 15:15, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM explained on 11/20/2024 :
    set theory claims that all natural
    numbers can be counted to such that no successors remain.

    No it doesn't.

    Even all rationals and algebraics.

    "we get the epitome (ω) of all real algebraic numbers [...] and with
    respect to this order we can talk about the nth algebraic number where
    not a single one of this epitome has been forgotten"
    "The infinite sequence thus defined has the peculiar property to contain
    the positive rational numbers completely, and each of them only once at
    a determined place"

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to FromTheRafters on Wed Nov 20 18:01:41 2024
    On 20.11.2024 15:14, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM formulated on Wednesday :


    It does not make it wrong, but it unmasks it at imprecise. That's why
    I don't like it. We can do better.

    It works well enough.

    Really? Then you can answer the following questions:

    Let every unit interval after a natural number on the real axis be
    coloured white with exception of the powers of 2 which are coloured
    black. Is it possible to shift the black intervals so that the whole
    real axis becomes black?

    Or: Let every unit interval after a natural number on the real axis be
    coloured as above with exception of the intervals after the odd prime
    numbers which are coloured red. Is it possible to shift the red
    intervals so that the whole real axis becomes red?

    What colour has the real axis after you have solved both tasks?

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From joes@21:1/5 to All on Wed Nov 20 18:12:41 2024
    Am Wed, 20 Nov 2024 17:51:19 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 20.11.2024 15:15, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM explained on 11/20/2024 :
    set theory claims that all natural numbers can be counted to such that
    no successors remain.

    No it doesn't.

    Even all rationals and algebraics.
    "we get the epitome (ω) of all real algebraic numbers [...] and with
    respect to this order we can talk about the nth algebraic number where
    not a single one of this epitome has been forgotten"
    "The infinite sequence thus defined has the peculiar property to contain
    the positive rational numbers completely, and each of them only once at
    a determined place"

    You are once again lacking in precision: every natural is finite and thus countable. The number of all of them together, the cardinality of the set, however is infinite (yet still countable), is not contained in N (not a
    member of the naturals).

    --
    Am Sat, 20 Jul 2024 12:35:31 +0000 schrieb WM in sci.math:
    It is not guaranteed that n+1 exists for every n.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From joes@21:1/5 to All on Wed Nov 20 18:20:44 2024
    Am Wed, 20 Nov 2024 12:57:22 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 19.11.2024 17:27, joes wrote:
    Am Tue, 19 Nov 2024 16:24:52 +0100 schrieb WM:

    Why? Because only potential infinity is involved. True bijections
    prove equinumerosity.
    What is a "true" bijection?
    A true bijection between two sets proves that both sets have the same
    number of elements.
    And a "false" one?

    The number of ℕ \ {1} is 1 less than ℕ.
    And what, pray tell, is Aleph_0 - 1 ?
    It is "infinitely many" like Aleph_0.
    Great.

    > There is a bijection.
    Only between numbers which have more successors than predecessors,
    All of them do.
    Then the numbers of elements would be identical.
    Exactly, even though I lost track of which two sets.

    --
    Am Sat, 20 Jul 2024 12:35:31 +0000 schrieb WM in sci.math:
    It is not guaranteed that n+1 exists for every n.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From joes@21:1/5 to All on Wed Nov 20 18:18:08 2024
    Am Wed, 20 Nov 2024 13:04:04 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 19.11.2024 17:42, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM submitted this idea :

    There is a bijection.
    Only between numbers which have more successors than predecessors,
    although it is claimed that no successors are remaining.
    You are not making any sense.
    It is not claimed.

    Try to count to a natural number that has fewer successors than
    predecessors. Impossible.
    Because there are no such numbers.

    But set theory claims that all natural numbers
    can be counted to such that no successors remain.
    Fuck no. Get your quantifiers in order: every single natural number
    is very clearly finite; the cardinal number corresponding
    to the set of all of them is countably infinite.

    --
    Am Sat, 20 Jul 2024 12:35:31 +0000 schrieb WM in sci.math:
    It is not guaranteed that n+1 exists for every n.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to joes on Wed Nov 20 19:37:20 2024
    On 20.11.2024 19:12, joes wrote:
    Am Wed, 20 Nov 2024 17:51:19 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 20.11.2024 15:15, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM explained on 11/20/2024 :
    set theory claims that all natural numbers can be counted to such that >>>> no successors remain.

    No it doesn't.

    Even all rationals and algebraics.
    "we get the epitome (ω) of all real algebraic numbers [...] and with
    respect to this order we can talk about the nth algebraic number where
    not a single one of this epitome has been forgotten"
    "The infinite sequence thus defined has the peculiar property to contain
    the positive rational numbers completely, and each of them only once at
    a determined place"

    You are once again lacking in precision:

    It was Cantor who said the above. There is no lack of precision.

    every natural is finite and thus
    countable.

    According to Cantor there is no number missing, let alone infinitely
    many. Set theory claims that all natural numbers can be counted to such
    that no successors remain. That is false.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to joes on Wed Nov 20 19:42:41 2024
    On 20.11.2024 19:18, joes wrote:
    Am Wed, 20 Nov 2024 13:04:04 +0100 schrieb WM:

    Try to count to a natural number that has fewer successors than
    predecessors. Impossible.
    Because there are no such numbers.

    All successors are natural numbers. If all can be counted, then no
    successors remain.

    But set theory claims that all natural numbers
    can be counted to such that no successors remain.
    et your quantifiers in order:

    That is a foolish excuse.

    every single natural number
    is very clearly finite;

    Every number that can be counted to is finite. But every number that can
    be counted to has more successors than predecessors. Therefore not every
    number can be counted to.

    the cardinal number corresponding
    to the set of all of them is countably infinite.

    The set of all numbers that can be counted to is finite, namely a
    number that is counted to. This cannot change by counting.

    Regards, WM





    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to joes on Wed Nov 20 19:44:39 2024
    On 20.11.2024 19:20, joes wrote:
    Am Wed, 20 Nov 2024 12:57:22 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 19.11.2024 17:27, joes wrote:
    Am Tue, 19 Nov 2024 16:24:52 +0100 schrieb WM:

    Why? Because only potential infinity is involved. True bijections
    prove equinumerosity.
    What is a "true" bijection?
    A true bijection between two sets proves that both sets have the same
    number of elements.
    And a "false" one?

    Does allow for very different numbers like prime numbers and algebraic
    numbers.

    The number of ℕ \ {1} is 1 less than ℕ.
    And what, pray tell, is Aleph_0 - 1 ?
    It is "infinitely many" like Aleph_0.
    Great.

    Infinitely great.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to FromTheRafters on Wed Nov 20 22:22:22 2024
    On 20.11.2024 21:08, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM was thinking very hard :
    On 20.11.2024 15:15, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM explained on 11/20/2024 :
    set theory claims that all natural numbers can be counted to such
    that no successors remain.

    No it doesn't.

    Even all rationals and algebraics.

    "we get the epitome (ω) of all real algebraic numbers [...] and with
    respect to this order we can talk about the nth algebraic number where
    not a single one of this epitome has been forgotten"
    "The infinite sequence thus defined has the peculiar property to
    contain the positive rational numbers completely, and each of them
    only once at a determined place"

    Which doesn't support your claim at all. No mention whatsoever of no successors remaining.

    "not a single one of this epitome has been forgotten" means not a single
    one remaining, let alone more than one.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Ross Finlayson on Wed Nov 20 22:30:59 2024
    On 20.11.2024 21:10, Ross Finlayson wrote:
    On 11/20/2024 12:05 PM, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM wrote on 11/20/2024 :

    What colour has the real axis after you have solved both tasks?

    Depending on the order of the tasks. I think half red or half black.

    Well you have to reference academic reference and describe "supertask"

    Only if Cantor's eneumerating are supertasks.

    besides "asymptotics" about where "the asymptotic density of black or
    red respectively is 1 in the limit",

    No it is 0 in the limit. The relative density f(n) in the interval (0,
    n] decreases below every positive eps. That proves the limit 0.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to FromTheRafters on Wed Nov 20 22:18:57 2024
    On 20.11.2024 21:05, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM wrote on 11/20/2024 :
    On 20.11.2024 15:14, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM formulated on Wednesday :


    It does not make it wrong, but it unmasks it at imprecise. That's
    why I don't like it. We can do better.

    It works well enough.

    Really? Then you can answer the following questions:

    Let every unit interval after a natural number on the real axis be
    coloured white with exception of the powers of 2 which are coloured
    black. Is it possible to shift the black intervals so that the whole
    real axis becomes black?

    No, of course not.

    Thank you. You are the first person not bewitched by set theory.

    Or: Let every unit interval after a natural number on the real axis be
    coloured as above with exception of the intervals after the odd prime
    numbers which are coloured red. Is it possible to shift the red
    intervals so that the whole real axis becomes red?

    No, of course not.

    What colour has the real axis after you have solved both tasks?

    Depending on the order of the tasks. I think half red or half black.

    Recidivistic?

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From joes@21:1/5 to All on Wed Nov 20 23:57:15 2024
    Am Wed, 20 Nov 2024 19:37:20 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 20.11.2024 19:12, joes wrote:
    Am Wed, 20 Nov 2024 17:51:19 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 20.11.2024 15:15, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM explained on 11/20/2024 :
    set theory claims that all natural numbers can be counted to such
    that no successors remain.
    No it doesn't.
    Even all rationals and algebraics.
    "we get the epitome (ω) of all real algebraic numbers [...] and with
    respect to this order we can talk about the nth algebraic number where
    not a single one of this epitome has been forgotten"
    "The infinite sequence thus defined has the peculiar property to
    contain the positive rational numbers completely, and each of them
    only once at a determined place"
    You are once again lacking in precision:
    It was Cantor who said the above. There is no lack of precision.
    You misunderstood him. I don't see anything about successors.

    every natural is finite and thus countable.
    According to Cantor there is no number missing, let alone infinitely
    many.
    Numbers "missing" is meaningless. What did you mean to say here?

    Set theory claims that all natural numbers can be counted to such
    that no successors remain. That is false.
    Obviously. There is no end to the successors such that you are done
    counting them after some finite number.

    --
    Am Sat, 20 Jul 2024 12:35:31 +0000 schrieb WM in sci.math:
    It is not guaranteed that n+1 exists for every n.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From joes@21:1/5 to All on Thu Nov 21 00:08:24 2024
    Am Wed, 20 Nov 2024 19:42:41 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 20.11.2024 19:18, joes wrote:
    Am Wed, 20 Nov 2024 13:04:04 +0100 schrieb WM:

    Try to count to a natural number that has fewer successors than
    predecessors. Impossible.
    Because there are no such numbers.
    All successors are natural numbers.
    So?

    If all can be counted, then no successors remain.
    All at once or every single one?
    There are no successors "after" all of the other numbers.

    But set theory claims that all natural numbers can be counted to such
    that no successors remain.
    et your quantifiers in order:
    That is a foolish excuse.
    You have shown that you don't understand them.

    every single natural number is very clearly finite;
    Every number that can be counted to is finite.
    There are countably infinite numbers, but ok.

    But every number that can
    be counted to has more successors than predecessors.
    Every number, period. There is no number without successors.

    Therefore not every number can be counted to.
    Well, the ordinal numbers less than epsilon_0 are called countably
    infinite.

    the cardinal number corresponding to the set of all of them is
    countably infinite.
    The set of all numbers that can be counted to is finite, namely a
    number that is counted to. This cannot change by counting.
    WTF there is no largest number. How do you think counting changes
    anything?

    --
    Am Sat, 20 Jul 2024 12:35:31 +0000 schrieb WM in sci.math:
    It is not guaranteed that n+1 exists for every n.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Thu Nov 21 01:38:34 2024
    According to Cantor there is no number missing, let alone infinitely
    many. [WM]

    Mückenheim, Du hast wirklich einen schweren DACHSCHADEN. Kannst Du eine
    Stelle aus Cantors Oevre zitieren, wo er sagt, that "there is no number missing"?

    Mensch, geh doch mal endlich zum Psychiater!

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Thu Nov 21 01:24:27 2024
    On 11/20/2024 3:57 PM, joes wrote:
    Am Wed, 20 Nov 2024 19:37:20 +0100 schrieb WM:

    According to Cantor there is no number missing, let alone infinitely
    many.

    *sigh*

    Numbers "missing" is meaningless. [...]

    Nuff said.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Thu Nov 21 01:20:08 2024
    Am 21.11.2024 um 01:12 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:
    On 11/20/2024 4:11 PM, Chris M. Thomasson wrote:
    On 11/20/2024 4:10 PM, Chris M. Thomasson wrote:
    On 11/20/2024 3:57 PM, joes wrote:
    Am Wed, 20 Nov 2024 19:37:20 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 20.11.2024 19:12, joes wrote:
    Am Wed, 20 Nov 2024 17:51:19 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 20.11.2024 15:15, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM explained on 11/20/2024 :
    set theory claims that all natural numbers can be counted to such >>>>>>>>> that no successors remain.
    No it doesn't.
    Even all rationals and algebraics.
    "we get the epitome (ω) of all real algebraic numbers [...] and with >>>>>>> respect to this order we can talk about the nth algebraic number >>>>>>> where
    not a single one of this epitome has been forgotten"
    "The infinite sequence thus defined has the peculiar property to >>>>>>> contain the positive rational numbers completely, and each of them >>>>>>> only once at a determined place"
    You are once again lacking in precision:
    It was Cantor who said the above. There is no lack of precision.
    You misunderstood him. I don't see anything about successors.

    every natural is finite and thus countable.
    According to Cantor there is no number missing, let alone infinitely >>>>> many.
    Numbers "missing" is meaningless. What did you mean to say here?

    Set theory claims that all natural numbers can be counted to such
    that no successors remain. That is false.
    Obviously. There is no end to the successors such that you are done
    counting them after some finite number.


    A balanced scale with no weights on either side. Place a unit weight
    on the right side and say this equal to 0 + 1. Wrt unit weight...

    ? ;^) lol.

    say balanced condition is zero. So, with the single unit weight on the
    right, place a unit weight on the left. We got a balanced scale
    representing 1 - 1 - 0?

    1-1=0 DAMN
    TYPOS! GRRRR! Sorry Everybody! ;^o

    lol

    Keep cool, man.

    Hey, we are cool, buddy! :-)

    .
    .
    .

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to FromTheRafters on Thu Nov 21 12:45:17 2024
    On 21.11.2024 00:04, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM explained on 11/20/2024 :

    "not a single one of this epitome has been forgotten" means not a
    single one remaining, let alone more than one.

    No it doesn't, it means the system used to list them is inherently
    unable to miss any.

    None is missed. That is no successors remain missed.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to joes on Thu Nov 21 12:50:19 2024
    On 21.11.2024 01:08, joes wrote:
    Am Wed, 20 Nov 2024 19:42:41 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 20.11.2024 19:18, joes wrote:
    Am Wed, 20 Nov 2024 13:04:04 +0100 schrieb WM:

    Try to count to a natural number that has fewer successors than
    predecessors. Impossible.
    Because there are no such numbers.
    All successors are natural numbers.
    So?

    If all can be counted, then no successors remain.
    All at once or every single one?

    Counting concerns every single number.
    But every number that can
    be counted to has more successors than predecessors.
    Every number, period. There is no number without successors.

    Then not all can be counted.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to FromTheRafters on Thu Nov 21 12:41:55 2024
    On 21.11.2024 00:01, FromTheRafters wrote:
    After serious thinking WM wrote :
    On 20.11.2024 21:05, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM wrote on 11/20/2024 :
    On 20.11.2024 15:14, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM formulated on Wednesday :


    It does not make it wrong, but it unmasks it at imprecise. That's
    why I don't like it. We can do better.

    It works well enough.

    Really? Then you can answer the following questions:

    Let every unit interval after a natural number on the real axis be
    coloured white with exception of the powers of 2 which are coloured
    black. Is it possible to shift the black intervals so that the whole
    real axis becomes black?

    No, of course not.

    Thank you. You are the first person not bewitched by set theory.

    The real line is infinitely long in both directions. Your shifted
    intervals are all on the positive real axis.

    But if Cantor was right, all integers, positive as well as all other
    could be in bijection with the powers of 2.

    Depending on the order of the tasks. I think half red or half black.

    Recidivistic?

    I recognize McDuck in disguise, or your notion that there are fewer
    primes than there are natural numbers. You keep finding different ways
    to say the same wrong thing.

    The analytical limit is wrong in your opinion?

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Moebius on Thu Nov 21 12:57:08 2024
    On 21.11.2024 01:38, Moebius wrote:

    According to Cantor there is no number missing, let alone infinitely
    many. [WM]

    Kannst Du eine
    Stelle aus Cantors Oevre zitieren, wo er sagt, that "there is no number missing"?

    "wobei keine einzige aus dem Inbegriffe (ω) vergessen ist."

    Gruß, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to FromTheRafters on Thu Nov 21 18:01:36 2024
    On 21.11.2024 14:10, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM formulated the question :
    On 21.11.2024 00:04, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM explained on 11/20/2024 :

    "not a single one of this epitome has been forgotten" means not a
    single one remaining, let alone more than one.

    No it doesn't, it means the system used to list them is inherently
    unable to miss any.

    None is missed. That is no successors remain missed.

    It says nothing about successors at all, just that there is a systematic method for listing them without missing any.

    And that is wrong because for every listed natural number almost all are
    not listed.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to FromTheRafters on Thu Nov 21 17:55:25 2024
    On 21.11.2024 14:05, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM wrote :

    Let every unit interval after a natural number on the real axis be >>>>>> coloured white with exception of the powers of 2 which are
    coloured black. Is it possible to shift the black intervals so
    that the whole real axis becomes black?

    The analytical limit is wrong in your opinion?

    Which limit?

    The limit of the sequence f(n) of relative coverings in the interval (0,
    n] is 0, not 1.

    Which limit?

    That is where Cantor's bijections are believed to be complete.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From joes@21:1/5 to All on Thu Nov 21 21:01:38 2024
    Am Thu, 21 Nov 2024 18:01:36 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 21.11.2024 14:10, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM formulated the question :
    On 21.11.2024 00:04, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM explained on 11/20/2024 :

    "not a single one of this epitome has been forgotten" means not a
    single one remaining, let alone more than one.
    No it doesn't, it means the system used to list them is inherently
    unable to miss any.
    None is missed. That is no successors remain missed.
    What successors are you talking about?
    It says nothing about successors at all, just that there is a
    systematic method for listing them without missing any.
    And that is wrong because for every listed natural number almost all are
    not listed.
    You are mistaken. The successors are also all listed - we are talking
    about all naturals here.

    --
    Am Sat, 20 Jul 2024 12:35:31 +0000 schrieb WM in sci.math:
    It is not guaranteed that n+1 exists for every n.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From joes@21:1/5 to All on Thu Nov 21 20:59:35 2024
    Am Thu, 21 Nov 2024 17:55:25 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 21.11.2024 14:05, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM wrote :

    Let every unit interval after a natural number on the real axis be >>>>>>> coloured white with exception of the powers of 2 which are
    coloured black. Is it possible to shift the black intervals so
    that the whole real axis becomes black?

    The analytical limit is wrong in your opinion?
    Which limit?
    The limit of the sequence f(n) of relative coverings in the interval (0,
    n] is 0, not 1.
    Yes, of the infinite real axis none are black.

    Which limit?
    That is where Cantor's bijections are believed to be complete.
    I mean, bijections are also complete for every finite subset.

    --
    Am Sat, 20 Jul 2024 12:35:31 +0000 schrieb WM in sci.math:
    It is not guaranteed that n+1 exists for every n.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From joes@21:1/5 to All on Thu Nov 21 21:05:12 2024
    Am Thu, 21 Nov 2024 12:50:19 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 21.11.2024 01:08, joes wrote:
    Am Wed, 20 Nov 2024 19:42:41 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 20.11.2024 19:18, joes wrote:
    Am Wed, 20 Nov 2024 13:04:04 +0100 schrieb WM:

    Try to count to a natural number that has fewer successors than
    predecessors. Impossible.
    Because there are no such numbers.
    All successors are natural numbers.
    So?

    If all can be counted, then no successors remain.
    All at once or every single one?
    Counting concerns every single number.
    Every single natural can be counted to.

    But every number that can be counted to has more successors than
    predecessors.
    Every number, period. There is no number without successors.
    Then not all can be counted.
    Not finitely.

    --
    Am Sat, 20 Jul 2024 12:35:31 +0000 schrieb WM in sci.math:
    It is not guaranteed that n+1 exists for every n.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to joes on Thu Nov 21 22:40:12 2024
    On 21.11.2024 21:59, joes wrote:
    Am Thu, 21 Nov 2024 17:55:25 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 21.11.2024 14:05, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM wrote :

    Let every unit interval after a natural number on the real axis be >>>>>>>> coloured white with exception of the powers of 2 which are
    coloured black. Is it possible to shift the black intervals so >>>>>>>> that the whole real axis becomes black?

    The analytical limit is wrong in your opinion?
    Which limit?
    The limit of the sequence f(n) of relative coverings in the interval (0,
    n] is 0, not 1.
    Yes, of the infinite real axis none are black.

    Not none but less than any definable eps.

    Which limit?
    That is where Cantor's bijections are believed to be complete.
    I mean, bijections are also complete for every finite subset.

    No, for any finite subset (0, n] there is no complete bijection. Too few
    black unit intervals available to cover (0, n].

    Regards, WM


    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to joes on Thu Nov 21 22:45:52 2024
    On 21.11.2024 22:05, joes wrote:
    Am Thu, 21 Nov 2024 12:50:19 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 21.11.2024 01:08, joes wrote:
    Am Wed, 20 Nov 2024 19:42:41 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 20.11.2024 19:18, joes wrote:
    Am Wed, 20 Nov 2024 13:04:04 +0100 schrieb WM:

    Try to count to a natural number that has fewer successors than
    predecessors. Impossible.
    Because there are no such numbers.
    All successors are natural numbers.
    So?

    If all can be counted, then no successors remain.
    All at once or every single one?
    Counting concerns every single number.
    Every single natural can be counted to.

    Nonsense.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From joes@21:1/5 to All on Thu Nov 21 22:45:28 2024
    Am Wed, 20 Nov 2024 19:44:39 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 20.11.2024 19:20, joes wrote:
    Am Wed, 20 Nov 2024 12:57:22 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 19.11.2024 17:27, joes wrote:
    Am Tue, 19 Nov 2024 16:24:52 +0100 schrieb WM:

    Why? Because only potential infinity is involved. True bijections
    prove equinumerosity.
    What is a "true" bijection?
    A true bijection between two sets proves that both sets have the same
    number of elements.
    Determined by the sets differing only in a finite number of elements?

    And a "false" one?
    Does allow for very different numbers like prime numbers and algebraic numbers.
    The number of ℕ \ {1} is 1 less than ℕ.
    And what, pray tell, is Aleph_0 - 1 ?
    It is "infinitely many" like Aleph_0.
    Great.
    Infinitely great.
    Thanks for agreeing with |N| = |N\{0}|.

    --
    Am Sat, 20 Jul 2024 12:35:31 +0000 schrieb WM in sci.math:
    It is not guaranteed that n+1 exists for every n.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Fri Nov 22 08:49:05 2024
    Am 22.11.2024 um 03:58 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:
    On 11/21/2024 1:45 PM, WM wrote:
    On 21.11.2024 22:05, joes wrote:
    Am Thu, 21 Nov 2024 12:50:19 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 21.11.2024 01:08, joes wrote:
    Am Wed, 20 Nov 2024 19:42:41 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 20.11.2024 19:18, joes wrote:
    Am Wed, 20 Nov 2024 13:04:04 +0100 schrieb WM:

    Try to count to a natural number that has fewer successors than >>>>>>>> predecessors. Impossible.
    Because there are no such numbers.
    All successors are natural numbers.
    So?

    Mückenheim labert wieder einmal saudummen Scheißdreck daher.

    If all can be counted, then no successors remain.

    <facepalm>

    All at once or every single one?
    Counting concerns every single number.
    Every single natural can be counted to.

    Nonsense.

    Ach, Mückemheim, halt doch mal die Fresse!

    Proof by induction:

    1 can be counted to (obviously). If n (where n is a natural number) can
    be counted to, then n+1 can be counted to (obviously). Hence for each
    and every natural numbers n: n can be counted too. qed

    Du bist einfach für jede Form von Mathematik zu doof und zu blöde, Mückenheim.

    What one cannot be counted to?

    I guess any one of the dark numbers in his asshole will do.

    .
    .
    .

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to joes on Fri Nov 22 13:00:52 2024
    On 21.11.2024 23:45, joes wrote:
    Am Wed, 20 Nov 2024 19:44:39 +0100 schrieb WM:

    Why? Because only potential infinity is involved. True bijections
    prove equinumerosity.
    What is a "true" bijection?
    A true bijection between two sets proves that both sets have the same
    number of elements.
    Determined by the sets differing only in a finite number of elements?

    Not differing at all.

    And a "false" one?
    Does allow for very different numbers like prime numbers and algebraic
    numbers.
    The number of ℕ \ {1} is 1 less than ℕ.
    And what, pray tell, is Aleph_0 - 1 ?
    It is "infinitely many" like Aleph_0.
    Great.
    Infinitely great.
    Thanks for agreeing with |N| = |N\{0}|.

    Of course. ℵo means nothing but infinitely many.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Chris M. Thomasson on Fri Nov 22 12:45:16 2024
    On 22.11.2024 03:58, Chris M. Thomasson wrote:
    On 11/21/2024 1:45 PM, WM wrote:

    Counting concerns every single number.
    Every single natural can be counted to.

    Nonsense.

    What one cannot be counted to?

    For instance, the indices of the finite endsegments.
    Remember: The intersection of all endsegments is empty, but the
    intersection of endsegments which can be counted to is infinite.
    Note that every endsegment loses only one number.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Moebius on Fri Nov 22 13:08:28 2024
    On 22.11.2024 08:49, Moebius wrote:
    Am 22.11.2024 um 03:58 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:
    On 11/21/2024 1:45 PM, WM wrote:
    On 21.11.2024 22:05, joes wrote:

    Counting concerns every single number.
    Every single natural can be counted to.

    Nonsense.

    Proof by induction:

    Induction proves that every initial segment of endsegments has an
    infinite intersection.

    1 can be counted to (obviously). If n (where n is a natural number) can
    be counted to, then n+1 can be counted to (obviously). Hence for each
    and every natural numbers n: n can be counted too. qed

    But not all endsegments have an infinite intersection. All endsegments
    have an empty intersection. Since every endsegment can lose only one
    number, there must be infinitely many endsegments involved in reducing
    the intersection from infinite to empty. Their indices however cannot be counted to.

    What one cannot be counted to?

    Just the indices involved in reducing the intersection from infinite to
    empty. They are dark.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From joes@21:1/5 to All on Fri Nov 22 12:28:06 2024
    Am Thu, 21 Nov 2024 22:40:12 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 21.11.2024 21:59, joes wrote:
    Am Thu, 21 Nov 2024 17:55:25 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 21.11.2024 14:05, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM wrote :

    Let every unit interval after a natural number on the real axis >>>>>>>>> be coloured white with exception of the powers of 2 which are >>>>>>>>> coloured black. Is it possible to shift the black intervals so >>>>>>>>> that the whole real axis becomes black?
    The analytical limit is wrong in your opinion?
    Which limit?
    The limit of the sequence f(n) of relative coverings in the interval
    (0, n] is 0, not 1.
    Yes, of the infinite real axis none are black.
    Not none but less than any definable eps.
    Less than every positive number = zero. Also I was pulling your leg.

    Which limit?
    That is where Cantor's bijections are believed to be complete.
    I mean, bijections are also complete for every finite subset.
    No, for any finite subset (0, n] there is no complete bijection. Too few black unit intervals available to cover (0, n].
    Haha what I was talking about a function like
    {(0, 1), (1, 0), (n, n)} for all n>1.

    There IS a bijection between {0, 1, ..., n} and {2^k for all k<n}
    for all n e N.

    --
    Am Sat, 20 Jul 2024 12:35:31 +0000 schrieb WM in sci.math:
    It is not guaranteed that n+1 exists for every n.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From joes@21:1/5 to All on Fri Nov 22 12:32:19 2024
    Am Fri, 22 Nov 2024 13:00:52 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 21.11.2024 23:45, joes wrote:
    Am Wed, 20 Nov 2024 19:44:39 +0100 schrieb WM:

    Why? Because only potential infinity is involved. True bijections >>>>>>> prove equinumerosity.
    What is a "true" bijection?
    A true bijection between two sets proves that both sets have the
    same number of elements.
    Determined by the sets differing only in a finite number of elements?
    Not differing at all.
    Ah yes, the sets {-1} u N and {-2} u N have different sizes.

    The number of ℕ \ {1} is 1 less than ℕ.
    And what, pray tell, is Aleph_0 - 1 ?
    It is "infinitely many" like Aleph_0.
    Thanks for agreeing with |N| = |N\{0}|.
    Of course. ℵo means nothing but infinitely many.
    Good. Then we can consider those sets to have the same number.

    --
    Am Sat, 20 Jul 2024 12:35:31 +0000 schrieb WM in sci.math:
    It is not guaranteed that n+1 exists for every n.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From joes@21:1/5 to All on Fri Nov 22 12:39:17 2024
    Am Fri, 22 Nov 2024 13:08:28 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 22.11.2024 08:49, Moebius wrote:
    Am 22.11.2024 um 03:58 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:
    On 11/21/2024 1:45 PM, WM wrote:
    On 21.11.2024 22:05, joes wrote:

    Counting concerns every single number.
    Every single natural can be counted to.
    Nonsense.
    Proof by induction:
    Induction proves that every initial segment of endsegments has an
    infinite intersection.
    True. But not the intersection of all of them, since that is the (ugh)
    infinite initial segment, and "infinite" itself is not a natural number
    covered by induction - only all the naturals themselves.

    1 can be counted to (obviously). If n (where n is a natural number) can
    be counted to, then n+1 can be counted to (obviously). Hence for each
    and every natural numbers n: n can be counted too. qed
    But not all endsegments have an infinite intersection.
    Yes they do (with what?).

    All endsegments have an empty intersection.
    No, all segments have an infinite intersection with each other,
    namely the one that comes "later", with a larger index.

    Since every endsegment can lose only one
    number, there must be infinitely many endsegments involved in reducing
    the intersection from infinite to empty.
    Exactly. That is all of them, there are infinitely segments.

    What one cannot be counted to?
    Just the indices involved in reducing the intersection from infinite to empty. They are dark.
    They don't exist. That is why they are disregarded.

    --
    Am Sat, 20 Jul 2024 12:35:31 +0000 schrieb WM in sci.math:
    It is not guaranteed that n+1 exists for every n.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to joes on Fri Nov 22 15:51:11 2024
    On 22.11.2024 13:32, joes wrote:
    Am Fri, 22 Nov 2024 13:00:52 +0100 schrieb WM:

    The number of ℕ \ {1} is 1 less than ℕ.
    And what, pray tell, is Aleph_0 - 1 ?
    It is "infinitely many" like Aleph_0.
    Thanks for agreeing with |N| = |N\{0}|.
    Of course. ℵo means nothing but infinitely many.
    Good. Then we can consider those sets to have the same number.

    That is the big mistake. It makes you think that the sets of naturals
    and of prime numbers could cover each other.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to joes on Fri Nov 22 15:48:55 2024
    On 22.11.2024 13:39, joes wrote:
    Am Fri, 22 Nov 2024 13:08:28 +0100 schrieb WM:

    All endsegments have an empty intersection.
    No, all segments have an infinite intersection with each other,
    namely the one that comes "later", with a larger index.

    The set of all endsegmente has an empty intersection.

    Since every endsegment can lose only one
    number, there must be infinitely many endsegments involved in reducing
    the intersection from infinite to empty.
    Exactly. That is all of them, there are infinitely segments.

    Up to every endsegemnet with visible index, the intersection is
    infinite: ∩{E(1), E(2), ..., E(k)} = E(k) with |E(k)| = ℵo.

    What one cannot be counted to?
    Just the indices involved in reducing the intersection from infinite to
    empty. They are dark.
    They don't exist.

    The decrease from ℵo to 0 can only be accomplished by ℵo endsegments
    each of which loses one number until all numbers are gone.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From joes@21:1/5 to All on Fri Nov 22 15:11:26 2024
    Am Fri, 22 Nov 2024 15:51:11 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 22.11.2024 13:32, joes wrote:
    Am Fri, 22 Nov 2024 13:00:52 +0100 schrieb WM:

    The number of ℕ \ {1} is 1 less than ℕ.
    And what, pray tell, is Aleph_0 - 1 ?
    It is "infinitely many" like Aleph_0.
    Thanks for agreeing with |N| = |N\{0}|.
    Of course. ℵo means nothing but infinitely many.
    Good. Then we can consider those sets to have the same number.
    That is the big mistake. It makes you think that the sets of naturals
    and of prime numbers could cover each other.
    As it should. You can give each prime an index.

    --
    Am Sat, 20 Jul 2024 12:35:31 +0000 schrieb WM in sci.math:
    It is not guaranteed that n+1 exists for every n.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to joes on Fri Nov 22 22:08:46 2024
    On 22.11.2024 16:11, joes wrote:
    Am Fri, 22 Nov 2024 15:51:11 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 22.11.2024 13:32, joes wrote:
    > Am Fri, 22 Nov 2024 13:00:52 +0100 schrieb WM:

    >>>>>>>> The number of ℕ \ {1} is 1 less than ℕ.
    >>>>>>> And what, pray tell, is Aleph_0 - 1 ?
    >>>>>> It is "infinitely many" like Aleph_0.
    >>> Thanks for agreeing with |N| = |N\{0}|.
    >> Of course. ℵo means nothing but infinitely many.
    > Good. Then we can consider those sets to have the same number.
    That is the big mistake. It makes you think that the sets of naturals
    and of prime numbers could cover each other.
    As it should. You can give each prime an index.

    But not every index a prime.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Fri Nov 22 16:50:16 2024
    On 11/22/2024 9:51 AM, WM wrote:
    On 22.11.2024 13:32, joes wrote:

    Then we can consider those sets
    to have the same number.

    That is the big mistake.
    It makes you think that
    the sets of naturals and of prime numbers
    could cover each other.

    ℙ is the set of prime numbers.
    ℙ(n) is the set of the first n prime numbers.
    max.ℙ(n) is the nᵗʰ prime number.

    For each n ∈ ℕ
    a set ℙ(n) of the first n prime numbers exists,
    and, since ℙ(n) is a finite set,
    max.ℙ(n) = pr(n) the nᵗʰ prime number exists.

    Therefore,
    n ↦ pr(n) ↦ n: one.to.one

    ℙ covers ℕ, and ℕ covers ℙ

    ℙ ≠⊂ ℕ
    ℙ and ℕ are infinite sets.

    ----
    For each n ∈ ℕ
    a set ℙ(n) of the first n prime numbers exists,

    ⎛ Assume otherwise.
    ⎜ Assume n′ ∈ ℕ and ℙ(n′) doesn't exist.v

    ⎜ The ℕ.subset of numbers i
    ⎜ such that ℙ(i) doesn't exist
    ⎜ is not empty, and
    ⎜ holds a first element 𝔊+1 such that
    ⎜ ℙ(𝔊+1) doesn't exist and
    ⎜ ℙ(𝔊) exists

    ⎜ max.ℙ(𝔊) = pr(𝔊) is the 𝔊ᵗʰ prime.

    ⎜ pr(𝔊)!+1 is not.divisible by each of ⟦2,pr(𝔊)⟧ᴺ

    ⎜ The ℕ.subset of numbers i
    ⎜ such that i is not.divisible by each of ⟦2,pr(𝔊)⟧ᴺ
    ⎜ is not empty and
    ⎜ holds a first element p such that
    ⎜ p is not.divisible by each of ⟦2,pr(𝔊)⟧ᴺ and
    ⎜ each of ⦅pr(𝔊),p⦆ᴺ is divisible by one of ⟦2,pr(𝔊)⟧ᴺ

    ⎜ None of ⦅pr(𝔊),p⦆ᴺ divides p or else
    ⎜ one of ⟦2,pr(𝔊)⟧ᴺ dividing one of ⦅pr(𝔊),p⦆ᴺ
    ⎜ would divide p, which it doesn't.

    ⎜ None of ⟦2,p⦆ᴺ divides p
    ⎜ p is a prime number.
    ⎜ p = pr(𝔊+1) next prime after pr(𝔊)
    ⎜ ℙ(𝔊+1) = ℙ(𝔊)∪{p} exists

    ⎜ However,
    ⎜ ℙ(𝔊+1) doesn't exist.
    ⎝ Contradiction.

    Therefore,
    for each n ∈ ℕ
    a set ℙ(n) of the first n prime numbers exists.

    And
    n ↦ pr(n) ↦ n: one.to.one

    ℙ covers ℕ, and ℕ covers ℙ

    ℙ ≠⊂ ℕ
    ℙ and ℕ are infinite sets.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Sat Nov 23 06:18:35 2024
    On 22.11.2024 16:11, joes wrote:
    Am Fri, 22 Nov 2024 15:51:11 +0100 schrieb WM:

    the sets of naturals and of prime numbers [can] cover each other.

    As it should. You can give each prime an index.

    Indeed! The two formulas

    | p(1) = min P
    | p(n+1) = min {p e P : p > p(n)} (for all n e IN)

    (recursively) define the function p: IN --> P. Where IN is the set of
    all natural numbers and P is the set of all prime numbers.

    Hint: p(1) = 2, p(2) = 3, p(3) = 5, ...

    Actually, if p e P, then there is an (index) n e IN such that p(n) = p.

    (It's easy to prove that p: IN --> P is a bijection.)

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Sat Nov 23 06:30:11 2024
    Am 23.11.2024 um 06:18 schrieb Moebius:
    On 22.11.2024 16:11, joes wrote:
    Am Fri, 22 Nov 2024 15:51:11 +0100 schrieb WM:

    the sets of naturals and of prime numbers [can] cover each other.

    As it should. You can give each prime an index.

    Indeed! The two formulas

    | p(1) = min P
    | p(n+1) = min {p e P : p > p(n)}   (for all n e IN)

    (recursively) define the function p: IN --> P. Where IN is the set of
    all natural numbers and P is the set of all prime numbers.

    Hint: p(1) = 2, p(2) = 3, p(3) = 5, ...

    Actually, if p e P, then there is an (index) n e IN such that p(n) = p.

    (It's easy to prove that p: IN --> P is a bijection.)

    p(n) is the n-th prime in the sequence of primes ordered by size.

    .
    .
    .

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Sat Nov 23 06:31:00 2024
    Am 23.11.2024 um 06:18 schrieb Moebius:
    On 22.11.2024 16:11, joes wrote:
    Am Fri, 22 Nov 2024 15:51:11 +0100 schrieb WM:

    the sets of naturals and of prime numbers [can] cover each other.

    As it should. You can give each prime an index.

    Indeed! The two formulas

    | p(1) = min P
    | p(n+1) = min {p e P : p > p(n)}   (for all n e IN)

    (recursively) define the function p: IN --> P. Where IN is the set of
    all natural numbers and P is the set of all prime numbers.

    Hint: p(1) = 2, p(2) = 3, p(3) = 5, ...

    Actually, if p e P, then there is an (index) n e IN such that p(n) = p.

    (It's easy to prove that p: IN --> P is a bijection.)

    p(n) is the n-th prime in the sequence of prime numbers ordered by size.

    .
    .
    .

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Sat Nov 23 06:32:09 2024
    Am 23.11.2024 um 06:18 schrieb Moebius:
    On 22.11.2024 16:11, joes wrote:
    Am Fri, 22 Nov 2024 15:51:11 +0100 schrieb WM:

    the sets of naturals and of prime numbers [can] cover each other.

    As it should. You can give each prime an index.

    Indeed! The two formulas

    | p(1) = min P
    | p(n+1) = min {p e P : p > p(n)}   (for all n e IN)

    (recursively) define the function p: IN --> P. Where IN is the set of
    all natural numbers and P is the set of all prime numbers.

    Hint: p(1) = 2, p(2) = 3, p(3) = 5, ...

    Actually, if p e P, then there is an (index) n e IN such that p(n) = p.

    (It's easy to prove that p: IN --> P is a bijection.)

    p(n) is the n-th prime number in the sequence of prime numbers ordered
    by size.

    .
    .
    .

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to FromTheRafters on Sat Nov 23 11:15:05 2024
    On 22.11.2024 22:49, FromTheRafters wrote:
    After serious thinking WM wrote :
    On 22.11.2024 16:11, joes wrote:
    Am Fri, 22 Nov 2024 15:51:11 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 22.11.2024 13:32, joes wrote:
      > Am Fri, 22 Nov 2024 13:00:52 +0100 schrieb WM:

      >>>>>>>> The number of ℕ \ {1} is 1 less than ℕ.
      >>>>>>> And what, pray tell, is Aleph_0 - 1 ?
      >>>>>> It is "infinitely many" like Aleph_0.
      >>> Thanks for agreeing with |N| = |N\{0}|.
      >> Of course. ℵo means nothing but infinitely many.
      > Good. Then we can consider those sets to have the same number.
    That is the big mistake. It makes you think that the sets of naturals
    and of prime numbers could cover each other.
    As it should. You can give each prime an index.

    But not every index a prime.

    Why not? It looks like a bijection to me.

    Up to every prime, yes. But not for all numbers.

    Let every unit interval after a natural number on the real axis be
    coloured white with exception of the intervals after the prime numbers
    which are coloured red. It is impossible to shift the red intervals so
    that the whole real axis becomes red. Every interval (10n, 10 (n+1)] is deficient - on the whole real axis.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Moebius on Sat Nov 23 11:27:30 2024
    On 23.11.2024 06:32, Moebius wrote:
    Am 23.11.2024 um 06:18 schrieb Moebius:
    On 22.11.2024 16:11, joes wrote:
    Am Fri, 22 Nov 2024 15:51:11 +0100 schrieb WM:

    the sets of naturals and of prime numbers [can] cover each other.

    As it should. You can give each prime an index.

    Indeed! The two formulas

    | p(1) = min P
    | p(n+1) = min {p e P : p > p(n)}   (for all n e IN)

    (recursively) define the function p: IN --> P. Where IN is the set of
    all natural numbers and P is the set of all prime numbers.

    Hint: p(1) = 2, p(2) = 3, p(3) = 5, ...

    Actually, if p e P, then there is an (index) n e IN such that p(n) = p.

    (It's easy to prove that p: IN --> P is a bijection.)

    p(n) is the n-th prime number in the sequence of prime numbers ordered
    by size.

    Up to every definable prime there is a bijection. But not for all naturals.

    Let every unit interval on the real axis be coloured white. Cover the
    unit intervals of prime numbers by red hats. It is impossible to shift
    the red hats so that all unit intervals of the whole real axis get red
    hats. There are too few prime numbers.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Sat Nov 23 11:30:32 2024
    On 22.11.2024 22:50, Jim Burns wrote:


    ℙ covers ℕ, and ℕ covers ℙ

    Let every unit interval on the infinite real axis be coloured white.
    Cover the unit intervals of prime numbers by red hats. It is impossible
    to shift the red hats so that all unit intervals of the whole real axis
    get red hats. There are too few prime numbers.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to FromTheRafters on Sat Nov 23 13:33:37 2024
    On 23.11.2024 13:20, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM laid this down on his screen :

    Let every unit interval after a natural number on the real axis be
    coloured white with exception of the intervals after the prime numbers
    which are coloured red. It is impossible to shift the red intervals so
    that the whole real axis becomes red. Every interval (10n, 10 (n+1)]
    is deficient - on the whole real axis.

    So what? Your imaginings don't affect the fact that there is a bijection.

    If there was a bijection, then the whole axis could become red.
    Do you believe that?

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to FromTheRafters on Sat Nov 23 13:47:30 2024
    On 23.11.2024 13:35, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM has brought this to us :
    On 23.11.2024 13:20, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM laid this down on his screen :

    Let every unit interval after a natural number on the real axis be
    coloured white with exception of the intervals after the prime
    numbers which are coloured red. It is impossible to shift the red
    intervals so that the whole real axis becomes red. Every interval
    (10n, 10 (n+1)] is deficient - on the whole real axis.

    So what? Your imaginings don't affect the fact that there is a
    bijection.

    If there was a bijection,

    There is.

    then the whole axis could become red.

    What makes you think that?

    A bijection proves that every prime number (and its colour) can be put
    to a natural number (and colour it).

    Do you believe that?

    No, of course not.

    Relieving.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to FromTheRafters on Sat Nov 23 20:40:40 2024
    On 23.11.2024 19:43, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM wrote on 11/23/2024 :
    On 23.11.2024 13:35, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM has brought this to us :
    On 23.11.2024 13:20, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM laid this down on his screen :

    Let every unit interval after a natural number on the real axis be >>>>>> coloured white with exception of the intervals after the prime
    numbers which are coloured red. It is impossible to shift the red
    intervals so that the whole real axis becomes red. Every interval
    (10n, 10 (n+1)] is deficient - on the whole real axis.

    So what? Your imaginings don't affect the fact that there is a
    bijection.

    If there was a bijection,

    There is.

    then the whole axis could become red.

    What makes you think that?

    A bijection proves that every prime number (and its colour) can be put
    to a natural number (and colour it).

    ???

    A bijection between natural numbers and prime numbers proves that for
    every prime number there is a natural number: p_1, p_2, p_3, ...
    If that is correct, then there are as many natural numbers as prime
    numbers and as many prime numbers as natural numbers. Then the following scenario is possible:

    Cover the unit intervals of prime numbers by red hats. Then shift the
    red hats so that all unit intervals of the positive real axis get red hats.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From joes@21:1/5 to All on Sat Nov 23 19:53:24 2024
    Am Sat, 23 Nov 2024 20:40:40 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 23.11.2024 19:43, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM wrote on 11/23/2024 :
    On 23.11.2024 13:35, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM has brought this to us :
    On 23.11.2024 13:20, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM laid this down on his screen :

    Let every unit interval after a natural number on the real axis be >>>>>>> coloured white with exception of the intervals after the prime
    numbers which are coloured red. It is impossible to shift the red >>>>>>> intervals so that the whole real axis becomes red. Every interval >>>>>>> (10n, 10 (n+1)] is deficient - on the whole real axis.

    So what? Your imaginings don't affect the fact that there is a
    bijection.

    If there was a bijection,
    There is.
    then the whole axis could become red.
    What makes you think that?
    A bijection between natural numbers and prime numbers proves that for
    every prime number there is a natural number: p_1, p_2, p_3, ...
    You do know the proof that there are infinitely many primes?

    If that is correct, then there are as many natural numbers as prime
    numbers and as many prime numbers as natural numbers. Then the following scenario is possible:
    Cover the unit intervals of prime numbers by red hats. Then shift the
    red hats so that all unit intervals of the positive real axis get red
    hats.
    That is the world we live in.

    --
    Am Sat, 20 Jul 2024 12:35:31 +0000 schrieb WM in sci.math:
    It is not guaranteed that n+1 exists for every n.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to joes on Sat Nov 23 21:15:57 2024
    On 23.11.2024 20:53, joes wrote:
    Am Sat, 23 Nov 2024 20:40:40 +0100 schrieb WM:

    A bijection between natural numbers and prime numbers proves that for
    every prime number there is a natural number: p_1, p_2, p_3, ...
    You do know the proof that there are infinitely many primes?

    Of course. Nevertheless they are less than 1/10 of the natural numbers.

    If that is correct, then there are as many natural numbers as prime
    numbers and as many prime numbers as natural numbers. Then the following
    scenario is possible:
    Cover the unit intervals of prime numbers by red hats. Then shift the
    red hats so that all unit intervals of the positive real axis get red
    hats.
    That is the world we live in.

    Some people believe to live in such a world. But the stupidity contained
    in their heads surpasses all stupidity contained in the real universe.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Sat Nov 23 21:45:06 2024
    On 23.11.2024 21:18, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/23/2024 5:30 AM, WM wrote:
    On 22.11.2024 22:50, Jim Burns wrote:

    ℙ covers ℕ, and ℕ covers ℙ

    Let every unit interval on
    the infinite real axis
    be coloured white. Cover the unit intervals of prime numbers
    by red hats.
    It is impossible to shift the red hats

    Yes, because we are finite beings,
    and there are infinitely.many red hats.

    No, the reason is that every shift removes the hat from its place and
    requires an other hat, taken from wherever, but with certainty leaving
    an uncovered interval. That does never change.

    It is impossible to shift the red hats
    so that all unit intervals of
    the whole real axis get red hats.
    There are too few prime numbers.

    No.

    ⎛ Assume that that is so.

    That need not be assumed but that is obviously so for every part of the
    real axis.

    ⎜ Assume that there are
    ⎜ enough red hats for the first 𝔊 numbers
    ⎜ but not enough for the 𝔊+1ᵗʰ

    That is a mistake. If there are enough hats for G natnumbers, then there
    are also enough for G^G^G natnumbers. Alas they leave G^G^G unit
    intervals without hats. That is the catch!

    There are too few prime numbers.

    No,
    there being too few primes
    leads to contradiction.

    Shall unit intervals disappear like Bob?

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Sat Nov 23 15:18:26 2024
    On 11/23/2024 5:30 AM, WM wrote:
    On 22.11.2024 22:50, Jim Burns wrote:

    ℙ covers ℕ, and ℕ covers ℙ

    Let every unit interval on
    the infinite real axis
    be coloured white.
    Cover the unit intervals of prime numbers
    by red hats.
    It is impossible to shift the red hats

    Yes, because we are finite beings,
    and there are infinitely.many red hats.

    It is impossible to shift the red hats
    so that all unit intervals of
    the whole real axis
    get red hats.
    There are too few prime numbers.

    No.

    ⎛ Assume that that is so.
    ⎜ Assume that there are
    ⎜ enough red hats for the first 𝔊 numbers
    ⎜ but not enough for the 𝔊+1ᵗʰ

    ⎜ Before shifting red hats,
    ⎜ the 𝔊ᵗʰ red hat was at the 𝔊ᵗʰ prime pr(𝔊)
    ⎜ and there were no more primes after pr(𝔊)

    ⎜ However,
    ⎜ the number pr(𝔊)!+1 is not.divisible.by
    ⎜ each number in sequence ⟦2,pr(𝔊)⟧
    ⎜ ⟦2,pr(𝔊)⟧ ᵉᵃᶜʰ~⃒ pr(G)!+1

    ⎜ Non.empty.set {i∈ℕ:⟦2,pr(𝔊)⟧ᵉᵃᶜʰ~⃒i} of numbers
    ⎜ not.divisible.by each in ⟦2,pr(𝔊)⟧
    ⎜ holds least min.{i∈ℕ:⟦2,pr(𝔊)⟧ᵉᵃᶜʰ~⃒i}

    ⎜ min.{i∈ℕ:⟦2,pr(𝔊)⟧ᵉᵃᶜʰ~⃒i} is prime

    ⎜⎛ Each of ⟦2,pr(𝔊)⟧
    ⎜⎜ not.divides min.{i∈ℕ:⟦2,pr(𝔊)⟧ᵉᵃᶜʰ~⃒i}
    ⎜⎜
    ⎜⎜ For each of ⦅pr(𝔊),min.{i∈ℕ:⟦2,pr(𝔊)⟧ᵉᵃᶜʰ~⃒i}⦆
    ⎜⎜ one of ⟦2,pr(𝔊)⟧ divides it,
    ⎜⎜ otherwise,
    ⎜⎜( min.{i∈ℕ:⟦2,pr(𝔊)⟧ᵉᵃᶜʰ~⃒i} isn't least,
    ⎜⎜ which it is.
    ⎜⎜
    ⎜⎜ Each of ⦅pr(𝔊),min.{i∈ℕ:⟦2,pr(𝔊)⟧ᵉᵃᶜʰ~⃒i}⦆ ⎜⎜ not.divides min.{i∈ℕ:⟦2,pr(𝔊)⟧ᵉᵃᶜʰ~⃒i}
    ⎜⎜ Otherwise,
    ⎜⎜⎛ one of ⟦2,pr(𝔊)⟧ which divides it
    ⎜⎜⎝ also divides min.{i∈ℕ:⟦2,pr(𝔊)⟧ᵉᵃᶜʰ~⃒i}
    ⎜⎝ which it doesn't.

    ⎜ Each of ⟦2,min.{i∈ℕ:⟦2,pr(𝔊)⟧ᵉᵃᶜʰ~⃒i}⦆
    ⎜ not.divides min.{i∈ℕ:⟦2,pr(𝔊)⟧ᵉᵃᶜʰ~⃒i}

    ⎜ min.{i∈ℕ:⟦2,pr(𝔊)⟧ᵉᵃᶜʰ~⃒i} is prime
    ⎜ min.{i∈ℕ:⟦2,pr(𝔊)⟧ᵉᵃᶜʰ~⃒i} > pr(𝔊)

    ⎜ Therefore,
    ⎜ there is another prime after pr(G)
    ⎝ Contradiction.

    There are too few prime numbers.

    No,
    there being too few primes
    leads to contradiction.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Sat Nov 23 15:46:16 2024
    On 11/23/24 2:40 PM, WM wrote:
    On 23.11.2024 19:43, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM wrote on 11/23/2024 :
    On 23.11.2024 13:35, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM has brought this to us :
    On 23.11.2024 13:20, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM laid this down on his screen :

    Let every unit interval after a natural number on the real axis
    be coloured white with exception of the intervals after the prime >>>>>>> numbers which are coloured red. It is impossible to shift the red >>>>>>> intervals so that the whole real axis becomes red. Every interval >>>>>>> (10n, 10 (n+1)] is deficient - on the whole real axis.

    So what? Your imaginings don't affect the fact that there is a
    bijection.

    If there was a bijection,

    There is.

    then the whole axis could become red.

    What makes you think that?

    A bijection proves that every prime number (and its colour) can be
    put to a natural number (and colour it).

    ???

    A bijection between natural numbers and prime numbers proves that for
    every prime number there is a natural number: p_1, p_2, p_3, ...
    If that is correct, then there are as many natural numbers as prime
    numbers and as many prime numbers as natural numbers. Then the following scenario is possible:

    Cover the unit intervals of prime numbers by red hats. Then shift the
    red hats so that all unit intervals of the positive real axis get red hats.

    Regards, WM


    And you can, as
    the red hat on the number 2, can be moved to the number 1
    the red hat on the number 3, can be moved to the number 2
    the red hat on the number 5, can be moved to the number 3

    and in general, the red hat on the nth prime number can be moved to the
    number n

    Since there are a countable infinite number of prime numbers, there
    exist an nth prime number for every n, so all the numbers get covered.

    We have a 1:1 relationship (bijection) established between the set of
    prime numbers and the set of Natural Numbers.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Richard Damon on Sat Nov 23 22:11:40 2024
    On 23.11.2024 21:46, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/23/24 2:40 PM, WM wrote:
    On 23.11.2024 19:43, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM wrote on 11/23/2024 :
    On 23.11.2024 13:35, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM has brought this to us :
    On 23.11.2024 13:20, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM laid this down on his screen :

    Let every unit interval after a natural number on the real axis >>>>>>>> be coloured white with exception of the intervals after the
    prime numbers which are coloured red. It is impossible to shift >>>>>>>> the red intervals so that the whole real axis becomes red. Every >>>>>>>> interval (10n, 10 (n+1)] is deficient - on the whole real axis. >>>>>>>
    So what? Your imaginings don't affect the fact that there is a
    bijection.

    If there was a bijection,

    There is.

    then the whole axis could become red.

    What makes you think that?

    A bijection proves that every prime number (and its colour) can be
    put to a natural number (and colour it).

    ???

    A bijection between natural numbers and prime numbers proves that for
    every prime number there is a natural number: p_1, p_2, p_3, ...
    If that is correct, then there are as many natural numbers as prime
    numbers and as many prime numbers as natural numbers. Then the
    following scenario is possible:

    Cover the unit intervals of prime numbers by red hats. Then shift the
    red hats so that all unit intervals of the positive real axis get red
    hats.

    Regards, WM


    And you can, as
    the red hat on the number 2, can be moved to the number 1
    the red hat on the number 3, can be moved to the number 2
    the red hat on the number 5, can be moved to the number 3

    A very naive recipe.

    and in general, the red hat on the nth prime number can be moved to the number n

    Since there are a countable infinite number of prime numbers, there
    exist an nth prime number for every n,

    Yes, for every n that belongs to a tiny initial segment.

    so all the numbers get covered.

    No.

    We have a 1:1 relationship (bijection) established between the set of
    prime numbers and the set of Natural Numbers.

    No. Every hat taken from wherever leaves there a naked unit interval.
    Therefore for every interval (0, n] inside which hats are moved, the
    relative covering is about n/logn.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From joes@21:1/5 to All on Sat Nov 23 21:35:36 2024
    Am Sat, 23 Nov 2024 21:45:06 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 23.11.2024 21:18, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/23/2024 5:30 AM, WM wrote:
    On 22.11.2024 22:50, Jim Burns wrote:

    ℙ covers ℕ, and ℕ covers ℙ

    Let every unit interval on the infinite real axis be coloured white.
    Cover the unit intervals of prime numbers by red hats.
    It is impossible to shift the red hats

    Yes, because we are finite beings,
    and there are infinitely.many red hats.

    No, the reason is that every shift removes the hat from its place and requires an other hat, taken from wherever, but with certainty leaving
    an uncovered interval. That does never change.
    No. That other place where we take the hats from, larger primes, are of
    course covered by even larger primes. We don't stop at some arbitrary
    finite number, but continue forever.

    It is impossible to shift the red hats so that all unit intervals of
    the whole real axis get red hats.
    There are too few prime numbers.
    No. Assume that that is so.
    That need not be assumed but that is obviously so for every part of the
    real axis.
    Not true. The first n prime numbers are obviously in bijection with the
    numbers 1 to n.

    Assume that there are enough red hats for the first 𝔊 numbers but
    not enough for the 𝔊+1ᵗʰ
    That is a mistake. If there are enough hats for G natnumbers, then there
    are also enough for G^G^G natnumbers. Alas they leave G^G^G unit
    intervals without hats. That is the catch!
    Right, that is your mistake. There are still hats left over.

    There are too few prime numbers.
    No, there being too few primes leads to contradiction.
    Shall unit intervals disappear like Bob?
    Like who?

    --
    Am Sat, 20 Jul 2024 12:35:31 +0000 schrieb WM in sci.math:
    It is not guaranteed that n+1 exists for every n.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to FromTheRafters on Sat Nov 23 22:33:58 2024
    On 23.11.2024 22:07, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM wrote :

    A bijection between natural numbers and prime numbers proves that for
    every prime number there is a natural number: p_1, p_2, p_3, ...
    If that is correct, then there are as many natural numbers as prime
    numbers and as many prime numbers as natural numbers. Then the
    following scenario is possible:

    Cover the unit intervals of prime numbers by red hats. Then shift the
    red hats so that all unit intervals of the positive real axis get red
    hats.

    What makes you think that that follows?

    Cantor.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to joes on Sat Nov 23 22:44:36 2024
    On 23.11.2024 22:35, joes wrote:
    Am Sat, 23 Nov 2024 21:45:06 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 23.11.2024 21:18, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/23/2024 5:30 AM, WM wrote:
    On 22.11.2024 22:50, Jim Burns wrote:

    ℙ covers ℕ, and ℕ covers ℙ

    Let every unit interval on the infinite real axis be coloured white.
    Cover the unit intervals of prime numbers by red hats.
    It is impossible to shift the red hats

    Yes, because we are finite beings,
    and there are infinitely.many red hats.

    No, the reason is that every shift removes the hat from its place and
    requires an other hat, taken from wherever, but with certainty leaving
    an uncovered interval. That does never change.
    No. That other place where we take the hats from, larger primes, are of course covered by even larger primes. We don't stop at some arbitrary
    finite number, but continue forever.

    It is impossible to shift the red hats so that all unit intervals of
    the whole real axis get red hats.
    There are too few prime numbers.
    No. Assume that that is so.
    That need not be assumed but that is obviously so for every part of the
    real axis.
    Not true. The first n prime numbers are obviously in bijection with the numbers 1 to n.

    But the prime numbers come from a larger interval than (0, n]. For every interval (0, n] there are more hats required than are present. The
    density of prime numbers in (0, n} is about n/logn.

    Could by simple reordering this formula be falsified, then number theory
    could be chucked away.

    Assume that there are enough red hats for the first 𝔊 numbers but
    not enough for the 𝔊+1ᵗʰ
    That is a mistake. If there are enough hats for G natnumbers, then there
    are also enough for G^G^G natnumbers. Alas they leave G^G^G unit
    intervals without hats. That is the catch!
    Right, that is your mistake. There are still hats left over.

    But fewer than are required. Because n > n/logn.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Sat Nov 23 16:48:09 2024
    On 11/23/2024 3:45 PM, WM wrote:
    On 23.11.2024 21:18, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/23/2024 5:30 AM, WM wrote:

    It is impossible to shift the red hats
    so that all unit intervals of
    the whole real axis get red hats.
    There are too few prime numbers.

    No.

    ⎛ Assume that that is so.

    That need not be assumed but
    that is obviously so for every part of the real axis.

    The obviously.so are best to assume.

    However,
    some of the seemingly.obviously.so
    require contradictions/gibberish
    and, although they seem obvious, are NOT so.

    Insufficient red hats require contradictions/gibberish.
    So, it is NOT so.

    ⎜ Assume that there are
    ⎜ enough red hats for the first 𝔊 numbers
    ⎜ but not enough for the 𝔊+1ᵗʰ

    That is a mistake.
    If there are enough hats for G natnumbers,
    then there are also enough for G^G^G natnumbers.

    Thank you.

    Alas they leave G^G^G unit intervals without hats.
    That is the catch!

    After all hat.shifts,
    there is no first number without a hat.

    After all hat.shifts,
    the set of numbers without hats is empty.

    There are too few prime numbers.

    No,
    there being too few primes
    leads to contradiction.

    Shall unit intervals disappear like Bob?

    After all swaps,
    Bob is not in any room (visible or dark)
    which Bob has ever been in.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Sat Nov 23 23:01:00 2024
    On 23.11.2024 22:48, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/23/2024 3:45 PM, WM wrote:

    ⎜ Assume that there are
    ⎜ enough red hats for the first 𝔊 numbers
    ⎜ but not enough for the 𝔊+1ᵗʰ

    That is a mistake.
    If there are enough hats for G natnumbers,
    then there are also enough for G^G^G natnumbers.

    Thank you.

    Alas they leave G^G^G unit intervals without hats.
    That is the catch!

    After all hat.shifts,
    there is no first number without a hat.

    But almost all numbers are without hat because the number of hats has
    not increased.

    After all hat.shifts,
    the set of numbers without hats is empty.

    Then the number of hats must have increased.
    Then number theory can be wasted, because its formula for n/logn primes
    in (0, n] is no longer valid after Cantor-reordering.

    There are too few prime numbers.

    No,
    there being too few primes
    leads to contradiction.

    Shall unit intervals disappear like Bob?

    After all swaps,
    Bob is not in any room (visible or dark)

    He is in a dark room.

    which Bob has ever been in.

    But the unit intervals remain steadfast on the real line.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From joes@21:1/5 to All on Sat Nov 23 23:44:42 2024
    Am Sat, 23 Nov 2024 23:01:00 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 23.11.2024 22:48, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/23/2024 3:45 PM, WM wrote:

    ⎜ Assume that there are ⎜ enough red hats for the first 𝔊 numbers ⎜
    but not enough for the 𝔊+1ᵗʰ
    That is a mistake.
    If there are enough hats for G natnumbers,
    then there are also enough for G^G^G natnumbers.
    Thank you.

    Alas they leave G^G^G unit intervals without hats.
    That is the catch!
    After all hat.shifts,
    there is no first number without a hat.
    But almost all numbers are without hat because the number of hats has
    not increased.
    No. "Almost all" means everything except for a finite number.
    If something remains you only shifted a finite number.

    After all hat.shifts,
    the set of numbers without hats is empty.
    Then the number of hats must have increased.
    Then number theory can be wasted, because its formula for n/logn primes
    in (0, n] is no longer valid after Cantor-reordering.
    It is still valid for every finite interval.

    There are too few prime numbers.
    No, there being too few primes leads to contradiction.
    Shall unit intervals disappear like Bob?
    After all swaps, Bob is not in any room (visible or dark)
    He is in a dark room.

    which Bob has ever been in.
    But the unit intervals remain steadfast on the real line.
    Bob is in none of them.

    --
    Am Sat, 20 Jul 2024 12:35:31 +0000 schrieb WM in sci.math:
    It is not guaranteed that n+1 exists for every n.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Sat Nov 23 21:22:17 2024
    On 11/23/24 4:11 PM, WM wrote:
    On 23.11.2024 21:46, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/23/24 2:40 PM, WM wrote:
    On 23.11.2024 19:43, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM wrote on 11/23/2024 :
    On 23.11.2024 13:35, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM has brought this to us :
    On 23.11.2024 13:20, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM laid this down on his screen :

    Let every unit interval after a natural number on the real axis >>>>>>>>> be coloured white with exception of the intervals after the
    prime numbers which are coloured red. It is impossible to shift >>>>>>>>> the red intervals so that the whole real axis becomes red.
    Every interval (10n, 10 (n+1)] is deficient - on the whole real >>>>>>>>> axis.

    So what? Your imaginings don't affect the fact that there is a >>>>>>>> bijection.

    If there was a bijection,

    There is.

    then the whole axis could become red.

    What makes you think that?

    A bijection proves that every prime number (and its colour) can be
    put to a natural number (and colour it).

    ???

    A bijection between natural numbers and prime numbers proves that for
    every prime number there is a natural number: p_1, p_2, p_3, ...
    If that is correct, then there are as many natural numbers as prime
    numbers and as many prime numbers as natural numbers. Then the
    following scenario is possible:

    Cover the unit intervals of prime numbers by red hats. Then shift the
    red hats so that all unit intervals of the positive real axis get red
    hats.

    Regards, WM


    And you can, as
    the red hat on the number 2, can be moved to the number 1
    the red hat on the number 3, can be moved to the number 2
    the red hat on the number 5, can be moved to the number 3

    A very naive recipe.

    But it works.


    and in general, the red hat on the nth prime number can be moved to
    the number n

    Since there are a countable infinite number of prime numbers, there
    exist an nth prime number for every n,

    Yes, for every n that belongs to a tiny initial segment.

    No, for EVERY n.

    Show one that it doesn't work for!


    so all the numbers get covered.

    No.

    WHich one doesn't.

    Your LYING claims just prove your ignorance.


    We have a 1:1 relationship (bijection) established between the set of
    prime numbers and the set of Natural Numbers.

    No. Every hat taken from wherever leaves there a naked unit interval. Therefore for every interval (0, n] inside which hats are moved, the
    relative covering is about n/logn.

    Yes, it leave a naked unit interval, that will later be replaced by the
    n-th prime.

    Your problem is you apparently you can only think about finite sets, so
    you brain just explodes when you try to handle a truely infinite one.

    Infinity isn't just a redeculously big number, it is a different class
    of numbers, something your "finite number" logic just doesn't handle.



    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Sun Nov 24 00:37:10 2024
    On 11/23/2024 5:01 PM, WM wrote:
    On 23.11.2024 22:48, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/23/2024 3:45 PM, WM wrote:

    ⎜ Assume that there are
    ⎜ enough red hats for the first 𝔊 numbers
    ⎜ but not enough for the 𝔊+1ᵗʰ

    That is a mistake.
    If there are enough hats for G natnumbers,
    then there are also enough for G^G^G natnumbers.

    Thank you.

    Alas they leave G^G^G unit intervals without hats.
    That is the catch!

    After all hat.shifts,
    there is no first number without a hat.

    But almost all numbers are without hat
    because the number of hats has not increased.

    If there are enough hats for G natural numbers,
    then there are also enough for G^G^G natural numbers.

    If there are NOT enough for G^G^G natural numbers,
    then there are also NOT enough for G natural numbers.

    G precedes G^G^G.
    If, for both G and G^G^G, there are NOT enough hats,
    G^G^G is not first for which there are not enough.

    That generalizes to
    each natural number is not.first for which
    there are NOT enough hats.

    ----
    Consider the set of natural numbers for which
    there are NOT enough hats.

    Since it is a set of natural numbers,
    there are two possibilities:
    -- It could be the empty set.
    -- It could be non.empty and hold a first number.

    Its first number, if it existed, would be
    the first natural number for which
    there are NOT enough hats.

    However,
    the FIRST natural number for which
    there are NOT enough hats
    does not exist.

    ⎛ Recall that it does not exist
    ⎜ because,
    ⎜ if there are enough hats for G natural numbers,
    ⎝ then there are also enough for G^G^G natural numbers.

    The set of natural numbers
    for which there are NOT enough hats
    does not hold its first number.
    No number exists that can be the first number.

    It can only be the first case, that
    the set of natural numbers
    for which there are NOT enough hats
    is empty.

    Its complement,
    the set of natural numbers
    for which there ARE enough hats
    is the complete set of natural numbers.

    ----
    Therefore,
    for each natural number,
    there are enough hats.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Richard Damon on Sun Nov 24 11:31:00 2024
    On 24.11.2024 03:22, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/23/24 4:11 PM, WM wrote:

    Cover the unit intervals of prime numbers by red hats. Then shift
    the red hats so that all unit intervals of the positive real axis
    get red hats.

    And you can, as
    the red hat on the number 2, can be moved to the number 1
    the red hat on the number 3, can be moved to the number 2
    the red hat on the number 5, can be moved to the number 3

    A very naive recipe.

    But it works.

    It fails in every step to cover the interval (0, n] with hats taken from
    this interval.

    Yes, for every n that belongs to a tiny initial segment.

    No, for EVERY n.

    Show one that it doesn't work for!

    The complete covering fails in every interval (0, n] with hats taken
    from this interval.


    so all the numbers get covered.

    No.

    WHich one doesn't.

    Almost all. The reason is simple mathematics. For every interval (0, n]
    the relative covering is 1/10, independent of how the hats are shifted.
    This cannot be remedied in the infinite limit because outside of all
    finite intervals (0, n] there are no further hats available.

    On the other hand, we cannot find a first n that cannot be covered by a
    hat. This dilemma cannot be resolved by negating one of the two facts.
    It can only be solved by dark numbers.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Sun Nov 24 12:06:16 2024
    On 24.11.2024 06:37, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/23/2024 5:01 PM, WM wrote:


    If there are enough hats for G natural numbers,
    then there are also enough for G^G^G natural numbers.

    So it is. But that does not negate the fact that for every interval (0,
    n] the relative covering is 1/10, independent of how the hats are
    shifted. This cannot be remedied in the infinite limit because outside
    of all finite intervals (0, n] there are no further hats available.

    If there are NOT enough for G^G^G natural numbers,
    then there are also NOT enough for G natural numbers.

    G precedes G^G^G.
    If, for both G and G^G^G, there are NOT enough hats,
    G^G^G is not first for which there are not enough.

    That generalizes to
    each natural number is not.first for which
    there are NOT enough hats.

    It seems so but the sequence 1/10, 1/10, 1/10, ... has limit 1/10 with
    no doubt. This dilemma is the reason why dark numbers are required.

    ----
    Consider the set of natural numbers for which
    there are NOT enough hats.

    It is dark.

    Since it is a set of natural numbers,
    there are two possibilities:
    -- It could be the empty set.
    -- It could be non.empty and hold a first number.

    Both attempts fail. That is the reason why dark numbers are required.

    Its first number, if it existed, would be
    the first natural number for which
    there are NOT enough hats.

    However,
    the FIRST natural number for which
    there are NOT enough hats
    does not exist.

    That however does not negate the fact that for all intervals (0, n] and
    also for all intervals (10n, 10(n+1)] with no exception from which
    another load of hats could be acquired there are not enough hats to
    cover all n.
    Therefore,
    for each natural number,
    there are enough hats.

    Then mathematics fails. I don't accept that a constant sequence has
    another limit than this constant.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to FromTheRafters on Sun Nov 24 12:14:48 2024
    On 24.11.2024 12:07, FromTheRafters wrote:
    on 11/23/2024, WM supposed :
    On 23.11.2024 22:07, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM wrote :

    A bijection between natural numbers and prime numbers proves that
    for every prime number there is a natural number: p_1, p_2, p_3, ...
    If that is correct, then there are as many natural numbers as prime
    numbers and as many prime numbers as natural numbers. Then the
    following scenario is possible:

    Cover the unit intervals of prime numbers by red hats. Then shift
    the red hats so that all unit intervals of the positive real axis
    get red hats.

    What makes you think that that follows?

    Cantor.

    Show me Cantor shifting interval hats!

    Constructing a bijection between the two sets is visualized by hats.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to joes on Sun Nov 24 11:19:47 2024
    On 24.11.2024 00:44, joes wrote:
    Am Sat, 23 Nov 2024 23:01:00 +0100 schrieb WM:

    But almost all numbers are without hat because the number of hats has
    not increased.
    No. "Almost all" means everything except for a finite number.

    Here it means infinitely many more.

    Then number theory can be wasted, because its formula for n/logn primes
    in (0, n] is no longer valid after Cantor-reordering.
    It is still valid for every finite interval.

    It is also valid for the infinite interval because outside of all
    intervals (0, n] there are no more hats available.
    Further in number theory it is accepted for the whole set.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Sun Nov 24 07:12:56 2024
    On 11/24/24 5:31 AM, WM wrote:
    On 24.11.2024 03:22, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/23/24 4:11 PM, WM wrote:

    Cover the unit intervals of prime numbers by red hats. Then shift
    the red hats so that all unit intervals of the positive real axis
    get red hats.

    And you can, as
    the red hat on the number 2, can be moved to the number 1
    the red hat on the number 3, can be moved to the number 2
    the red hat on the number 5, can be moved to the number 3

    A very naive recipe.

    But it works.

    It fails in every step to cover the interval (0, n] with hats taken from
    this interval.

    But that isn't the requirement.

    The requirement it to map from ALL Prime Natural Numbers to ALL Natural
    Numbers


    Yes, for every n that belongs to a tiny initial segment.

    No, for EVERY n.

    Show one that it doesn't work for!

    The complete covering fails in every interval (0, n] with hats taken
    from this interval.

    Which isn't the interval in question.

    Your funny-mental fallacy is that you think an infinite set can be
    thought of as just some finite set allowed to keep growning until it
    reaches infinity,

    That is just the wrong model.


    so all the numbers get covered.

    No.

    WHich one doesn't.

    Almost all. The reason is simple mathematics. For every interval (0, n]
    the relative covering is 1/10, independent of how the hats are shifted.
    This cannot be remedied in the infinite limit because outside of all
    finite intervals (0, n] there are no further hats available.

    But finite sets aren't infinite sets, and don't act the same as them.


    On the other hand, we cannot find a first n that cannot be covered by a
    hat. This dilemma cannot be resolved by negating one of the two facts.
    It can only be solved by dark numbers.


    Nope, your idea of mathematics has contradictions in it that have
    exploded your mind and left just a "dark hole" behind. You can not just
    use finite mathematics on infinite sets.

    Regards, WM



    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Sun Nov 24 07:14:54 2024
    On 11/24/24 5:19 AM, WM wrote:
    On 24.11.2024 00:44, joes wrote:
    Am Sat, 23 Nov 2024 23:01:00 +0100 schrieb WM:

    But almost all numbers are without hat because the number of hats has
    not increased.
    No. "Almost all" means everything except for a finite number.

    Here it means infinitely many more.

    Then number theory can be wasted, because its formula for n/logn primes
    in (0, n] is no longer valid after Cantor-reordering.
    It is still valid for every finite interval.

    It is also valid for the infinite interval because outside of all
    intervals (0, n] there are no more hats available.
    Further in number theory it is accepted for the whole set.

    Regards, WM


    Of course there are, EVERY prime number go a hat.

    Your funny-mental problem is that you think the infinite acts just like
    the finite, which it doesn't.

    You just never have HAD an infinite sets, just sets bigger than YOU can
    count to.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to FromTheRafters on Sun Nov 24 13:24:53 2024
    On 24.11.2024 12:55, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM formulated the question :
    On 24.11.2024 12:07, FromTheRafters wrote:
    on 11/23/2024, WM supposed :
    On 23.11.2024 22:07, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM wrote :

    A bijection between natural numbers and prime numbers proves that
    for every prime number there is a natural number: p_1, p_2, p_3, ... >>>>>> If that is correct, then there are as many natural numbers as
    prime numbers and as many prime numbers as natural numbers. Then
    the following scenario is possible:

    Cover the unit intervals of prime numbers by red hats. Then shift
    the red hats so that all unit intervals of the positive real axis
    get red hats.

    What makes you think that that follows?

    Cantor.

    Show me Cantor shifting interval hats!

    Constructing a bijection between the two sets is visualized by hats.

    Where?

    Here!

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Richard Damon on Sun Nov 24 13:26:39 2024
    On 24.11.2024 13:12, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/24/24 5:31 AM, WM wrote:
    On 24.11.2024 03:22, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/23/24 4:11 PM, WM wrote:

    Cover the unit intervals of prime numbers by red hats. Then shift
    the red hats so that all unit intervals of the positive real axis
    get red hats.

    And you can, as
    the red hat on the number 2, can be moved to the number 1
    the red hat on the number 3, can be moved to the number 2
    the red hat on the number 5, can be moved to the number 3

    A very naive recipe.

    But it works.

    It fails in every step to cover the interval (0, n] with hats taken
    from this interval.

    But that isn't the requirement.

    The requirement it to map from ALL Prime Natural Numbers to ALL Natural Numbers


    Yes, for every n that belongs to a tiny initial segment.

    No, for EVERY n.

    Show one that it doesn't work for!

    The complete covering fails in every interval (0, n] with hats taken
    from this interval.

    Which isn't the interval in question.

    Your funny-mental fallacy is that you think an infinite set can be
    thought of as just some finite set allowed to keep growning until it
    reaches infinity,

    That is just the wrong model.


    so all the numbers get covered.

    No.

    WHich one doesn't.

    Almost all. The reason is simple mathematics. For every interval (0,
    n] the relative covering is 1/10, independent of how the hats are
    shifted. This cannot be remedied in the infinite limit because outside
    of all finite intervals (0, n] there are no further hats available.

    But finite sets aren't infinite sets, and don't act the same as them.

    All finite sets are the infinite set.

    You can not just
    use finite mathematics on infinite sets.

    But I can use the analytical limit of the constant sequence.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From joes@21:1/5 to All on Sun Nov 24 14:40:55 2024
    Am Sun, 24 Nov 2024 11:31:00 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 24.11.2024 03:22, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/23/24 4:11 PM, WM wrote:

    Cover the unit intervals of prime numbers by red hats. Then shift
    the red hats so that all unit intervals of the positive real axis
    get red hats.
    And you can, as the red hat on the number 2, can be moved to the
    number 1 the red hat on the number 3, can be moved to the number 2
    the red hat on the number 5, can be moved to the number 3

    It fails in every step to cover the interval (0, n] with hats taken from
    this interval.
    Nobody cares about a nonbijection from N to N. We are interested in a
    bijection from N to P, or {0, 1, ..., n} to {p0, p1, ..., p_n}

    Yes, for every n that belongs to a tiny initial segment.
    No, for EVERY n. Show one that it doesn't work for!
    The complete covering fails in every interval (0, n] with hats taken
    from this interval.
    Think about it the other way around: when we take the primes and
    number them, we are never done, because there are inf.many primes.
    Therefore we need the set of all naturals, N, to count them. Then
    there can't be fewer primes than naturals, since the cardinality
    of N is the smallest infinity.

    so all the numbers get covered.
    No.
    WHich one doesn't.
    Almost all. For every interval (0, n]
    the relative covering is 1/10, independent of how the hats are shifted.
    As above, nobody is arguing that the primes are somehow more infinite.

    This cannot be remedied in the infinite limit because outside of all
    finite intervals (0, n] there are no further hats available.
    Yes it can, if you start out with a proper finite bijection.

    On the other hand, we cannot find a first n that cannot be covered by a
    hat. This dilemma cannot be resolved by negating one of the two facts.
    It can only be solved by dark numbers.
    Or getting over your wrong intuition.

    --
    Am Sat, 20 Jul 2024 12:35:31 +0000 schrieb WM in sci.math:
    It is not guaranteed that n+1 exists for every n.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to joes on Sun Nov 24 16:23:14 2024
    On 24.11.2024 15:40, joes wrote:
    Am Sun, 24 Nov 2024 11:31:00 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 24.11.2024 03:22, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/23/24 4:11 PM, WM wrote:

    Cover the unit intervals of prime numbers by red hats. Then shift
    the red hats so that all unit intervals of the positive real axis
    get red hats.
    And you can, as the red hat on the number 2, can be moved to the
    number 1 the red hat on the number 3, can be moved to the number 2
    the red hat on the number 5, can be moved to the number 3

    It fails in every step to cover the interval (0, n] with hats taken from
    this interval.
    Nobody cares about a nonbijection from N to N. We are interested in a bijection from N to P, or {0, 1, ..., n} to {p0, p1, ..., p_n}

    That can be excluded because there are too few hats in all intervals.

    Yes, for every n that belongs to a tiny initial segment.
    No, for EVERY n. Show one that it doesn't work for!
    The complete covering fails in every interval (0, n] with hats taken
    from this interval.
    Think about it the other way around: when we take the primes and
    number them, we are never done, because there are inf.many primes.
    Therefore we need the set of all naturals, N, to count them.

    Even the naturals divisible by 10000000 would suffice if Cantor was
    right. But he is not.

    so all the numbers get covered.
    No.
    WHich one doesn't.
    Almost all. For every interval (0, n]
    the relative covering is 1/10, independent of how the hats are shifted.
    As above, nobody is arguing that the primes are somehow more infinite.

    They are less than the naturals.

    This cannot be remedied in the infinite limit because outside of all
    finite intervals (0, n] there are no further hats available.
    Yes it can, if you start out with a proper finite bijection.

    If it could exist, then all hats could cover all naturals. But that is
    excluded by the relative covering of 1/10 in all intervals (0, n].

    On the other hand, we cannot find a first n that cannot be covered by a
    hat. This dilemma cannot be resolved by negating one of the two facts.
    It can only be solved by dark numbers.
    Or getting over your wrong intuition.

    The limit of a constant sequence is its constant. No intuition.

    Regards, WM


    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Sun Nov 24 12:22:53 2024
    On 11/24/24 7:26 AM, WM wrote:
    On 24.11.2024 13:12, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/24/24 5:31 AM, WM wrote:
    On 24.11.2024 03:22, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/23/24 4:11 PM, WM wrote:

    Cover the unit intervals of prime numbers by red hats. Then shift >>>>>>> the red hats so that all unit intervals of the positive real axis >>>>>>> get red hats.

    And you can, as
    the red hat on the number 2, can be moved to the number 1
    the red hat on the number 3, can be moved to the number 2
    the red hat on the number 5, can be moved to the number 3

    A very naive recipe.

    But it works.

    It fails in every step to cover the interval (0, n] with hats taken
    from this interval.

    But that isn't the requirement.

    The requirement it to map from ALL Prime Natural Numbers to ALL
    Natural Numbers


    Yes, for every n that belongs to a tiny initial segment.

    No, for EVERY n.

    Show one that it doesn't work for!

    The complete covering fails in every interval (0, n] with hats taken
    from this interval.

    Which isn't the interval in question.

    Your funny-mental fallacy is that you think an infinite set can be
    thought of as just some finite set allowed to keep growning until it
    reaches infinity,

    That is just the wrong model.


    so all the numbers get covered.

    No.

    WHich one doesn't.

    Almost all. The reason is simple mathematics. For every interval (0,
    n] the relative covering is 1/10, independent of how the hats are
    shifted. This cannot be remedied in the infinite limit because
    outside of all finite intervals (0, n] there are no further hats
    available.

    But finite sets aren't infinite sets, and don't act the same as them.

    All finite sets are the infinite set.

    You can not just use finite mathematics on infinite sets.

    But I can use the analytical limit of the constant sequence.

    Regards, WM


    Nope, since the finite sets are not the same as the infinite set, the
    property you are looking at just doesn't exist in the infinite set.

    Limit theory only works if the limit actually exists

    You can get things that APPEAR to reach a limit, but actually don't.

    You are just confirming that yoiu mind HAS benn exploded by the
    contradictions of using finite logic on infinite sets, and that has left
    the great big "dark hole" in your logic, that doesn't actually exist.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Richard Damon on Sun Nov 24 18:32:27 2024
    On 24.11.2024 18:22, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/24/24 7:26 AM, WM wrote:
    On 24.11.2024 13:12, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/24/24 5:31 AM, WM wrote:
    On 24.11.2024 03:22, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/23/24 4:11 PM, WM wrote:

    Cover the unit intervals of prime numbers by red hats. Then
    shift the red hats so that all unit intervals of the positive
    real axis get red hats.

    And you can, as
    the red hat on the number 2, can be moved to the number 1
    the red hat on the number 3, can be moved to the number 2
    the red hat on the number 5, can be moved to the number 3

    A very naive recipe.

    But it works.

    It fails in every step to cover the interval (0, n] with hats taken
    from this interval.

    But that isn't the requirement.

    The requirement it to map from ALL Prime Natural Numbers to ALL
    Natural Numbers


    Yes, for every n that belongs to a tiny initial segment.

    No, for EVERY n.

    Show one that it doesn't work for!

    The complete covering fails in every interval (0, n] with hats taken
    from this interval.

    Which isn't the interval in question.

    Your funny-mental fallacy is that you think an infinite set can be
    thought of as just some finite set allowed to keep growning until it
    reaches infinity,

    That is just the wrong model.


    so all the numbers get covered.

    No.

    WHich one doesn't.

    Almost all. The reason is simple mathematics. For every interval (0,
    n] the relative covering is 1/10, independent of how the hats are
    shifted. This cannot be remedied in the infinite limit because
    outside of all finite intervals (0, n] there are no further hats
    available.

    But finite sets aren't infinite sets, and don't act the same as them.

    All finite sets are the infinite set.

    You can not just use finite mathematics on infinite sets.

    But I can use the analytical limit of the constant sequence.

    Nope, since the finite sets are not the same as the infinite set, the property you are looking at just doesn't exist in the infinite set.

    The finite sets contains all hats because all natural numbers and all
    10n are in finite sets. No hat is outside.>
    Limit theory only works if the limit actually exists

    If limits exist at all, then the limit of the sequence 1/10, 1/10, 1/10,
    ... does exist.

    You can get things that APPEAR to reach a limit, but actually don't.

    But if infinite sets do exist, then the set ℕ does exist, and all its elements are members of finite intervals (0, n].

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Sun Nov 24 12:26:47 2024
    On 11/24/24 10:23 AM, WM wrote:
    On 24.11.2024 15:40, joes wrote:
    Am Sun, 24 Nov 2024 11:31:00 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 24.11.2024 03:22, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/23/24 4:11 PM, WM wrote:

    Cover the unit intervals of prime numbers by red hats. Then shift >>>>>>> the red hats so that all unit intervals of the positive real axis >>>>>>> get red hats.
    And you can, as the red hat on the number 2, can be moved to the
    number 1 the red hat on the number 3, can be moved to the number 2 >>>>>> the red hat on the number 5, can be moved to the number 3

    It fails in every step to cover the interval (0, n] with hats taken from >>> this interval.
    Nobody cares about a nonbijection from N to N. We are interested in a
    bijection from N to P, or {0, 1, ..., n} to {p0, p1, ..., p_n}

    That can be excluded because there are too few hats in all intervals.

    But the bijection is for INFINITE sets, not finite sets, so you are just showing you believe in strawmen.


    Yes, for every n that belongs to a tiny initial segment.
    No, for EVERY n. Show one that it doesn't work for!
    The complete covering fails in every interval (0, n] with hats taken
    from this interval.
    Think about it the other way around: when we take the primes and
    number them, we are never done, because there are inf.many primes.
    Therefore we need the set of all naturals, N, to count them.

    Even the naturals divisible by 10000000 would suffice if Cantor was
    right. But he is not.

    But he is, and you are not because you mind has been exploded by your
    use of incorrect logic.


    so all the numbers get covered.
    No.
    WHich one doesn't.
    Almost all. For every interval (0, n]
    the relative covering is 1/10, independent of how the hats are shifted.
    As above, nobody is arguing that the primes are somehow more infinite.

    They are less than the naturals.

    Nope, They form a 1:1 so are of the same size, Aleph_0, you just don't understand the mathematics of such a thing, causing your mind to be
    exploded.


    This cannot be remedied in the infinite limit because outside of all
    finite intervals (0, n] there are no further hats available.
    Yes it can, if you start out with a proper finite bijection.

    If it could exist, then all hats could cover all naturals. But that is excluded by the relative covering of 1/10 in all intervals (0, n].

    Nope, that is just your mind being exploded by your use of invalid logic
    on an infinte set.


    On the other hand, we cannot find a first n that cannot be covered by a
    hat. This dilemma cannot be resolved by negating one of the two facts.
    It can only be solved by dark numbers.
    Or getting over your wrong intuition.

    The limit of a constant sequence is its constant. No intuition.

    Only if the results applies to the infinite.

    Sorry, your logic is just bad, being based on an incorrect "intuition"


    Regards, WM



    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Sun Nov 24 13:16:45 2024
    On 11/23/2024 3:45 PM, WM wrote:

    If there are enough hats for G natnumbers,
    then there are also enough for G^G^G natnumbers.

    On 11/24/2024 6:06 AM, WM wrote:
    On 24.11.2024 06:37, Jim Burns wrote:

    If there are enough hats for G natural numbers,
    then there are also enough for G^G^G natural numbers.

    So it is.

    Thank you.
    That is enough to see that
    the hats behave like they are
    more than unreasonably.large.but.finite.

    But that does not negate the fact that
    for every interval (0,n]
    the relative covering is 1/10,
    independent of how the hats are shifted.
    This cannot be remedied in the infinite limit
    because
    outside of all finite intervals (0, n]
    there are no further hats available.

    All the hats for which
    if there are G.many then there are G^G^G.many
    are enough to "remedy" the 1/10.relative.covering

    If each G can match G^G^G
    then
    all of those numbers G match
    a proper subset G^G^G of all of those numbers G.

    Matching.a.proper.subset is
    the sort of behavior which permits Bob to disappear
    with enough room.swapping _inside_ the Hotel.

    You (WM) treat that behavior as proof that
    we are wrong and you (WM) are right.
    What it is is proof that
    not all sets behave like finite sets.

    By 'finite', I mean our 'finite', with
    its fundamentally different behavior,
    not your (WM's) 'finite', which merely means
    more of the same, even though
    the 'more' is 'super.colossally more'.

    If there are NOT enough for G^G^G natural numbers,
    then there are also NOT enough for G natural numbers.

    G precedes G^G^G.
    If, for both G and G^G^G, there are NOT enough hats,
    G^G^G is not first for which there are not enough.

    That generalizes to
    each natural number is not.first for which
    there are NOT enough hats.

    It seems so but
    the sequence 1/10, 1/10, 1/10, ... has limit 1/10
    with no doubt.

    If there are enough hats for G natural numbers,
    then there are also enough for G^G^G natural numbers.

    The number G^G^G is not.first for which
    there are NOT enough hats.

    ⎛ Assume otherwise.
    ⎜ Assume G^G^G is first for which
    ⎜ there are NOT enough hats.

    ⎜ G < G^G^G
    ⎜ There ARE enough hats for G.
    ⎜ If there are enough hats for G natural numbers,
    ⎜ then there are also enough for G^G^G natural numbers.
    ⎜ There ARE enough hats for G^G^G

    ⎜ However,
    ⎜ there are NOT enough hats for G^G^G
    ⎝ Contradiction.

    Therefore,
    the number G^G^G is not.first for which
    there are NOT enough hats.

    A similar argument can be made for
    each natural number.
    Therefore,
    each natural number is not.first for which
    there are NOT enough hats.

    This dilemma is the reason
    why dark numbers are required.

    ----
    Consider the set of natural numbers for which
    there are NOT enough hats.

    It is dark.

    It is not dark what we mean by 'natural number'.
    A natural number is countable.to from.0

    That knowledge narrows the possibilities to two.

    Since it is a set of natural numbers,
    there are two possibilities:
    -- It could be the empty set.
    -- It could be non.empty and hold a first number.

    Both attempts fail.

    The natural numbers "fail" at
    being finitely.many.
    It is nothing more than that.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Sun Nov 24 14:14:57 2024
    On 11/24/24 12:32 PM, WM wrote:
    On 24.11.2024 18:22, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/24/24 7:26 AM, WM wrote:
    On 24.11.2024 13:12, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/24/24 5:31 AM, WM wrote:
    On 24.11.2024 03:22, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/23/24 4:11 PM, WM wrote:

    Cover the unit intervals of prime numbers by red hats. Then
    shift the red hats so that all unit intervals of the positive >>>>>>>>> real axis get red hats.

    And you can, as
    the red hat on the number 2, can be moved to the number 1
    the red hat on the number 3, can be moved to the number 2
    the red hat on the number 5, can be moved to the number 3

    A very naive recipe.

    But it works.

    It fails in every step to cover the interval (0, n] with hats taken
    from this interval.

    But that isn't the requirement.

    The requirement it to map from ALL Prime Natural Numbers to ALL
    Natural Numbers


    Yes, for every n that belongs to a tiny initial segment.

    No, for EVERY n.

    Show one that it doesn't work for!

    The complete covering fails in every interval (0, n] with hats
    taken from this interval.

    Which isn't the interval in question.

    Your funny-mental fallacy is that you think an infinite set can be
    thought of as just some finite set allowed to keep growning until it
    reaches infinity,

    That is just the wrong model.


    so all the numbers get covered.

    No.

    WHich one doesn't.

    Almost all. The reason is simple mathematics. For every interval
    (0, n] the relative covering is 1/10, independent of how the hats
    are shifted. This cannot be remedied in the infinite limit because
    outside of all finite intervals (0, n] there are no further hats
    available.

    But finite sets aren't infinite sets, and don't act the same as them.

    All finite sets are the infinite set.

    You can not just use finite mathematics on infinite sets.

    But I can use the analytical limit of the constant sequence.

    Nope, since the finite sets are not the same as the infinite set, the
    property you are looking at just doesn't exist in the infinite set.

    The finite sets contains all hats because all natural numbers and all
    10n are in finite sets. No hat is outside.>

    But there is no finite set with ALL natural numbers.

    Like usual, you mess up with your qualifiers.


    Limit theory only works if the limit actually exists

    If limits exist at all, then the limit of the sequence 1/10, 1/10,
    1/10, ... does exist.

    But the concept of 1/10th of an infinte set does not exist.

    Sorry, you are just proving your stupidity,


    You can get things that APPEAR to reach a limit, but actually don't.

    But if infinite sets do exist, then the set ℕ does exist, and all its elements are members of finite intervals (0, n].

    No, any given element is a member of a finite set, but you can't then
    say that ALL are in such a set.

    WIth infinity, Any and All are different qualifiers.


    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Mon Nov 25 00:39:37 2024
    Am 25.11.2024 um 00:30 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:
    On 11/24/2024 4:24 AM, WM wrote:
    On 24.11.2024 12:55, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM wrote:

    Constructing a bijection between the two sets is visualized by hats.

    Where?

    Here!

    In the psychiatric hospital you -Mückenheim- are in?

    A dunce hat? Humm, were you wearing such a hat when you were born? I
    feel sorry for your Mom, wow! Ouch.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Mon Nov 25 01:05:05 2024
    Am 25.11.2024 um 00:29 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:

    Let me guess... WM thinks [...]

    Ha ha ha :-) ... Good one!!!

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Mon Nov 25 13:11:26 2024
    On 24.11.2024 19:16, Jim Burns wrote:

    On 11/23/2024 3:45 PM, WM wrote:

    for every interval (0,n]
    the relative covering is 1/10,
    independent of how the hats are shifted.
    This cannot be remedied in the infinite limit
    because
    outside of all finite intervals (0, n]
    there are no further hats available.

    All the hats for which
     if there are G.many then there are G^G^G.many
    are enough to "remedy" the 1/10.relative.covering

    Not at all!

    If each G can match G^G^G

    That is a false assumption.
    If there are enough hats to cover G then there are enough hats to cover
    G^G^G. G does not cover G^G^G.

    Matching.a.proper.subset is
    the sort of behavior which permits Bob to disappear
    with enough room.swapping _inside_ the Hotel.

    You (WM) treat that behavior as proof that
    we are wrong and you (WM) are right.

    I accept logic. Exchange of two elements never leads to loss of one of
    them. You do not.

    What it is  is proof that
    not all sets behave like finite sets.

    Nonsense. Logic is also prevailing in infinite sets.

    If there are enough hats for G natural numbers,
    then there are also enough for G^G^G natural numbers.

    The number G^G^G is not.first for which
    there are NOT enough hats.

    There is no such number because the set of definable hats is potentially infinite.

    Therefore,
    the number G^G^G is not.first for which
    there are NOT enough hats.

    We do not disagree. Therefore you need not prove a difference for G and
    G^G^G.

    A similar argument can be made for
     each natural number.

    No, it can be made for each definable natural number, i.e., for a number belonging to a tiny finite initial segment which is followed bay almost
    all numbers.

    Consider the set of natural numbers for which
    there are NOT enough hats.

    It is dark.

    It is not dark what we mean by 'natural number'.
    A natural number is countable.to from.0

    That is a definable number.
    The natural numbers "fail" at
    being finitely.many.
    It is nothing more than that.

    If they are infinitely many but complete, then they and their number
    don't vary. |ℕ| - 1 < |ℕ| < |ℕ| + 1.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Richard Damon on Mon Nov 25 13:18:28 2024
    On 24.11.2024 20:14, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/24/24 12:32 PM, WM wrote:

    The finite sets contain all hats because all natural numbers and all
    10n are in finite sets. No hat is outside.>

    But there is no finite set with ALL natural numbers.

    ℕ is fixed, that means |ℕ| is fixed.

    Like usual, you mess up with your qualifiers.
    Limit theory only works if the limit actually exists

    If limits exist at all, then the limit of the sequence 1/10, 1/10,
    1/10, ... does exist.

    But the concept of 1/10th of an infinte set does not exist..

    It does.

    You can get things that APPEAR to reach a limit, but actually don't.

    But if infinite sets do exist, then the set ℕ does exist, and all its
    elements are members of finite intervals (0, n].

    No, any given element is a member of a finite set, but you can't then
    say that ALL are in such a set.

    All are in the union of all finite sets.

    WIth infinity, Any and All are different qualifiers.

    Use them to increase your qualification.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Mon Nov 25 12:52:24 2024
    On 11/25/24 7:18 AM, WM wrote:
    On 24.11.2024 20:14, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/24/24 12:32 PM, WM wrote:

    The finite sets contain all hats because all natural numbers and all
    10n are in finite sets. No hat is outside.>

    But there is no finite set with ALL natural numbers.

    ℕ is fixed, that means |ℕ| is fixed.

    But infinite, and thus a series of finite sets are not actually an approximation for it.

    Your problem is that your "generator" for the Natural Numbers never
    finishes, so you never get to have them.


    Like usual, you mess up with your qualifiers.
    Limit theory only works if the limit actually exists

    If limits exist at all, then the limit of the sequence 1/10, 1/10,
    1/10, ... does exist.

    But the concept of 1/10th of an infinte set does not exist..

    It does.

    Nope, not the way you want it to be. 1/10 of Aleph_0 is still Aleph_0 so
    the two sets are the same size.


    You can get things that APPEAR to reach a limit, but actually don't.

    But if infinite sets do exist, then the set ℕ does exist, and all its
    elements are members of finite intervals (0, n].

    No, any given element is a member of a finite set, but you can't then
    say that ALL are in such a set.

    All are in the union of all finite sets.

    But your logic can't handle an infinite union, as it can never complete
    the process.


    WIth infinity, Any and All are different qualifiers.

    Use them to increase your qualification.

    Why, I understand the differences. You seem to not, and thus make your
    errors and have exploded your mind with the contradictions.


    Regards, WM



    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Mon Nov 25 13:08:48 2024
    On 11/25/2024 7:11 AM, WM wrote:
    On 24.11.2024 19:16, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/24/2024 6:06 AM, WM wrote:
    On 24.11.2024 06:37, Jim Burns wrote:

    Consider the set of natural numbers for which
    there are NOT enough hats.

    It is dark.

    It is not dark what we mean by 'natural number'.
    A natural number is countable.to from.0

    That is a definable number.

    Thus
    it is not dark that
    what we mean by 'natural number' is
    countable.to from.0 and is
    what you call a definable number.

    ----
    Therefore,
    the number G^G^G is not.first for which
    there are NOT enough hats.

    We do not disagree.
    Therefore you need not
    prove a difference for G and G^G^G.

    A similar argument can be made for
    each natural number.

    No,
    it can be made for each definable natural number,

    We agree.
    A similar argument can be made for each
    definable countable.to.from.0 what.we.call
    natural.number.

    ⎛ For each
    ⎜ definable countable.to.from.0 what.we.call
    ⎜ natural.number k
    ⎜ k is countable.past (k+1 exists)
    ⎜ k is countable.to (k-1 exists or k=0)
    ⎜ Each split of sequence ⟦0,k⟧ is countable.across
    ⎝ (i is last.before, j is first.after, i+1=j)

    it can be made for each definable natural number,
    i.e., for a number belonging to
    a tiny finite initial segment which is followed bay
    almost all numbers.

    No. The
    definable countable.to.from.0 what.we.call
    natural.numbers
    can each be counted.past (k+1 exists)
    are each not a second end
    are not two.ended
    are infinitely.many.

    That is 'infinitely.many' which can be ordered
    with any non.empty.subset less.than.two.ended.
    It is 'infinitely.many' which has
    fundamentally different behavior.
    It is 'infinitely.many' which Bob to disappear
    with enough room.swapping _inside_ the Hotel.

    It is not your 'infinitely.many' which is merely
    exceedingly.many.but.finite.

    a tiny finite initial segment which is followed bay
    almost all numbers.

    Each
    definable countable.to.from.0 what.we.call
    natural.number
    is followed by almost all
    definable countable.to.from.0 what.we.call
    natural.numbers.

    They are not exceedingly.many.but.finite.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From joes@21:1/5 to All on Mon Nov 25 21:05:14 2024
    Am Mon, 25 Nov 2024 13:18:28 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 24.11.2024 20:14, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/24/24 12:32 PM, WM wrote:

    The finite sets contain all hats because all natural numbers and all
    10n are in finite sets. No hat is outside.>
    Not all, but every.
    But there is no finite set with ALL natural numbers.
    Like usual, you mess up with your qualifiers.
    ℕ is fixed, that means |ℕ| is fixed.
    What does that have to do with it?

    Limit theory only works if the limit actually exists
    If limits exist at all, then the limit of the sequence 1/10, 1/10,
    1/10, ... does exist.
    But the concept of 1/10th of an infinte set does not exist..
    It does.
    It has the same cardinality.

    You can get things that APPEAR to reach a limit, but actually don't.
    But if infinite sets do exist, then the set ℕ does exist, and all its
    elements are members of finite intervals (0, n].
    No, any given element is a member of a finite set, but you can't then
    say that ALL are in such a set.
    All are in the union of all finite sets.
    Why not just directly take N, made up of finite numbers?

    WIth infinity, Any and All are different qualifiers.
    Use them to increase your qualification.
    *quantifiers

    --
    Am Sat, 20 Jul 2024 12:35:31 +0000 schrieb WM in sci.math:
    It is not guaranteed that n+1 exists for every n.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From joes@21:1/5 to like he on Mon Nov 25 21:13:35 2024
    Am Mon, 25 Nov 2024 13:11:26 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 24.11.2024 19:16, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/23/2024 3:45 PM, WM wrote:

    for every interval (0,n]
    the relative covering is 1/10,
    independent of how the hats are shifted. This cannot be remedied in
    the infinite limit because outside of all finite intervals (0, n]
    there are no further hats available.

    All the hats for which
     if there are G.many then there are G^G^G.many
    are enough to "remedy" the 1/10.relative.covering

    Not at all!
    If each G can match G^G^G
    That is a false assumption.
    If there are enough hats to cover G then there are enough hats to cover G^G^G. G does not cover G^G^G.
    Matching a proper subset is the sort of behavior which permits Bob to
    disappear with enough room swapping _inside_ the Hotel.
    You (WM) treat that behavior as proof that we are wrong and you (WM)
    are right.
    Exchange of two elements never leads to loss of one of them.
    That's still true in the infinite case.

    What it is  is proof that not all sets behave like finite sets.
    Nonsense. Logic is also prevailing in infinite sets.
    Infinite sets are not finite.

    If there are enough hats for G natural numbers,
    then there are also enough for G^G^G natural numbers.
    The number G^G^G is not.first for which there are NOT enough hats.
    There is no such number because the set of definable hats is potentially infinite.
    Right!

    Therefore,
    the number G^G^G is not.first for which there are NOT enough hats.
    We do not disagree. Therefore you need not prove a difference for G and G^G^G.
    Nor for G and 10G.

    A similar argument can be made for each natural number.
    No, it can be made for each definable natural number, i.e., for a number belonging to a tiny finite initial segment which is followed bay almost
    all numbers.
    Yes, like he said: for every natural.

    Consider the set of natural numbers for which there are NOT enough
    hats.
    It is dark.
    It is not dark what we mean by 'natural number'.
    A natural number is countable to from 0.
    That is a definable number.
    Yes, the naturals are all "definable". That is all mathematicians talk
    about, so you can just imagine they always mean your "N_def" when they
    say N.

    The natural numbers "fail" at being finitely many.
    It is nothing more than that.
    If they are infinitely many but complete, then they and their number
    don't vary. |ℕ| - 1 < |ℕ| < |ℕ| + 1.
    What would it even mean for the naturals to not be "complete"? Either
    you have the whole set or you don't.

    --
    Am Sat, 20 Jul 2024 12:35:31 +0000 schrieb WM in sci.math:
    It is not guaranteed that n+1 exists for every n.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Tue Nov 26 10:06:12 2024
    On 25.11.2024 19:08, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/25/2024 7:11 AM, WM wrote:
    On 24.11.2024 19:16, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/24/2024 6:06 AM, WM wrote:
    On 24.11.2024 06:37, Jim Burns wrote:

    Consider the set of natural numbers for which
    there are NOT enough hats.

    It is dark.

    It is not dark what we mean by 'natural number'.
    A natural number is countable.to from.0

    That is a definable number.

    Thus
    it is not dark that
    what we mean by 'natural number' is
    countable.to from.0  and is
    what you call a definable number.

    Consider the black hats at every 10 n and white hats at all other
    numbers n. It is possible to shift the black hats such that every
    interval (0, n] is completely covered by black hats. There is no first n discernible that cannot be covered by black hat. But the origin of each
    used black hat larger than n is now covered by a white hat. Without
    deleting all white hats it is not possible to cover all n by black hats.
    But deleting white hats is prohibited by logic. Exchanging can never
    delete one of the exchanged elements. Therefore we have here, like in
    all Cantor-pairings, the same impediment and further disussion is
    futile: You must deny logic. I do not.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Richard Damon on Tue Nov 26 09:52:26 2024
    On 25.11.2024 18:52, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/25/24 7:18 AM, WM wrote:


    All are in the union of all finite sets.

    But your logic can't handle an infinite union, as it can never complete
    the process.

    The process is completed. Otherwise no Cantor bijection could exist.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to joes on Tue Nov 26 10:11:22 2024
    On 25.11.2024 22:05, joes wrote:
    Am Mon, 25 Nov 2024 13:18:28 +0100 schrieb WM:

    But there is no finite set with ALL natural numbers.
    Like usual, you mess up with your qualifiers.
    ℕ is fixed, that means |ℕ| is fixed.
    What does that have to do with it?

    It is impossible to add or to delete an element.
    It is impossible to change |ℕ| by 1 or more.

    Limit theory only works if the limit actually exists
    If limits exist at all, then the limit of the sequence 1/10, 1/10,
    1/10, ... does exist.
    But the concept of 1/10th of an infinte set does not exist..
    It does.
    It has the same cardinality.

    Yes, it is much.

    You can get things that APPEAR to reach a limit, but actually don't.
    But if infinite sets do exist, then the set ℕ does exist, and all its >>>> elements are members of finite intervals (0, n].
    No, any given element is a member of a finite set, but you can't then
    say that ALL are in such a set.
    All are in the union of all finite sets.
    Why not just directly take N, made up of finite numbers?

    Why not? Do it. Consider the black hats at every 10 n and white hats at
    all other numbers n. It is possible to shift the black hats such that
    every interval (0, n] is completely covered by black hats. There is no
    first n discernible that cannot be covered by black hat. But the origin
    of each used black hat larger than n is now covered by a white hat.
    Without deleting all white hats it is not possible to cover all n by
    black hats. But deleting white hats is prohibited by logic. Exchanging
    can never delete one of the exchanged elements. Therefore we have here,
    like in all Cantor-pairings, the same impediment and further disussion
    is futile: You must deny logic. I do not.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From joes@21:1/5 to All on Tue Nov 26 10:10:36 2024
    Am Tue, 26 Nov 2024 10:11:22 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 25.11.2024 22:05, joes wrote:
    Am Mon, 25 Nov 2024 13:18:28 +0100 schrieb WM:

    But there is no finite set with ALL natural numbers.
    Like usual, you mess up with your qualifiers.
    ℕ is fixed, that means |ℕ| is fixed.
    What does that have to do with it?
    It is impossible to add or to delete an element.
    It is impossible to change |ℕ| by 1 or more.
    It is possible to change N to N\0.
    How does that relate to all infinitely many naturals being finite?

    Limit theory only works if the limit actually exists
    If limits exist at all, then the limit of the sequence 1/10, 1/10,
    1/10, ... does exist.
    But the concept of 1/10th of an infinte set does not exist..
    It does.
    It has the same cardinality.
    Yes, it is much.
    Countably infinite.

    You can get things that APPEAR to reach a limit, but actually
    don't.
    But if infinite sets do exist, then the set ℕ does exist, and all
    its elements are members of finite intervals (0, n].
    No, any given element is a member of a finite set, but you can't then
    say that ALL are in such a set.
    All are in the union of all finite sets.
    Why not just directly take N, made up of finite numbers?
    Why not? Do it. Consider the black hats at every 10 n and white hats at
    all other numbers n. It is possible to shift the black hats such that
    every interval (0, n] is completely covered by black hats. There is no
    first n discernible that cannot be covered by black hat.
    Cantor proved nothing more.

    But the origin
    of each used black hat larger than n is now covered by a white hat.
    Not if you really coloured ALL n.

    Without deleting all white hats it is not possible to cover all n by
    black hats. But deleting white hats is prohibited by logic. Exchanging
    can never delete one of the exchanged elements.
    An infinite exchange can.

    Therefore we have here,
    like in all Cantor-pairings, the same impediment and further disussion
    is futile.
    Thanks for shutting up.

    --
    Am Sat, 20 Jul 2024 12:35:31 +0000 schrieb WM in sci.math:
    It is not guaranteed that n+1 exists for every n.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to joes on Tue Nov 26 11:22:30 2024
    On 26.11.2024 11:10, joes wrote:
    Am Tue, 26 Nov 2024 10:11:22 +0100 schrieb WM:

    Exchanging
    can never delete one of the exchanged elements.
    An infinite exchange can.

    No.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to FromTheRafters on Tue Nov 26 13:06:16 2024
    On 26.11.2024 12:19, FromTheRafters wrote:

    How much paint would be needed to paint the entire cartesian plane?

    1 liter!

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to FromTheRafters on Tue Nov 26 12:52:04 2024
    On 26.11.2024 12:19, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM laid this down on his screen :

    Consider the black hats at every 10 n and white hats at all other
    numbers n. It is possible to shift the black hats such that every
    interval (0, n] is completely covered by black hats. There is no first
    n discernible that cannot be covered by  black hat. But the origin of
    each used black hat larger than n is now covered by a white hat.
    Without deleting all white hats it is not possible to cover all n by
    black hats. But deleting white hats is prohibited by logic. Exchanging
    can never delete one of the exchanged elements. Therefore we have
    here, like in all Cantor-pairings, the same impediment and further
    disussion is futile: You must deny logic. I do not.

    How much paint would be needed to paint the entire cartesian plane?

    If the plane exists, then the paint exists.

    Too
    much huh? then just paint the first quadrant with one quarter the amount
    of paint. Your 'logic' is too easily denied.

    You have not discussed it.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to FromTheRafters on Tue Nov 26 12:24:29 2024
    On 26.11.2024 12:15, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM pretended :

    It is impossible to change |ℕ| by 1 or more.

    Right, sets don't change. The set {2,3,4,...} does not equal the set of natural numbers, but |{2,3,4,...}| does equal |N|.

    Then your |N| is an imprecise measure. My |N| is precise.
    |{2,3,4,...}| = |N| - 1 =/= |N| .

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Tue Nov 26 10:06:15 2024
    On 11/26/24 6:24 AM, WM wrote:
    On 26.11.2024 12:15, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM pretended :

    It is impossible to change |ℕ| by 1 or more.

    Right, sets don't change. The set {2,3,4,...} does not equal the set
    of natural numbers, but |{2,3,4,...}| does equal |N|.

    Then your |N| is an imprecise measure. My |N| is precise.
    |{2,3,4,...}| = |N| - 1 =/= |N| .

    Regards, WM




    Then your measure is incorrect, as by the DEFINITION of measures of
    infinite sets, all countably infinite sets have the same "measure".

    The proble is you believe in logic system that are inconsistant and thus
    have blown themselves up in contradictions.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Tue Nov 26 12:50:25 2024
    On 11/26/24 11:59 AM, WM wrote:
    On 26.11.2024 16:06, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/26/24 6:24 AM, WM wrote:
    On 26.11.2024 12:15, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM pretended :

    It is impossible to change |ℕ| by 1 or more.

    Right, sets don't change. The set {2,3,4,...} does not equal the set
    of natural numbers, but |{2,3,4,...}| does equal |N|.

    Then your |N| is an imprecise measure. My |N| is precise.
    |{2,3,4,...}| = |N| - 1 =/= |N| .

    Then your measure is incorrect, as by the DEFINITION of measures of
    infinite sets, all countably infinite sets have the same "measure".

    That is one special definition of a very imprecise measure. We can do
    better.

    Regards, WM


    But maybe you can't and get something consistant.

    Sorry, you are just showing that you don't know what you are doing,
    because your mind just can't handle the actual concept of an actually
    infinite set.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Richard Damon on Tue Nov 26 17:59:40 2024
    On 26.11.2024 16:06, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/26/24 6:24 AM, WM wrote:
    On 26.11.2024 12:15, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM pretended :

    It is impossible to change |ℕ| by 1 or more.

    Right, sets don't change. The set {2,3,4,...} does not equal the set
    of natural numbers, but |{2,3,4,...}| does equal |N|.

    Then your |N| is an imprecise measure. My |N| is precise.
    |{2,3,4,...}| = |N| - 1 =/= |N| .

    Then your measure is incorrect, as by the DEFINITION of measures of
    infinite sets, all countably infinite sets have the same "measure".

    That is one special definition of a very imprecise measure. We can do
    better.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Richard Damon on Wed Nov 27 11:12:46 2024
    On 26.11.2024 18:50, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/26/24 11:59 AM, WM wrote:
    On 26.11.2024 16:06, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/26/24 6:24 AM, WM wrote:
    On 26.11.2024 12:15, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM pretended :

    It is impossible to change |ℕ| by 1 or more.

    Right, sets don't change. The set {2,3,4,...} does not equal the
    set of natural numbers, but |{2,3,4,...}| does equal |N|.

    Then your |N| is an imprecise measure. My |N| is precise.
    |{2,3,4,...}| = |N| - 1 =/= |N| .

    Then your measure is incorrect, as by the DEFINITION of measures of
    infinite sets, all countably infinite sets have the same "measure".

    That is one special definition of a very imprecise measure. We can do
    better.

    But maybe you can't and get something consistant.

    Of course. |{1, 2, 3, 4, ...}| = |ℕ| and |{2, 3, 4, ...}| = |ℕ| - 1 is consistent.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Wed Nov 27 07:32:01 2024
    On 11/27/24 5:12 AM, WM wrote:
    On 26.11.2024 18:50, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/26/24 11:59 AM, WM wrote:
    On 26.11.2024 16:06, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/26/24 6:24 AM, WM wrote:
    On 26.11.2024 12:15, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM pretended :

    It is impossible to change |ℕ| by 1 or more.

    Right, sets don't change. The set {2,3,4,...} does not equal the
    set of natural numbers, but |{2,3,4,...}| does equal |N|.

    Then your |N| is an imprecise measure. My |N| is precise.
    |{2,3,4,...}| = |N| - 1 =/= |N| .

    Then your measure is incorrect, as by the DEFINITION of measures of
    infinite sets, all countably infinite sets have the same "measure".

    That is one special definition of a very imprecise measure. We can do
    better.

    But maybe you can't and get something consistant.

    Of course. |{1, 2, 3, 4, ...}| = |ℕ| and |{2, 3, 4, ...}| = |ℕ| - 1 is consistent.

    Regards, WM



    So you think, but that is because you brain has been exploded by the contradiction.

    We can get to your second set two ways, and the set itself can't know which.

    We could have built the set by the operation of removing 1 like your
    math implies, or we can get to it by the operation of increasing each
    element by its successor, which must have the same number of elements,
    so we prove that in your logic |ℕ| - 1 == |ℕ|, which is one of Cantor's claim, and what you want to refute, but comes out of your "logic"

    So saying that |ℕ| -1 is different than |ℕ| just makes your logic inconsistant.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Richard Damon on Wed Nov 27 18:13:06 2024
    On 27.11.2024 13:32, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/27/24 5:12 AM, WM wrote:

    Of course. |{1, 2, 3, 4, ...}| = |ℕ| and |{2, 3, 4, ...}| = |ℕ| - 1 is >> consistent.

    So you think, but that is because you brain has been exploded by the contradiction.

    We can get to your second set two ways, and the set itself can't know
    which.

    We could have built the set by the operation of removing 1 like your
    math implies, or we can get to it by the operation of increasing each
    element by its successor, which must have the same number of elements,

    Yes, the same number of elements, but not the same number of natural
    numbers.

    Hint: Decreasing every element in the real interval (0, 1] by one point
    yields the real interval [0, 1). The set of points remains the same, the
    set of positive points decreases by 1.

    Replacing every element of the set {0, 1, 2, 3, ...} by its successor
    yields {1, 2, 3, ..., ω}. The number of ordinals remains the same, the
    number of finite ordinals decreases.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From joes@21:1/5 to All on Wed Nov 27 18:02:15 2024
    Am Wed, 27 Nov 2024 18:13:06 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 27.11.2024 13:32, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/27/24 5:12 AM, WM wrote:

    Of course. |{1, 2, 3, 4, ...}| = |ℕ| and |{2, 3, 4, ...}| = |ℕ| - 1 is >>> consistent.

    So you think, but that is because you brain has been exploded by the
    contradiction.
    We can get to your second set two ways, and the set itself can't know
    which.
    We could have built the set by the operation of removing 1 like your
    math implies, or we can get to it by the operation of increasing each
    element by its successor, which must have the same number of elements,

    Yes, the same number of elements, but not the same number of natural
    numbers.
    Decreasing every element in the real interval (0, 1] by one point
    yields the real interval [0, 1). The set of points remains the same, the
    set of positive points decreases by 1.
    What is "decreasing by a point"?

    Replacing every element of the set {0, 1, 2, 3, ...} by its successor
    yields {1, 2, 3, ..., ω}. The number of ordinals remains the same, the number of finite ordinals decreases.
    There is no natural whose successor is omega.

    --
    Am Sat, 20 Jul 2024 12:35:31 +0000 schrieb WM in sci.math:
    It is not guaranteed that n+1 exists for every n.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Wed Nov 27 12:58:15 2024
    On 11/27/24 12:13 PM, WM wrote:
    On 27.11.2024 13:32, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/27/24 5:12 AM, WM wrote:

    Of course. |{1, 2, 3, 4, ...}| = |ℕ| and |{2, 3, 4, ...}| = |ℕ| - 1
    is consistent.

    So you think, but that is because you brain has been exploded by the
    contradiction.

    We can get to your second set two ways, and the set itself can't know
    which.

    We could have built the set by the operation of removing 1 like your
    math implies, or we can get to it by the operation of increasing each
    element by its successor, which must have the same number of elements,

    Yes, the same number of elements, but not the same number of natural
    numbers.


    Of course they are, if n is a Natural Number, Sn (S being the Successor operator) is also one.

    Hint: Decreasing every element in the real interval (0, 1] by one point yields the real interval [0, 1). The set of points remains the same, the
    set of positive points decreases by 1.

    But what number changes "natural number" status?


    Replacing every element of the set {0, 1, 2, 3, ...} by its successor
    yields {1, 2, 3, ..., ω}. The number of ordinals remains the same, the number of finite ordinals decreases.

    Nope, because omega is NOT the successor for any natural number, the
    successor of EVERY Natural Number is a Natural Number.

    Defintions you know.

    It it the successor for the SET of natural numbers.


    Regards, WM

    So, you are just showing your ignorance of the definitions things you
    are talking about, because you are using a logic that has gone
    inconsistent and blown up your brain.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Richard Damon on Wed Nov 27 20:15:34 2024
    On 27.11.2024 18:58, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/27/24 12:13 PM, WM wrote:

    Replacing every element of the set {0, 1, 2, 3, ...} by its successor
    yields {1, 2, 3, ..., ω}. The number of ordinals remains the same, the
    number of finite ordinals decreases.

    Nope, because omega is NOT the successor for any natural number, the successor of EVERY Natural Number is a Natural Number.

    The successor of the last natural number is ω.

    It it the successor for the SET of natural numbers.

    And that is nothing else but all natural numbers.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to joes on Wed Nov 27 20:19:37 2024
    On 27.11.2024 19:02, joes wrote:
    Am Wed, 27 Nov 2024 18:13:06 +0100 schrieb WM:

    Decreasing every element in the real interval (0, 1] by one point
    yields the real interval [0, 1). The set of points remains the same, the
    set of positive points decreases by 1.
    What is "decreasing by a point"?

    That can only be performed for half-open intervals because most points
    are dark.

    Replacing every element of the set {0, 1, 2, 3, ...} by its successor
    yields {1, 2, 3, ..., ω}. The number of ordinals remains the same, the
    number of finite ordinals decreases.
    There is no natural whose successor is omega.

    If there is nothing between ℕ and ω, then replacing every element of the
    set {0, 1, 2, 3, ...} by its successor yields {1, 2, 3, ..., ω}.

    Regards, WM


    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to FromTheRafters on Wed Nov 27 20:25:45 2024
    On 27.11.2024 19:19, FromTheRafters wrote:
    WM explained :
    On 27.11.2024 13:32, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/27/24 5:12 AM, WM wrote:

    Of course. |{1, 2, 3, 4, ...}| = |ℕ| and |{2, 3, 4, ...}| = |ℕ| - 1 >>>> is consistent.

    So you think, but that is because you brain has been exploded by the
    contradiction.

    We can get to your second set two ways, and the set itself can't know
    which.

    We could have built the set by the operation of removing 1 like your
    math implies, or we can get to it by the operation of increasing each
    element by its successor, which must have the same number of elements,

    Yes, the same number of elements, but not the same number of natural
    numbers.

    Hint: Decreasing every element in the real interval (0, 1] by one
    point yields the real interval [0, 1). The set of points remains the
    same, the set of positive points decreases by 1.

    If you have a successor function for the real numbers, why don't you
    share it with the rest of the world?

    I don't because almost all real numbers are dark. Nevertheless we know
    that the interval (0, 1] contains all small positive numbers. Hence
    shifting it by 1 point we get [0, 1).

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Wed Nov 27 14:47:06 2024
    On 11/27/2024 12:13 PM, WM wrote:
    On 27.11.2024 13:32, Richard Damon wrote:

    [...]

    Yes, the same number of elements,
    but not the same number of natural numbers.

    A finite cardinal can change by 1
    ⎛ Finite cardinal Ψ requires the existence of
    ⎝ finite cardinals Ψ+1 Ψ-1 which aren't Ψ

    ℕᶠⁱⁿ is the set of finite cardinals.

    For each finite cardinal Ψ in ℕᶠⁱⁿ
    ⎛ ℕᶠⁱⁿ has subset |⟦0,Ψ-1⟧| = Ψ
    ⎜ ℕᶠⁱⁿ has subset |⟦0,Ψ⟧| = Ψ+1 > Ψ
    ⎜ |ℕᶠⁱⁿ| ≥ |⟦0,Ψ⟧| = Ψ+1 > Ψ
    ⎝ |ℕᶠⁱⁿ| ≠ Ψ

    |ℕᶠⁱⁿ| isn't any finite cardinal.
    Finite cardinals can change by 1
    The cardinal |ℕᶠⁱⁿ| cannot change by 1

    Yes,
    the sets can change membership by 1
    (for a different set)
    ℕᶠⁱⁿ ≠ Eᶠⁱⁿ(1) ≠ Eᶠⁱⁿ(2) ≠ Eᶠⁱⁿ(3) ≠ ...

    However,
    the cardinalities of those sets cannot change by 1
    |ℕᶠⁱⁿ| = |Eᶠⁱⁿ(1)| = |Eᶠⁱⁿ(2)| = |Eᶠⁱⁿ(3)| = ...

    ℕᶠⁱⁿ, Eᶠⁱⁿ(1), Eᶠⁱⁿ(2), Eᶠⁱⁿ(3), ...
    are infinite sets,
    NOT darkly.large.but.countable.to sets.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Wed Nov 27 21:36:09 2024
    Am 27.11.2024 um 21:28 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:
    On 11/27/2024 11:15 AM, WM wrote:
    On 27.11.2024 18:58, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/27/24 12:13 PM, WM wrote:

    Replacing every element of the set {0, 1, 2, 3, ...} by its
    successor yields {1, 2, 3, ..., ω}.

    Holy shit!

    Nein, Mückenheim!

    {n' : n e IN u {0}} = IN

    und bekanntlich ist ω nicht e IN u {0} also auch nicht e IN. <facepalm>

    Du bist wirklich dümmer als die Polizei erlaubt!

    Hinweis: ~En e IN u {0}: n' = ω.

    Nope, [...] the successor of EVERY natural number is a natural number
    [hence] omega is NOT the successor for any natural number

    Jep. Indeed!

    The successor of the last natural number is ω.

    Mückenheim, geh doch endlich mal zu einem Psychiater!

    There is no last natural number you fucking dipshit!

    Yeah.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Wed Nov 27 16:14:21 2024
    On 11/27/24 2:15 PM, WM wrote:
    On 27.11.2024 18:58, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/27/24 12:13 PM, WM wrote:

    Replacing every element of the set {0, 1, 2, 3, ...} by its successor
    yields {1, 2, 3, ..., ω}. The number of ordinals remains the same,
    the number of finite ordinals decreases.

    Nope, because omega is NOT the successor for any natural number, the
    successor of EVERY Natural Number is a Natural Number.

    The successor of the last natural number is ω.

    But there isn't a last natural number, if there was, there would only be
    a finite number of them.

    That is what breaks your logic, you just can't handle the infinite.


    It it the successor for the SET of natural numbers.

    And that is nothing else but all natural numbers.

    No, the set is different from its members.

    OI guess you logic is based on the proven inconsistant naive set theory
    which is why it gets so must worng.


    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From joes@21:1/5 to All on Wed Nov 27 21:47:29 2024
    Am Wed, 27 Nov 2024 22:43:11 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 27.11.2024 22:14, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/27/24 2:15 PM, WM wrote:

    It it the successor for the SET of natural numbers.
    And that is nothing else but all natural numbers.
    No, the set is different from its members.
    By what?
    By itself.

    --
    Am Sat, 20 Jul 2024 12:35:31 +0000 schrieb WM in sci.math:
    It is not guaranteed that n+1 exists for every n.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Wed Nov 27 22:33:06 2024
    On 27.11.2024 20:47, Jim Burns wrote:

    Finite cardinals can change by 1
    The cardinal |ℕᶠⁱⁿ| cannot change by 1

    Small wonder. Fuzzy properties like "many" cannot change by 1.

    Yes,
    the sets can change membership by 1

    However,
    the cardinalities of those sets cannot change by 1

    This proves that cardinality is a fuzzy property.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Richard Damon on Wed Nov 27 22:43:11 2024
    On 27.11.2024 22:14, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/27/24 2:15 PM, WM wrote:

    It it the successor for the SET of natural numbers.

    And that is nothing else but all natural numbers.

    No, the set is different from its members.

    By what?

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Wed Nov 27 19:31:18 2024
    On 11/27/24 4:33 PM, WM wrote:
    On 27.11.2024 20:47, Jim Burns wrote:

    Finite cardinals can change by 1
    The cardinal |ℕᶠⁱⁿ| cannot change by 1

    Small wonder. Fuzzy properties like "many" cannot change by 1.

    Yes,
    the sets can change membership by 1

    However,
    the cardinalities of those sets cannot change by 1

    This proves that cardinality is a fuzzy property.

    Regards, WM

    No, it shows that infinite values act differently than finite numbers.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Wed Nov 27 19:30:39 2024
    On 11/27/24 4:43 PM, WM wrote:
    On 27.11.2024 22:14, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/27/24 2:15 PM, WM wrote:

    It it the successor for the SET of natural numbers.

    And that is nothing else but all natural numbers.

    No, the set is different from its members.

    By what?

    Regards, WM



    It is a set, with set type properties, and its members are Natural
    Numbers, with Natural Number like propertis.

    The set is equal to N, which is the name of the set, but none of the
    members are 'equal' to N, they are MEMBERS of it.

    You are just showing your ignorance.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Richard Damon on Thu Nov 28 11:14:10 2024
    On 28.11.2024 01:31, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/27/24 4:33 PM, WM wrote:
    On 27.11.2024 20:47, Jim Burns wrote:

    Finite cardinals can change by 1
    The cardinal |ℕᶠⁱⁿ| cannot change by 1

    Small wonder. Fuzzy properties like "many" cannot change by 1.

    Yes,
    the sets can change membership by 1

    However,
    the cardinalities of those sets cannot change by 1

    This proves that cardinality is a fuzzy property.

    No, it shows that infinite values act differently than finite numbers.

    They do not act but are described. Blind men use fuzzy measured, seeing
    men use precise measures.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Richard Damon on Thu Nov 28 11:09:53 2024
    On 28.11.2024 01:30, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/27/24 4:43 PM, WM wrote:
    On 27.11.2024 22:14, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/27/24 2:15 PM, WM wrote:

    It it the successor for the SET of natural numbers.

    And that is nothing else but all natural numbers.

    No, the set is different from its members.

    By what?

    It is a set, with set type properties, and its members are Natural
    Numbers, with Natural Number like propertis.

    The set is equal to N, which is the name of the set, but none of the
    members are 'equal' to N, they are MEMBERS of it.

    The members together are ℕ.
    The collection of definable natnumbers is ℕ_def.
    The collection of all natnumbers is ℕ.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Thu Nov 28 08:00:38 2024
    On 11/28/24 5:14 AM, WM wrote:
    On 28.11.2024 01:31, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/27/24 4:33 PM, WM wrote:
    On 27.11.2024 20:47, Jim Burns wrote:

    Finite cardinals can change by 1
    The cardinal |ℕᶠⁱⁿ| cannot change by 1

    Small wonder. Fuzzy properties like "many" cannot change by 1.

    Yes,
    the sets can change membership by 1

    However,
    the cardinalities of those sets cannot change by 1

    This proves that cardinality is a fuzzy property.

    No, it shows that infinite values act differently than finite numbers.

    They do not act but are described. Blind men use fuzzy measured, seeing
    men use precise measures.

    Regards, WM


    And stupid people like you use contradictory logic based on undefined
    terms, so you actual see nothing but the darkness of the void created by
    your logic.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Thu Nov 28 07:56:44 2024
    On 11/28/24 5:09 AM, WM wrote:
    On 28.11.2024 01:30, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/27/24 4:43 PM, WM wrote:
    On 27.11.2024 22:14, Richard Damon wrote:
    On 11/27/24 2:15 PM, WM wrote:

    It it the successor for the SET of natural numbers.

    And that is nothing else but all natural numbers.

    No, the set is different from its members.

    By what?

    It is a set, with set type properties, and its members are Natural
    Numbers, with Natural Number like propertis.

    The set is equal to N, which is the name of the set, but none of the
    members are 'equal' to N, they are MEMBERS of it.

    The members together are ℕ.
    The collection of definable natnumbers is ℕ_def.
    The collection of all natnumbers is ℕ.

    Regards, WM

    But since all the members of N are definable, your N_def actually is N.

    Now, if you are crippled enough in your logic that keeps you from
    understanding big numbers, so you think your N_def is something else,
    that is just on you, and not a problem with the Natural Numbers.

    All you have shown is that your logic of finite numbers can not handle
    the actual infinite set of Natural Numbers, or even actually define your
    finite subset of them N_def, so N_def is just itself a contradiction,
    which has blown your brain to smithereens with its contradictions.

    You are unable to actually DEFINE what your N_def actually is, making
    your logic just a lie.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Fri Nov 29 13:12:39 2024
    On 11/29/2024 1:08 PM, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/27/2024 4:33 PM, WM wrote:
    On 27.11.2024 20:47, Jim Burns wrote:

    Finite cardinals can change by 1
    The cardinal |ℕᶠⁱⁿ| cannot change by 1

    Small wonder.
    Fuzzy properties like "many" cannot change by 1.

    ⎛ ℕᶠⁱⁿ is the set of finite cardinals.
    ⎜ Bob is not a cardinal.

    ⎜ ∀ᶜᵃʳᵈξ:  ξ ∈ ℕᶠⁱⁿ  ⇔
    ⎜ ⟦0,ξ⦆∪{Bob} ≠ ⟦0,ξ⟧  ∧  |⟦0,ξ⦆∪{Bob}| ≠ |⟦0,ξ⟧|

    ⎝ ℕᶠⁱⁿ∪{Bob} ≠ ℕᶠⁱⁿ  ∧  |ℕᶠⁱⁿ∪{Bob}| = |ℕᶠⁱⁿ|

    Dammit. Someone fire the editor.
    Better:

    ⎛ ℕᶠⁱⁿ is the set of finite cardinals.
    ⎜ Bob is not a cardinal.

    ⎜ ∀ᶜᵃʳᵈξ: ξ ∈ ℕᶠⁱⁿ ⇔
    ⎜ ⟦0,ξ⦆∪{Bob} ≠ ⟦0,ξ⦆ ∧ |⟦0,ξ⦆∪{Bob}| ≠ |⟦0,ξ⦆|

    ⎝ ℕᶠⁱⁿ∪{Bob} ≠ ℕᶠⁱⁿ ∧ |ℕᶠⁱⁿ∪{Bob}| = |ℕᶠⁱⁿ|

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Fri Nov 29 13:08:59 2024
    On 11/27/2024 4:33 PM, WM wrote:
    On 27.11.2024 20:47, Jim Burns wrote:

    Finite cardinals can change by 1
    The cardinal |ℕᶠⁱⁿ| cannot change by 1

    Small wonder.
    Fuzzy properties like "many" cannot change by 1.

    ⎛ ℕᶠⁱⁿ is the set of finite cardinals.
    ⎜ Bob is not a cardinal.

    ⎜ ∀ᶜᵃʳᵈξ: ξ ∈ ℕᶠⁱⁿ ⇔
    ⎜ ⟦0,ξ⦆∪{Bob} ≠ ⟦0,ξ⟧ ∧ |⟦0,ξ⦆∪{Bob}| ≠ |⟦0,ξ⟧|

    ⎝ ℕᶠⁱⁿ∪{Bob} ≠ ℕᶠⁱⁿ ∧ |ℕᶠⁱⁿ∪{Bob}| = |ℕᶠⁱⁿ|

    Yes,
    the sets can change membership by 1
    However,
    the cardinalities of those sets cannot change by 1

    This proves that cardinality is a fuzzy property.

    The whole ℕᶠⁱⁿ×ℕᶠⁱⁿ matrix can fit in
    its first column ℕᶠⁱⁿ×{0}

    ⎛ ℕᶠⁱⁿ×ℕᶠⁱⁿ ⇉ ℕᶠⁱⁿ×{0} ⇉ ℕᶠⁱⁿ×ℕᶠⁱⁿ
    ⎜ ⟨i,j⟩ ↦ ⟨n,0⟩ ↦ ⟨i,j⟩
    ⎜ n = (i+j)⋅(i+j+1)/2+j
    ⎜ (i+j) = ⌊(2⋅n+¼)¹ᐟ²-½⌋
    ⎜ j = n-(i+j)⋅((i+j)+1)/2
    ⎝ i = (i+j)-j

    The fuzzy cardinality property
    predicts that it can.
    Your crisp cardinoid property
    predicts otherwise
    and is incorrect.

    After all the swaps
    (of which no swap is a change in cardinality)
    what remains is a proper subset
    (which is not a change in cardinality).

    'Bye, Bob.

    This proves that cardinality is a fuzzy property.


    ⎜ An hungry Fox with fierce attack
    ⎜ Sprang on a Vine, but tumbled back,
    ⎜ Nor could attain the point in view,
    ⎜ So near the sky the bunches grew.
    ⎜ As he went off, "They're scurvy stuff,"
    ⎜ Says he, "and not half ripe enough--
    ⎜ And I 've more rev'rence for my tripes
    ⎜ Than to torment them with the gripes."
    ⎜ For those this tale is very pat
    ⎜ Who lessen what they can't come at.

    http://mythfolklore.net/aesopica/phaedrus/43.htm

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Fri Nov 29 20:37:24 2024
    On 29.11.2024 19:08, Jim Burns wrote:


    After all the swaps
     (of which no swap is a change in cardinality)
    what remains is a proper subset

    Not proper. No element can leave by swaps.

    (which is not a change in cardinality).

    Irrelevant. Cardinality is a fuzzy measure.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Fri Nov 29 15:54:59 2024
    On 11/29/2024 2:37 PM, WM wrote:
    On 29.11.2024 19:08, Jim Burns wrote:

    After all the swaps
     (of which no swap is a change in cardinality)
    what remains is a proper subset
    (which is not a change in cardinality).

    Not proper.

    Proper.
    The sets
    are larger than
    each cardinal which can change by 1
    have a cardinal which cannot change by 1

    The proper subset has the same cardinality.

    No element can leave by swaps.

    All the swaps match all the elelments of that set
    and all the elments of that proper subset.
    No elements leave.

     (which is not a change in cardinality).

    Irrelevant. Cardinality is a fuzzy measure.

    The whole ℕᶠⁱⁿ×ℕᶠⁱⁿ matrix can fit in
    its first column ℕᶠⁱⁿ×{0}

    The fuzzy cardinality property
    predicts that it can.
    Your crisp cardinoid property
    predicts otherwise
    and is incorrect.

    After all the swaps
    (of which no swap is a change in cardinality)
    what remains is a proper subset
    (which is not a change in cardinality).

    'Bye, Bob.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Fri Nov 29 22:29:46 2024
    On 29.11.2024 21:54, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/29/2024 2:37 PM, WM wrote:
    On 29.11.2024 19:08, Jim Burns wrote:

    JB contradicting himself:

    After all the swaps
    No elements leave.

    After all the swaps
    what remains is a proper subset.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Fri Nov 29 20:44:55 2024
    On 11/29/2024 4:29 PM, WM wrote:
    On 29.11.2024 21:54, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/29/2024 2:37 PM, WM wrote:
    On 29.11.2024 19:08, Jim Burns wrote:



    JB contradicting himself:

    After all the swaps
    (of which no swap is a change in cardinality)
    what remains is a proper subset
    (which is not a change in cardinality).

    I (JB) contradict the finiteness of
    the set of all finite cardinals.
    Nothing more than that.

    Change a set having a finite cardinality by 1.
    The new set has a changed cardinality.
    (This is essentially what 'finite cardinal' means).

    The set of finite cardinalities,
    for any finite cardinal,
    includes more than that cardinal.
    Each finite cardinal is not the one that set has.

    Change the set of finite cardinalities by 1.
    The new set has NOT changed cardinality.
    The sets do not have any of
    the cardinalities which would change.
    The sets have a different cardinality,
    one which does not change when the set changes.


    After all the swaps
    (of which no swap is a change in cardinality)
    what remains is a proper subset
    (which is not a change in cardinality).
    Because infinite.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Sat Nov 30 12:57:18 2024
    On 30.11.2024 02:44, Jim Burns wrote:

    The sets do not have any of
    the cardinalities which would change.
    The sets have a different cardinality,
     one which does not change when the set changes.

    Then the intersection which is infinite too remain infinite.

    After all the swaps
     (of which no swap is a change in cardinality)
    what remains is a proper subset
     (which is not a change in cardinality).
    Because infinite.

    Like the intersection.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Sat Nov 30 12:32:04 2024
    On 11/30/2024 6:57 AM, WM wrote:
    On 30.11.2024 02:44, Jim Burns wrote:

    The sets do not have any of
    the cardinalities which would change.
    The sets have a different cardinality,
     one which does not change when the set changes.

    Then the intersection which is infinite
    too remain infinite.

    About end segments of the finite cardinals:

    The new end.segment with one element removed
    has the same infinite cardinality ℵ₀

    That removed element
    is not in common with each end.segment
    is not.in the intersection of all.

    Again.
    A third end.segment, with another removed,
    has the same infinite cardinality ℵ₀

    Both removed elements
    are not in common with each end.segment
    are not.in the intersection of all.

    After all the finitely.ranked removals,
    each finitely.ranked finite.cardinal
    is not.in the intersection of all.
    All finite.cardinals are finitely.ranked.
    All are not.in.

    The intersection of all the end segments of
    the finite.cardinals
    contains only
    finite.cardinals which aren't finitely.ranked.

    There aren't any.
    The intersection of all is empty.

    After all the swaps
      (of which no swap is a change in cardinality)
    what remains is a proper subset
      (which is not a change in cardinality).
    Because infinite.

    Like the intersection.

    The intersection of a collection of end.segments
    is particular to that collection.
    The collection doesn't change.
    Each end.segment doesn't change.
    Each finite.cardinal doesn't change.

    However,
    we can consider other collections,
    other end.segments,
    other finite.cardinals.

    Like the intersection.

    Apparently, what you (WM) call "the intersection"
    is each of infinitely.many intersections,
    some infinite, some empty,
    "changing" from one to another,
    in a manner you accept or you do not accept.

    It's a mess, but it's your mess.
    Our sets do not change.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Sat Nov 30 20:07:52 2024
    On 30.11.2024 18:32, Jim Burns wrote:

    Apparently, what you (WM) call "the intersection"
    is each of infinitely.many intersections,

    and their limit.
    Our sets do not change.

    But there is a sequence of endsegments E(1), E(2), E(3), ...
    and a sequence of their intersections
    E(1), E(1)∩E(2), E(1)∩E(2)∩E(3), ... .
    Both are identical - from the first endsegment on until every existing endsegment.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Sat Nov 30 16:45:48 2024
    On 11/30/2024 2:07 PM, WM wrote:
    On 30.11.2024 18:32, Jim Burns wrote:

    Apparently, what you (WM) call "the intersection"
    is each of infinitely.many intersections,

    and their limit.

    some infinite, some empty,
    "changing" from one to another,
    in a manner you accept or you do not accept.

    The limit of
    all the end segments of the finite cardinals
    is one of those intersections.

    It is the set of common finite.cardinals,
    common to each end.segment, that is, their intersection.
    It is empty.

    Intersections of some other end.segment.collections
    are infinite. And still others also empty.

    Our sets do not change.

    But there is a sequence of endsegments
    E(1), E(2), E(3), ...

    With an empty set of common finite.cardinals.

    and a sequence of their intersections
    E(1), E(1)∩E(2), E(1)∩E(2)∩E(3), ... .

    With an empty set of common finite.cardinals.

    Both are identical -
    from the first endsegment
    on until every existing endsegment.

    Yes, they are identical. And identically empty.

    ----
    Consider a finite.cardinal ξ
    There are only finitely.many
    fore.segments ⟦0,β⟧ ⊆ ⟦0,ξ-1⟧ which ξ is not.in.
    There only finitely.many
    end.segments E(β+1) = ℕ\⟦0,β⟧ which ξ is in.

    Consider a collection Ends of end.segments.

    If Ends is an infinite collection,
    then
    ⎛ there are more end.segments in Ends
    ⎜ than there are end.segments holding ξ
    ⎜ ξ is not common to all end.segments in Ends
    ⎝ ξ is not.in ⋂Ends

    The same argument applies to each finite cardinal.
    If Ends is an infinite collection,
    then
    ⎛ Each finite.cardinal is not.in ⋂Ends
    ⎝ ⋂Ends = {}

    Each infinite collection of
    end.segments of
    finite.cardinals
    has an empty intersection.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Sat Nov 30 22:56:00 2024
    On 30.11.2024 22:45, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/30/2024 2:07 PM, WM wrote:

    But there is a sequence of endsegments
    E(1), E(2), E(3), ...

    With an empty set of common finite.cardinals.

    Inclusion monotony prevents an empty set of common finite cardinals
    without an empty endsegment. In non-empty endsegments there are common
    finite cardinals.

    and a sequence of their intersections
    E(1), E(1)∩E(2), E(1)∩E(2)∩E(3), ... .

    With an empty set of common finite.cardinals.

    Both are identical -
    from the first endsegment
    on until every existing endsegment.

    Yes, they are identical. And identically empty.

    You said that the endsegments are never empty.

    Each infinite collection of
     end.segments of
      finite.cardinals
    has an empty intersection.

    Because an infinite collection of endsegments requires infinitely many
    indices, that is all indices. As long as some contents n, n+1, n+2, ...
    is in endsegments, the indices reach only from 1 to n-1.

    Regards, WM



    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Sat Nov 30 18:34:56 2024
    On 11/30/2024 4:56 PM, WM wrote:
    On 30.11.2024 22:45, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/30/2024 2:07 PM, WM wrote:

    But there is a sequence of endsegments
    E(1), E(2), E(3), ...

    With an empty set of common finite.cardinals.

    Inclusion monotony prevents
    an empty set of common finite cardinals
    without an empty endsegment.

    No,
    inclusion.monotony does not prevent
    an empty set of common finite.ordinals
    without an empty end segment.

    For collection ENDS holding infinitely.many end.segments,
    each finite ordinal ξ
    ⎛ is not.in only finitely.many fore.segments ⟦0,β⟧ ⊆ ⟦0,ξ-1⟧
    ⎜ is in only finitely.many end.segments E(β+1) = ℕ\⟦0,β⟧
    ⎜ is in fewer.than.infinitely.many end.segments in ENDS
    ⎜ is not in common with each end segment in ENDS
    ⎝ is not in ⋂ENDS

    For a collection ENDS holding infinitely.many end.segments,
    ⎛ each finite ordinal ξ is not in ⋂ENDS
    ⎝ ⋂ENDS = {}

    Inclusion monotony prevents
    an empty set of common finite cardinals
    without an empty endsegment.

    No.
    For a collection ENDS holding infinitely.many end.segments,
    ENDS′ = ENDS\{{}} is
    ⎛ a collection without an empty end.segment
    ⎜ holding infinitely.many end.segments,
    ⎜ having an empty intersection.
    ⎝ ⋂ENDS′ = {}

    Yes, they are identical. And identically empty.

    You said that the endsegments are never empty.

    I intended to say that those intersections are empty.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Sun Dec 1 11:02:45 2024
    On 01.12.2024 00:34, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/30/2024 4:56 PM, WM wrote:

    Inclusion monotony prevents
    an empty set of common finite cardinals without an empty endsegment.

    No

    It does.
    E(1), E(2), E(3), ...
    and
    E(1), E(1)∩E(2), E(1)∩E(2)∩E(3), ...
    are identical for every n and in the limit because
    E(1)∩E(2)∩...∩E(n) = E(n).

    inclusion.monotony does not prevent
    an empty set of common finite.ordinals
    without an empty end segment.

    Stupid or impudent. No reason to continue.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Richard Damon@21:1/5 to All on Sun Dec 1 07:12:25 2024
    On 12/1/24 5:02 AM, WM wrote:
    On 01.12.2024 00:34, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/30/2024 4:56 PM, WM wrote:

    Inclusion monotony prevents
    an empty set of common finite cardinals without an empty endsegment.

    No

    It does.
    E(1), E(2), E(3), ...
    and
    E(1), E(1)∩E(2), E(1)∩E(2)∩E(3), ...
    are identical for every n and in the limit because
    E(1)∩E(2)∩...∩E(n) = E(n).

    inclusion.monotony does not prevent
    an empty set of common finite.ordinals
    without an empty end segment.

    Stupid or impudent. No reason to continue.

    Thanks for your confession, YOU are Stupid and impudent.

    No reason to continue thinking you have anything to say.


    Regards, WM


    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Sun Dec 1 15:02:16 2024
    On 12/1/2024 5:02 AM, WM wrote:
    On 01.12.2024 00:34, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/30/2024 4:56 PM, WM wrote:

    Inclusion monotony prevents
    an empty set of common finite cardinals
    without an empty endsegment.

    No

    It does.
    E(1), E(2), E(3), ...
    and
    E(1), E(1)∩E(2), E(1)∩E(2)∩E(3), ...
    are identical for every n and in the limit
    because
    E(1)∩E(2)∩...∩E(n) = E(n).

    Identical sequences without an empty end.segment.
    Identical empty set of common finite.cardinals.

    Inclusion monotony does not prevent
    an empty set of common finite.cardinals
    without an empty end.segment.


    ENDS is the set of end.segments of finite.cardinals.

    ENDS⁺ = ENDS\{{}} is
    the set of end.segments of finite.cardinals
    without the empty end.segment
    Even if {} is in ENDS, {} isn't in ENDS⁺

    ⋂ENDS⁺ = {}


    For each finite.cardinal k
    |ENDS⁺| > k

    For each finite.cardinal k
    ⎛ |{fore.segments k is not.in}| < |ENDS⁺|
    ⎜ |{end.segments k is in}| < |ENDS⁺|
    ⎜ |{in ENDS⁺, end.segments k is in}| < |ENDS⁺|
    ⎜ k is not in common with each end segment in ENDS⁺
    ⎝ k is not in ⋂ENDS⁺

    Each finite.cardinal k is not.in ⋂ENDS⁺

    ⋂ENDS⁺ = {}

    inclusion.monotony does not prevent
    an empty set of common finite.ordinals
    without an empty end segment.

    Stupid or impudent. No reason to continue.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to Jim Burns on Sun Dec 1 21:33:48 2024
    On 01.12.2024 21:02, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 12/1/2024 5:02 AM, WM wrote:

    E(1), E(2), E(3), ...
    and
    E(1), E(1)∩E(2), E(1)∩E(2)∩E(3), ...
    are identical for every n and in the limit
    because
    E(1)∩E(2)∩...∩E(n) = E(n).

    Identical sequences without an empty end.segment.
    Identical empty set of common finite.cardinals.

    Inclusion monotony does not prevent
    an empty set of common finite.cardinals
     without an empty end.segment.

    Stupid or impudent. No reason to continue.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Jim Burns@21:1/5 to All on Sun Dec 1 17:46:14 2024
    On 12/1/2024 3:33 PM, WM wrote:
    On 01.12.2024 21:02, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 12/1/2024 5:02 AM, WM wrote:

    E(1), E(2), E(3), ...
    and
    E(1), E(1)∩E(2), E(1)∩E(2)∩E(3), ...
    are identical for every n and in the limit
    because
    E(1)∩E(2)∩...∩E(n) = E(n).

    Identical sequences without an empty end.segment.
    Identical empty set of common finite.cardinals.

    Inclusion monotony does not prevent
    an empty set of common finite.cardinals
      without an empty end.segment.

    ENDS⁺ is the set of
    non.empty end.segments of finite.cardinals.
    ⎛ ℕ,E(1),E(2),... ∈ ENDS⁺
    ⎝ {} ∉ ENDS⁺

    For each end.segment E(k) ∈ ENDS⁺
    for each finite.cardinal j
    |E(k)| > j

    For each finite.cardinal j
    |ENDS⁺| > j

    For each finite.cardinal j
    ⎛ j is only in each of ⟨ℕ,E(1),...,E(j)⟩ ⊆ ENDS⁺
    ⎜ |⟨ℕ,E(1),...,E(j)⟩| < |ENDS⁺|
    ⎜ j is not.in.common.with each E(k) ∈ ENDS⁺
    ⎝ j ∉ ⋂ENDS⁺

    For each finite.cardinal j
    j ∉ ⋂ENDS⁺

    ⋂ENDS⁺ = {}

    Stupid or impudent. No reason to continue.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Mon Dec 2 06:49:19 2024
    Am 02.12.2024 um 00:19 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:

    Infinite[ly many] finite sets: <<< [!]

    { { 1 }, { 1, 2 }, { 1, 2, 3 }, { 1, 2, 3, 4 }, ... }

    ?

    In fact, in axiomatic set theory (due to von Neumann):

    IN = {{}, {0}, {0, 1}, {0, 1, 2}, ...}

    where 0 = {}, 1 = {0}, 2 = {0, 1}, ... etc. In general: n+1 = {0, ..., n}.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From joes@21:1/5 to All on Mon Dec 2 19:15:47 2024
    Am Sat, 30 Nov 2024 22:56:00 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 30.11.2024 22:45, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/30/2024 2:07 PM, WM wrote:

    But there is a sequence of endsegments E(1), E(2), E(3), ...
    With an empty set of common finite cardinals.
    Inclusion monotony prevents an empty set of common finite cardinals
    without an empty endsegment.
    Wrong.
    In non-empty endsegments there are common finite cardinals.
    Only for finite intersections.

    and a sequence of their intersections E(1), E(1)∩E(2), E(1)∩E(2)∩E(3),
    Both are identical -
    from the first endsegment on until every existing endsegment.
    Yes, they are identical. And identically empty.
    You said that the endsegments are never empty.
    The limit is empty.

    Each infinite collection of end segments of
    finite cardinals has an empty intersection.
    Because an infinite collection of endsegments requires infinitely many indices, that is all indices. As long as some contents n, n+1, n+2, ...
    is in endsegments, the indices reach only from 1 to n-1.
    And as long as you only consider a finite number of segments, you don't
    have infinitely many of them.

    --
    Am Sat, 20 Jul 2024 12:35:31 +0000 schrieb WM in sci.math:
    It is not guaranteed that n+1 exists for every n.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Tue Dec 3 00:35:04 2024
    Am 02.12.2024 um 06:49 schrieb Moebius:
    Am 02.12.2024 um 00:19 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:

    Infinite[ly many] finite sets:   <<<  [!]

    { { 1 }, { 1, 2 }, { 1, 2, 3 }, { 1, 2, 3, 4 }, ... }

    ?

    In fact, in axiomatic set theory (due to von Neumann):

        IN = {{}, {0}, {0, 1}, {0, 1, 2}, ...}

    where 0 = {}, 1 = {0}, 2 = {0, 1}, ... etc. In general: n+1 = {0, ..., n}.

    Then IN is the set of all natural numbers AND the set of all FISONs _at
    the same time_. :-)

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to joes on Tue Dec 3 13:54:07 2024
    On 02.12.2024 20:15, joes wrote:
    Am Sat, 30 Nov 2024 22:56:00 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 30.11.2024 22:45, Jim Burns wrote:
    On 11/30/2024 2:07 PM, WM wrote:

    But there is a sequence of endsegments E(1), E(2), E(3), ...
    With an empty set of common finite cardinals.
    Inclusion monotony prevents an empty set of common finite cardinals
    without an empty endsegment.
    Wrong.

    Simply true.

    In non-empty endsegments there are common finite cardinals.
    Only for finite intersections.

    and a sequence of their intersections E(1), E(1)∩E(2), E(1)∩E(2)∩E(3),
    Both are identical -
    from the first endsegment on until every existing endsegment.
    Yes, they are identical. And identically empty.
    You said that the endsegments are never empty.
    The limit is empty.

    True.

    Each infinite collection of end segments of
    finite cardinals has an empty intersection.
    Because an infinite collection of endsegments requires infinitely many
    indices, that is all indices. As long as some contents n, n+1, n+2, ...
    is in endsegments, the indices reach only from 1 to n-1.
    And as long as you only consider a finite number of segments,

    i.e., as long as their contents is infinite,

    you don't
    have infinitely many of them.

    So it is.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From joes@21:1/5 to All on Sun Dec 15 20:35:48 2024
    Am Sun, 15 Dec 2024 12:12:13 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 15.12.2024 11:51, Mikko wrote:
    On 2024-12-14 21:40:48 +0000, WM said:

    In a geometry where all points exist, all points can be passed.
    Yes but none of them can be passed before passing other points.
    That contradicts the actual existence of all.
    On the contrary. The density of the points prevents passing them.

    When other points are passed, the former has been passed before.
    Otherwise it would not be the former.
    When. This goes for all points, so none can actually be passed.

    --
    Am Sat, 20 Jul 2024 12:35:31 +0000 schrieb WM in sci.math:
    It is not guaranteed that n+1 exists for every n.

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From WM@21:1/5 to joes on Mon Dec 16 09:48:09 2024
    On 15.12.2024 21:35, joes wrote:
    Am Sun, 15 Dec 2024 12:12:13 +0100 schrieb WM:
    On 15.12.2024 11:51, Mikko wrote:
    On 2024-12-14 21:40:48 +0000, WM said:

    In a geometry where all points exist, all points can be passed.
    Yes but none of them can be passed before passing other points.
    That contradicts the actual existence of all.
    On the contrary. The density of the points prevents passing them.

    The ratio of sizes of intervals and distances of intervals is in the
    average infinite. But all intervals have finite lengths. That means that
    in fact infinite relative distances must exist. This contradicts the
    density of intervals at least at some locations. Take a point in such a location as start point for the cursor. Then is hits a first interval.
    Crash.

    Regards, WM

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Thu Dec 26 23:49:48 2024
    Am 26.12.2024 um 05:52 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:
    On 11/9/2024 3:49 AM, WM wrote:

    idiotic nonsense.

    Huh? Keep in mind that

    Huh?! "Mind"?! Is that a joke?

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)
  • From Moebius@21:1/5 to All on Fri Dec 27 05:19:40 2024
    Am 27.12.2024 um 05:07 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:
    On 12/26/2024 2:49 PM, Moebius wrote:
    Am 26.12.2024 um 05:52 schrieb Chris M. Thomasson:
    On 11/9/2024 3:49 AM, WM wrote:

    idiotic nonsense.

    Huh? Keep in mind that

    Huh?! "Mind"?! Is that a joke?

    WM has to have some kind of mind, right? ;^)

    Well, if you say so. :-P

    Some sort of ... I guess.

    .
    .
    .

    --- SoupGate-Win32 v1.05
    * Origin: fsxNet Usenet Gateway (21:1/5)